1 What Did Mary Know? Russellian Monism Without Intrinsics Jussi Jylkkä Note

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 What Did Mary Know? Russellian Monism Without Intrinsics Jussi Jylkkä Note What did Mary know? Russellian Monism Without Intrinsics Jussi Jylkkä Note: this is a non-peer reviewed preprint. Abstract. The Mary thought experiment aims to demonstrate that science cannot capture what experiences feel like. Russellian Monism (RM) avoids this problem by claiming that phenomenality is an intrinsic (non-relational and non-dispositional) property of matter and beyond the scope of science, which is limited to describing extrinsic (relational and dispositional) properties. Against RM, I argue that metaphysical intrinsicality is not compatible with neuroscientific theories where experiences are considered as causal processes. Second, I argue that if intrinsic properties have causal power, they can also affect neuroscientific measuring devices and be scientifically modeled. Thus, intrinsic properties are not inscrutable, as RM holds. In the third part of the article, I sketch the outlines of RM without intrinsics. I propose that the core Kantian thesis of RM about limits of science can be maintained without postulating metaphysical intrinsics. I argue that metaphysical intrinsicality can be replaced with Weak Intrinsicality, meaning model-independence. Science is confined to observations and models, whereas an experience is the concrete, model- independent process that produces observations of its neural mechanisms. On this account, the epistemic gap is difference between a model and the modeled. Keywords: Knowledge argument, Hard problem of consciousness, Russellian Monism, Kant, Transcendental idealism, Intrinsic properties, Neural correlates of consciousness, Constitutive mechanisms of consciousness 1 1. Mary and the limits of science Jackson's (1982) Knowledge Argument, also known as the Mary thought experiment, is one of the most influential arguments against physicalism, i.e., the view that experiences are physical phenomena. It aims to demonstrate that science cannot afford knowledge about certain aspects of experiences, namely what it feels like to undergo them (see also Feigl, 1958; Maxwell, 1965; Meehl, 1966; Nagel, 1979; Robinson, 1982). More generally, the argument aims to show that physicalism is false: because science doesn’t afford knowledge of what experiences feel like, that feel cannot be physical. If it were, science could describe it like it describes all other physical phenomena. Jackson (1982, p. 130) formulates the thought experiment as follows: Mary is a brilliant scientist who is, for whatever reason, forced to investigate the world from a black and white room via a black and white television monitor. She specializes in the neurophysiology of vision and acquires, let us suppose, all the physical information there is to obtain about what goes on when we see ripe tomatoes, or the sky, and use terms like ‘red’, ‘blue’, and so on. She discovers, for example, just which wavelength combinations from the sky stimulate the retina, and exactly how this produces via the central nervous system the contraction of the vocal chords and expulsion of air from the lungs that results in the uttering of the sentence ‘The sky is blue’ […] What will happen when Mary is released from her black and white room or is given a color television monitor? Will she learn anything or not? It seems just obvious that she will learn something about the world and our visual experience of it. But then is it inescapable that her previous knowledge was incomplete. But she had all the physical information. Ergo there is more to have than that, and Physicalism is false. Despite her complete scientific knowledge, Mary does not know what seeing red feels like: upon leaving the room, she learns the phenomenal or qualitative character of red experiences. There are a range of responses to the Mary argument, from purely epistemic or philosophy of language –based (e.g., the phenomenal concepts strategy; Stoljar, 2005), through naturalistic ones (e.g., the ability hypothesis; Nemirow, 1980), to heavily metaphysical ones (e.g., Russellian monism [Goff, 2017; Russell, 1927; Strawson, 2003] or property dualism [Chalmers, 1996]). Here I focus on Russellian Monism (RM), whose most central claim I take to be Kantian: science is in some sense limited. On the standard Russellian view, the limits of science are assumed to stem from what types of properties it deals with: Science can only model extrinsic (relational or causal-dispositional) properties of matter, but not their intrinsic categorical basis. Phenomenal properties, in turn, are assumed to form the intrinsic or categorical basis of causal dispositions, which, unlike the dispositions themselves, are beyond science (Alter & Nagasawa, 2012; Goff, 2017; Russell, 1927). These properties are also called quiddities (Chalmers, 1996) or inscrutables (Montero, 2015). I argue that we can accept the core Kantian claim of RM that science is limited without postulating metaphysical intrinsics. As an alternative to RM’s notion of intrinsicality, I propose Weak Intrinsicality which means model- or representation-independence: science has no access to reality beyond observations and models. On my approach, an experience is the concrete process that produces observations of its neural mechanisms. On the account I put forth, science can indeed model all aspects of experiences, including what they feel like, but only model. Thus, the epistemic gap between an experience and its scientific model doesn’t reflect an ontological difference, but rather only the difference between a model and the modeled. I will proceed as follows. The first part of the paper (§2) is negative and presents against RM’s notion of intrinsics two problems. First, I argue that the notion of intrinsics as non-relational and non- dispositional is incompatible with neuroscientific theories which consider the neural mechanisms of consciousness as relational processes. A plausible approach for the Russellian is to hold that the phenomenality that we are familiar with is the intrinsic nature of what neuroscience models as constitutive mechanisms of experiences (CMEs). However, given that the CMEs are relational processes, they cannot have intrinsic (non-relational) natures. This is closely related to the combination problem of RM (Chalmers, 2017; Goff, 2017), i.e., the problem of how the intrinsic natures of fundamental particles combine to form human experiences. My second argument against the Russellian notion of intrinsics relates to the claim that they are supposed to be scientifically inscrutable; something that science cannot describe (Montero, 2015; see also Goff, 2017; Strawson, 2006, 2019). I present a dilemma against RM: If