Aristotle's Ethical Theory & Modern Health Care

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aristotle's Ethical Theory & Modern Health Care Bull.lnd. Inst. Hist, Med. Vol. XXVI pp. 75 to 80 ARISTOTLE'S ETHICAL THEORY & MODERN HEALTH CARE SISIR K. MAJUMDAR* ABSTRACT The Greek physician of antiquity - Hippocrates (460 - 356 B.C.) is called the Father of Modern Medicine and the Hippocratic Oath to which doctors of modern medicine traditionally and formally express their allegiance. forms the basic founda- tion of medical ethics. The tradition of Western ethical philosophy began with the ancient Greeks. Form Socrates (469-399 B.C.) and his immediate successors, Plato (427-347 B.C ) and Aristotle (384-322 B.C.), there is a clear line of continuity, through Hellenistic period (from the death of Alexander the Great (323 B.C.) to the end of Ptolemic dynasty (30 B.C.) and the Roman annexation of Egypt - broadly post- Aristotelian) and medieval thought to the present day. But the society has qualita- tively and quantitatively changed since the Industrial Revolution in the late 18th and 19th centuries. Society, today, is just a collection of discrete individuals, each with his or her own purposes and interests. Hence it has become almost imperative to apply the principle of autonomy to issues in the ethics of health care. The aim of this short essay is, therefore, an attempt to explore the relevance, if any, of Aristotelian ethical theory to the modern health care. Aristotle's ethical theory, in the main, 1978). This socio-political scenario in represents the prevailing opinions of edu- Greece of the day reflects the limitations cated and experienced men of his day in of Aristotle's ethics and its relevance to Athens and other city-states of Greece. the modern society of today. Ethics is derived from the Greek word Aristotle's concept of justice in "Ethos" meaning custom and, in antiquity, his most famous ethical treat se "NICOMACHEAN ETHICS" is still widely it was a systematic account of the prin- prevalent (Russell, 1946). He thought that ciples by which decent, well-behaved citi- each thing or person had its or his proper zens would regulate their conduct. Even sphere, to overstep which is unjust. Some in those days, society was not homoge- men, in virtue of their character and apti- neous. In the City-state of democratic Ath- tudes, have a wider sphere than others, ens, the citizens with voting rights num- and there is no injustice if they enjoy a bered about 50,000 and the slaves have greater share of happiness (eudaimonia). been calculated at about 100,000 (Tofallis This view is taken for granted in Aristotle. • "Hasiniketan", 200, Summernouse Drive, Wilmington Dartford, Kent DA2 7PB, England, U.K. 76 Aristotle's Ethical Theory - Majumdar In a society, as it is today in most parts of state to achieve its purpose. Aristotle's the world, particularly in this country, this celebrated description of man - a "politikon concept of justice has definite relevance zoon" - an animal that naturally lives in a to the distribution or 'availability of re- state - "Polis". Medical or health care sources in the health market. Ability to system as one of the essential institutions pay is the determining factor, discrete in- of the state should also assist that state dividualism rules over everything else in to achieve its purpose, in this case, the modern health care. "happiness" or eudaimonia for the individual Autonomy and the principle of re- citizen. "Eudaimonia" or "happiness" is spect for autonomy is important in con- "a virtuous activity of the soul". temporary medical ethics. Autonomy On "Virtue"(arete}, Aristotle classi- (meaning "self rule") is the capacity to think fied human character into five types, rang- (autonomy of thought), decide (autonomy ing from the great souled man to the moral of will) and act (autonomy of action) on the monster. Medicine has a moral tradition basis of such thought and decision, freely dating back to Hippocrates and Galen (131- and independently and without any. hin- 200 A.D.). Good health of the society de- drance. Autonomy is, therefore, a sub- pends on the good health of the individual class of freedom or liberty, but not all free- member of the society. Aristotle's con- dom or liberty is autonomy. According to cept on virtues could be the guiding phi- Aristotle, the concept of autonomy may losophy of modern health care manage- be termed as man's specific rationality. ment. Thus, the role of doctors is to provide good Modern health care systems are dif- expert advice concerning various available ferent in different countries. In most coun- options and then to support the patient's tries, health care is a purchasable, private or his/ her legal guardian's (when the commodity, depending on the individual's patient is incapable of exercising his or her ability to pay. Private medicine, as in the autonomy). Coercion or malicious way of U.S.A. is the classic example of this influencing in such matters by doctors is laissez faire medicine. In Great Britain, not acceptable. This is the usual norm in the National Health Service (N.H.S.) es- current medical practice in this country. tablished in 1948 is undergoing tremen- Aristotle's "teleology" (Greek-telos, dous changes and is slowly and steadily 'end', 'purpose') flavours all his work, includ- proceeding towards privatisation. When ing his ethical theory. The "end" of man is Britain is departing from the socialist health to live "well" or "happily" (Eudaimonia); the system, the U.S.A. is rushing fast today state arises naturally as assistinq and to some sort of socialist health system. working towards that end; and the various The Marxist doctrine - "from each accord- institutions of the state should be judged ing to his ability to each according to his by the standard of how far they assist the needs" is still lurking in the psyche of those Bull. Ind. Inst. Hist, Med. Vol. XXVI 77 who formulate health care systems in dif- to their financial ability to pay, but not ac- ferent countries. This is what is likely to cording to social status. It is money and happen in the U.S.A. in the near future money alone which holds the key in se- under the proposed health care system. lection. It fits well into libertarian and utili- In Great Britain, market economy is tarian theories of justice so long as it is guiding every system - health, medical, approved by the individual's purse education, etc. Patients, rather clients Justice is one of the central concer- (from the Greek word "Klin" meaning 'bed) ns of philosophers and Aristotle's formal are consumers in the health market. Trust principle of justice is still widely accepted. hospitals are providers. Ability to pay for The formal principle of justice or equality the care is the criteria. Individual choice attributed to Aristotle is that equals should in the selection of doctor or health care or be treated equally and unequals unequally hospital gets priority. The care needs to in proportion to the relevant inequalities be cost-effective. The carers - hospital (Aristotle, Politics, Book3,Chapter 9, managers, fund-holding general practitio- P.193, Penguin Books, London, 1988). But ners (G.P.'s) are shopping around in the this Aristotelian principle of justice with market place - the corridors of private and demands for equal consideration, fairness Trust hospitals. It is just? Just or unjust, and impartiality is interpreted by different market forces will regulate accessability authorities in different ways to justify their to hightech modern medicine on the basis own thinking on the matter. of people's ability to pay. All these fit well With enormous scientific advance- into Aristotle's concept of distributivejus- ment in the 20th century, medical treat- tice. ment has become expensive. Costs pro- Aristotle's concept of doctors is as hibit the supply of hightech medicine uni- foliows (Temkin, 1953) and is still preva- versally. Resources are scarce. There is lent in the world of health and medical care disparity between supply and demand. in many parts of the world: Morality dominates the allocation of rare 1.0rdinary Practitioners (Demiourgos) resources, Inequality in health care is the 2.Master of the Craft (Architektonikos) result in the end. Private medicine flour- 3.Man who studied medicine as part of ishes for the rich few and shies away from general education. the maximum number of people and thus The third category of doctors fits into unequals are treated unequally. On top of the making process of modern doctors. everything else, market economy or forces Others are self-styled or self-trained or rule the world of modern health care. In quack doctors/village healers, still preva- this respect, privatisation of health services lent in many parts ofthe developing world. seems to be consistent with Aristotle's Doctors of today, in private practice, may ethical theory on distributive justice. But select their patients or clients according it is in conflict with the prevalent situation 78 Aristotle's Ethical Theory - Majumdar in modern health care in Briltain and also versial issue. in some West European countries where In modern times, the physician has the cradle-to-grave welfare state is consid- become the confidant of the healthy and ered as a mark of a civilized society. Re- the sick, the expert of social agencies, the cession and again population threaten to counsellor of the judge, the authority to make it all unaffordable. It is a moral di- whom even the planners of foreign and lemma for the society and the state. In this domestic policies look up. To the Greek sphere, 'Aristotle's concept of distributive philosophers like Plato and Aristotle, the justice is under considerable strain.
Recommended publications
  • 7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul
    7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul Roger Crisp n the recent revival of interest in Aristotelian ethics, relatively little attention has been paid to the virtue of greatness of soul (megalopsuchia). This is partly Ibecause of the focus on the more structurally central concepts of Aristotle’s theory, in particular happiness (eudaimonia) and virtue (aret¯e). But in fact a study of greatness of soul can reveal important insights into the overall shape of Aristotelian ethics, including the place of external goods and luck in the virtuous life, and the significance of “the noble” (to kalon). Further, Aristotle describes the great-souled person in more detail than any other, and calls greatness of soul a “sort of crown of the virtues” (NE IV.3.1124a1–2). Many have found aspects of the portrait of the great-souled person in the Nicomachean Ethics repellent or absurd, but that is no good reason for the student of Aristotle to shy away from it. In this chapter, I shall elucidate Aristotle’s account of greatness of soul, addressing some puzzles internal to that account and bringing out its place in, and implications for, the ethics of Aristotle and of those modern writers influenced by him. Greatness of Soul as a Virtue To understand greatness of soul as an Aristotelian virtue requires first understand- ing Aristotle’s conception of virtue itself. Aristotle distinguishes virtues into two classes – intellectual virtues and virtues of character – corresponding to distinct aspects of the human soul (NE I.13). Greatness of soul is a virtue of character, though, like all such virtues, it requires its possessor to have the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom (phron¯esis; NE VI.13).
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Phronãªsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, And
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship Political Science 2013 Aristotelian Phronêsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice Stephen Salkever Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs Part of the Political Science Commons Citation Salkever, Stephen, "Aristotelian Phronêsis, the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice" (2013). Political Science Faculty Research and Scholarship. Paper 25. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/25 This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/polisci_pubs/25 For more information, please contact [email protected]. DRAFT—NOT FOR QUOTATION OR CITATION. Aristotelian Phronêsis , the Discourse of Human Rights, and Contemporary Global Practice Stephen Salkever Bryn Mawr College August, 2013 (A version of this paper was presented at a conference on Practical Wisdom and Globalizing Practice held in November 2012 at Sun Yat-sen University, Guangzhou, China. For questions and comments I thank my fellow conferees and especially the conference organizer, Prof. Xu Changfu of the SYSU Philosophy Department.) In this paper, I will outline some fundamental differences between the evaluative and explanatory language of Aristotelian practical reason based on his empirical psychological
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Challenges to Contemporary Philosophy—Nature, Knowledge, and the Good
    Introduction: Aristotelian Challenges to Contemporary Philosophy—Nature, Knowledge, and the Good The collection of articles presented in this book explores Aristotelianism and its critics from three distinct viewpoints in three historical periods: first, from the point of view of the philosophy of science and epistemology in Antiquity, secondly, from the perspective of the notion of individual rights in medieval philosophy; and, finally, against the background of 20th-century ethical discus- sions that offer alternatives to what can be taken as standard modern ethical theories (such as those developed by Sidgwick, for example). The main moti- vation of the selection is the general observation that, with respect to these specific themes, the influence and critical impact of Aristotelianism have not yet been sufficiently studied. When it comes to assessing central questions of the philosophy of science and epistemology and their relation to Aristotelianism, we argue that there is a danger of making simplified generalisations and attacking Aristotle as a straw man representing tendencies that derive from inaccurate or modernis- ing interpretations. The contributions in Part i focus on clearing up some such modernising misunderstandings pertaining to Aristotle’s theory of science. Secondly, with respect to the history and development of modern ethics with its notion of individual rights, Part ii of the collection addresses the question whether, in the late Middle Ages, there was a radical change in the analysis of rights. The contributors offer contrasting views on this, arguing first that ancient authors lacked neither terms nor concepts for individual rights. Others oppose this suggestion by claiming that the profundity of late medi- eval conceptual change entails that any resembling notions that one might find in antiquity can only be superficially similar to the modern ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Root of Moderation Discourse in Iran's Eleventh Presidential Election
    ISSN 2039-2117 (online) Mediterranean Journal of Vol 9 No 1 ISSN 2039-9340 (print) Social Sciences January 2018 Research Article © 2018 Jafari et.al.. This is an open access article licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). Philosophical Root of Moderation Discourse in Iran’s Eleventh Presidential Election Leila Jafari PHD Student, Faculty of Administrative Sciences and Economics, Department of Political Science, University of Isfahan Ali Alihosseini Associate Professor, Faculty of Administrative Sciences and Economics, Department of Political Science, University of Isfahan Corresponding Author Seyyedjavad Emamjomehzadeh Associate Professor, Faculty of Administrative Sciences and Economics, Department of Political Science, University of Isfahan Doi: 10.2478/mjss-2018-0014 Abstract Moderation was a triumphant discourse of Iran's eleventh presidential election. It’s a new attitude in the political realm and most of the movements relate themselves to it and each one interprete their actions according to moderation. For clarifying this ambiguous trend, we should refer to its philosophical root. It seems that Aristotle is the first one who represented this theory. In fact, moderation is one of the main principles of Aristotelian ethics. Understanding this concept requires understanding the basic concepts of the intellectual and moral theory of Aristotle. Moderation is the center of his theory of virtue. According to this principle, all the moral virtues are intermediates and excess, and defects in the actions and emotions cause moral vices. This theory could be the best way to pass excess and deficiencies in Iran's political sphere. Keywords: Aristotle's ethics, moderation, virtue, excess, deficiency 1.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS in BYZANTIUM* York: George Braziller
    Linos G. BENAKIS Vahanian, G. (1965b, December 8). Swallowed Vahanian, G. (1966b). Theology and ‘The End UDC 1/14:17 up by Godlessness. The ChristianCen- of the Age of Religion’. (J. B. Metz, Linos G. BENAKIS tury, LXXXII(49), 1505-1507. Ed.) Concilium: Theology in the Age Vahanian, G. (1966a). No other God. New of Renewal, XVI, 99-110. ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS IN BYZANTIUM* York: George Braziller. Abstract This paper argues that research in the primary sources must precede the investigation of Byzan- tine philosophy. Two points are to be considered, on the one hand, the gathering of texts, and, on the other hand, the study of texts in relation to their sources. Thus the external evidence as well as the internal evidence of texts should be examined. In this double regard, the manuscripts containing Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics are considered. Their authors are Michael of Ephesos, Eustratios of Nicaea, “Anonymus”, Heliodoros of Prussa, Georgios Pachymeres, Michael Psellos, John Italos, Nikephoros Blemmydes, George Gemistos Plethon. Keywords: Byzantine philosophy, Aristotle’s Byzantine Commentators, Michael of Ephesos, Eustratios of Nicaea, “Anonymus”, Heliodoros of Prussa, Georgios Pachymeres, Michael Psellos, John Italos, Nikephoros Blemmydes, George Gemistos Plethon. This paper is primarily technical in nature. b. The study of texts in relation to their It will argue that when one begins to examine a sources. Namely, the identification of less investigated area of the field of Byzantine sources – distinguishing between instan- Philosophy, research in the primary sources ces of mere borrowing and instances of a must still precede every interpretative act and more critical incorporation of such sour- critical approach.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemplating Friendship in Aristotle's Ethics
    Chapter One Contemplating Friendship in Aristotle’s Ethics Aristotle begins the Nicomachean Ethics by embracing the claim that all human activity aims at the good. Living from 384–322 BC, and having been a student in Plato’s Academy for nearly twenty years before founding his own philosophical school in Athens, the Lyceum, in 335 BC, Aristotle identifies the highest human good as happiness eudaimonia( ). Aristotle defines happiness as an activity of soul in accord with the reason of a serious person, and thus as an activity of soul in accord with virtue. Such a definition is problematic, however, because virtue is divided by Aristotle into two different types: moral virtue and intellectual virtue. Which of these virtues for Aristotle constitutes happiness is one of the most contested debates in the contemporary literature on the Nicomachean Ethics. On one side of this debate are ranged scholars such as J. L. Ackrill and David Bostock who hold that Aristotle has an “inclusive” view of happiness.1 This means that the happy life requires the practice, in some form, of both the moral and the intellectual virtues. Scholars on the other side of the debate, such as C. D. C. Reeve and Thomas Nagel, believe that Aristotle has an “exclusive” or “dominant” view of happiness.2 This view holds that happiness is grounded in the intellectual virtue of contemplation, which is separable from and superior to moral virtue. I argue that Aristotle’s text comprehends both the “inclusive” and “exclusive” views of happiness attributed to it. In acts of moral virtue, Aristotle argues, reason determines the mean and guides the passions to it, which is then usually followed by an external action of the body.
    [Show full text]
  • A COMPARISON of ARISTOTELIAN and BUDDHIST ETHICS and the IMPLICATIONS for a “MORAL WAY” for YOUNG PEOPLE ANNE MULDOON Submit
    A COMPARISON OF ARISTOTELIAN AND BUDDHIST ETHICS AND THE IMPLICATIONS FOR A “MORAL WAY” FOR YOUNG PEOPLE ANNE MULDOON Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Philosophy University of Glasgow Departments of Computing Science and Religious Education February 2008 ABSTRACT The impetus for this piece of work was the question ‘What type of people ought we to become?’, which first arose with Aristotle and which became, in Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue, ‘Who are we now becoming? '. Through a comparative study of the key concepts of Aristotelian ethics, for example, eudaimonia , the centrality of reason, the Doctrine of the Mean, and the key concepts of Buddhist ethics, for example, karma and nirvana, the interdependence of morality, meditation and insight, the central role of mindfulness and compassion, I will present the guidelines for a "moral way" for young people. An analysis of the differences between the two ethical systems draws out their different emphases on reason and compassion, and the separateness of self and other in Aristotelian moral agency in contrast to the inseparability of all sentient beings in Buddhism. But an examination of their similarities reveals how reason and emotion contribute to each, and how both are teleological in assuming that a person has a final end. The interplay of Aristotelian habituation and Buddhist mindfulness is identified as a potentially transformative “moral way” for young people, and suggestions are made for how to facilitate the two practices as a pedagogical support. The main recommendation is that, subject to further research and successful pilot-studies, habituation and mindfulness practices be introduced in Primary Two and maintained into secondary education in Scottish schools.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Harmony with Plato on Separable and Immortal Soul1
    Aristotle’s Harmony with Plato on Separable and Immortal Soul1 W. M. Coombs Department of Philosophy, University of Pretoria, South Africa [email protected] Abstract The possibility of a harmony between the psychological doctrine of Aristotle and that of Plato marks a significant issue within the context of the debate surrounding Aristotle‘s putative opposition to or harmony with Plato‘s philosophy. The standard interpretation of Aristotle‘s conception of the soul being purely hylomorphic leaves no room for harmonisation with Plato, nor does a functionalist interpretation that reduces Aristotle‘s psychological doctrine to physicalist terms. However, these interpretations have serious drawbacks, both in terms of ad-hoc explanations formulated in the developmentalist mode, and the misconstruing of some of the fundamental features of Aristotle‘s psychological doctrine. A dualist interpretation that accepts Aristotle‘s doctrine of some part of the soul being properly incorporeal, separable and immortal overcomes these drawbacks and, significantly, opens the door for Platonic harmonisation. Furthermore, it can be shown that the kind of immortality in question is also in line with the Platonic stance, due to a deep similarity between the conceptions of metaphysical and moral personhood held by Plato and his student. However, this Aristotelian dualism is not Platonic dualism simpliciter. Rather, it is best understood in terms of the division of labour between Aristotle and Plato suggested by the Neoplatonic commentators generally, and Simplicius in particular. I argue that though questions surrounding these issues and particularly the issue of reincarnation remain, an account of Aristotle‘s psychological doctrine as dualist and in harmony with Plato‘s view of the soul can be shown to be stronger than both standard hylomorphic and functionalist accounts, both exegetically and philosophically.
    [Show full text]
  • Nature and Moral Excellence in the Aristotelian Ethics
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1976 Nature and Moral Excellence in the Aristotelian Ethics Robert Geis Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Geis, Robert, "Nature and Moral Excellence in the Aristotelian Ethics" (1976). Master's Theses. 2840. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/2840 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1976 Robert Geis NATURE AND MORAL EXCELLENCE IN THE ARISTOTELIAN ETHICS by Robert Geis A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of master of Arts February 1976 PREFACE The past three decades have seen an appreciable growth of interest in ethics both here and in Europe, with discus­ sion equally fruitful in both the classical and modern po­ sitions. The topics discussed, varied and wide-ranging as the.problems they consider, continue to provide appreciat­ ion for the complexities that ethics must treat, whether the views set forth have been one's own or that of a major fig- ure. This thesis is of the latter kind. It centers direct­ ly on one theme in Aristotle's ethics, viz., the relation there of Nature and moral excellence.
    [Show full text]
  • Ibn Sīnā's Practical Philosophy
    Religious Inquiries Vol. 2, No. 3, Winter and Spring 2013, 5-27. Ibn Sīnā’s Practical Philosophy Hajj Mohammad Legenhausen1 This article is a brief review of Ibn Sīnā‘s practical philosophy. It begins with a discussion of the Platonic, Aristotelian, and Neo-Platonic influences on Ibn Sīnā‘s practical philosophy, as well as the influence of Fārābī and of Islamic religious teachings. The creative synthesis invented by Ibn Sīnā requires a particular view of the relation between religion and philosophy in such a manner that religion shapes the direction of philosophical inquiry, and philosophy opens the way to a more profound and esoteric understanding of religion. Keywords: Aristotle, Avicenna, Ibn Sīnā, Fārābī, ethics, neo-Platonism, Plato, practical wisdom, prophet, revelation, virtue. What is Practical Philosophy? Aristotle defines practical wisdom (φρόνησις, phronesis) as a kind of excellence or virtue: The distinction between virtues also reflects this difference. For some virtues are called virtues of thought, other virtues of character; wisdom, comprehension and intelligence (phronesis) are called virtues of thought, generosity and temperance, virtues of character. (Aristotle 1985, 1103a 4-6) So, if we begin with excellences or virtues, we may divide them into intellectual and moral virtues. Among the intellectual virtues will be found both theoretical and practical wisdom, that is, sophia and phronesis. In Arabic, these are called al- ikmat al-na ariyya and al- ikmat al-ʽamaliyya. The manner in which Ibn Sīnā uses these terms shows that he was following Aristotle‘s usage in the Nicomachean Ethics.2 1. Professor, Imam Khomeini Educational and Research Institute, Iran ([email protected]) 2.
    [Show full text]
  • ACADEMIA Letters Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics and Protestantism
    ACADEMIA Letters Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics and Protestantism David S. Sytsma The past generation has witnessed a remarkable revival of virtue ethics, and with it a renewed interest in Aristotle’s classic text on the subject—Nicomachean Ethics. Despite this renewed interest, many scholars, including Protestant ethicists, are unaware of the importance of Aris- totle’s Nicomachean Ethics for Protestantism historically. Indeed, we read of Protestants’ “re- jection of virtue ethics” (Gregory 2012: 269), or that following the Reformation, Protestants “grew increasingly wary of exhortations to practice the virtues” (DeYoung 2020: 28). One Protestant scholar believes that the adoption of something akin to “the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition of virtue ethics” would require “that we abandon our tradition” (Haas 2002: 91). We also find Protestants who argue for a concept of virtue but “do so from Scripture withoutref- erence to their own heritage” (Rehnman 2012: 490). As a historical fact, however, Protestants produced an astonishingly rich corpus of ethical texts based on Nicomachean Ethics, and new historical narratives are beginning to correct the record (Vos 2020: 85-108; Svensson 2019). This essay, therefore, will introduce readers to the origin and development of Protestant ethi- cal works in the tradition of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. At the outset of the Reformation, Martin Luther famously attacked Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics as the “worst enemy of grace” (Luther 1957: 12; Kusukawa 1995: 33). Already in 1518 he wanted the Nicomachean Ethics removed from Wittenberg’s curriculum, and in 1520 he wrote in Address to the Christian Nobility of Germany that Aristotle’s ethics “should be com- pletely discarded along with all the rest of his books that boast about nature” (Luther 1966b: 200; Kusukawa 1995: 39, 42).
    [Show full text]
  • The Morally Difficult Notion of Heaven: a Critique of the Faith-Based Ethics of Avicenna and Aquinas
    © 2018, American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly doi: Online First: The Morally Difficult Notion of Heaven: A Critique of the Faith-Based Ethics of Avicenna and Aquinas Amir Saemi Abstract. I will argue that Avicenna’s and Aquinas’s faith-based virtue ethics are crucially different from Aristotle’s virtue ethics, in that their ethics hinges on the theological notion of heaven, which is constitutively independent of the ethical life of the agent. As a result, their faith-based virtue ethics is objectionable. Moreover, I will also argue that the notion of heaven that Avicenna and Aquinas deploy in their moral philosophy is problematic; for it can rationally permit believers to commit morally horrendous actions. Finally, I will present a Kantian notion of heaven which is immune to the aforementioned moral objection. The Kantian notion of heaven, nevertheless, cannot ground any view of ethics as it is constitutively dependent on the ethical life of the agent. I. Introduction merican physicist Steven Weinberg said that “with or without [religion] you would have good people doing good things and evil people doing evil things. But for good people to do evil things, that takesA religion.”1 I will argue that Weinberg’s statement can be supported by a certain conception of heaven adopted by some religions. Heaven, in a reli- gious context, depicts the highest good, or complete happiness which bestows a final point (or telos) to the acts of believers. However, there is a conception of heaven, prevalent in Christian and Islamic thought, which renders Weinberg’s claim true: i.e., it implies that it would be rational for believers to do evil things.
    [Show full text]