intrinsics are causally efficacious, 2 then they can also affect the senses and measuring devices of observers. Thus, intrinsics are not inscrutable as RM would hold. Again, if intrinsics are not causally efficacious, then they can’t be scientifically observed and modeled, but neither is there mental causation, given that phenomenal properties are (a subset of) intrinsic properties. The take-home message is that one cannot integrate intrinsics or phenomenal properties in causal processes and simultaneously hold that they are in some strong sense private: it they have causal power we can observe them through their effects. These problems stem from the metaphysically strong notion of intrinsics in RM. On my view, the postulation of metaphysically distinct class of properties (intrinsic and extrinsic) is not justified at least by the Mary case alone—it is an epistemic problem that requires an epistemic explanation. In the second part of the paper (§3), I argue that the core Kantian thesis of RM can be preserved without postulating metaphysical intrinsics. Whereas traditional RM resembles metaphysical interpretations of Kant (e.g., Langton, 2001), I propose an alternative account that is similar to epistemic interpretations (e.g., Allais, 2015; Allison, 2004). I suggest that we replace RM’s metaphysically strong notion of intrinsicality with the epistemic notion of Weak Intrinsicality. Whereas RM’s metaphysical intrinsicality means a thing considered independent from all its relational properties, an object’s weakly intrinsic nature is the way it is independent of our modes of representing it. As Allais (2015) argues, we can only know objects as they manifest to us in experience, not as they are independently of being related to us. The way objects appear to us is shaped by our conscious-cognitive system, types of measuring devices, and the theories we use to conceptualize our observations. We cannot abstract ourselves away from how objects appear to us, since the appearance is determined not only by the observed object, but also ourselves. In short, we can’t represent objects as they are independent of our representing them. On the account I propose, science is limited simply because it is based on observations and models of external phenomena; science cannot say anything of objects beyond scientific representations. Again, we can know our experiences independently of models and observations. I call the nature of an object in abstraction from how it is represented by an observer its “weakly intrinsic nature”. I argue that Weak Intrinsicality can do the same explanatory work as the traditional Russellian metaphysical notion of intrinsicality but is more parsimonious and compatible with neuroscience of consciousness. On my approach, science is limited simply because it is “shaped by the lens of human consciousness” (Hawking & Mlodinow, 2010) or based on “pointer-readings” (Eddington, 1929): Any scientific
Recommended publications
  • Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (Ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016)
    Leibniz, Bayle and the Controversy on Sudden Change Markku Roinila (In: Giovanni Scarafile & Leah Gruenpeter Gold (ed.), Paradoxes of Conflicts, Springer 2016) Leibniz’s metaphysical views were not known to most of his correspondents, let alone to the larger public, until 1695 when he published an article in Journal des savants, titled in English “A New System of the Nature and Communication of Substances, and of the Union of the Soul and Body” (henceforth New System).1 The article raised quite a stir. Perhaps the most interesting and cunning critique of Leibniz’s views was provided by a French refugee in Rotterdam, Pierre Bayle (1647−1706) who is most famous for his Dictionnaire Historique et Critique (1697). The fascinating controversy on Leibniz’s idea of pre-established harmony and a number of other topics lasted for five years and ended only when Bayle died. In this paper I will give an overview of the communication, discuss in detail a central topic concerning spontaneity or a sudden change in the soul, and compare the views presented in the communication to Leibniz’s reflections in his partly concurrent New Essays on Human Understanding (1704) (henceforth NE). I will also reflect on whether the controversy could have ended in agreement if it would have continued longer. The New System Let us begin with the article that started the controversy, the New System. The article starts with Leibniz’s objection to the Cartesian doctrine of extension as a basic way of explaining motion. Instead, one should adopt a doctrine of force which belongs to the sphere of metaphysics (GP IV 478).
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:2012.10390V2 [Cs.AI] 20 Feb 2021 Inaccessible
    Opinion - Paper under review Deep Learning and the Global Workspace Theory Rufin VanRullen1, 2 and Ryota Kanai3 1CerCo, CNRS UMR5549, Toulouse, France 2ANITI, Universit´ede Toulouse, France 3Araya Inc, Tokyo. Japan Abstract Recent advances in deep learning have allowed Artificial Intelligence (AI) to reach near human-level performance in many sensory, perceptual, linguistic or cognitive tasks. There is a growing need, however, for novel, brain-inspired cognitive architectures. The Global Workspace theory refers to a large-scale system integrating and distributing infor- mation among networks of specialized modules to create higher-level forms of cognition and awareness. We argue that the time is ripe to consider explicit implementations of this theory using deep learning techniques. We propose a roadmap based on unsu- pervised neural translation between multiple latent spaces (neural networks trained for distinct tasks, on distinct sensory inputs and/or modalities) to create a unique, amodal global latent workspace (GLW). Potential functional advantages of GLW are reviewed, along with neuroscientific implications. 1 Cognitive neural architectures in brains and ma- chines Deep learning denotes a machine learning system using artificial neural networks with multiple \hidden" layers between the input and output layers. Although the underlying theory is more than 3 decades old [1, 2], it is only in the last decade that these systems have started to fully reveal their potential [3]. Many of the recent breakthroughs in AI (Artificial Intelligence) have been fueled by deep learning. Neuroscientists have been quick to point out the similarities (and differences) between the brain and these deep artificial neural networks [4{9]. The advent of deep learning has allowed the efficient computer implementation of perceptual and cognitive functions that had been so far arXiv:2012.10390v2 [cs.AI] 20 Feb 2021 inaccessible.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Body Problem and Brandom's Analytic Pragmatism
    The Mind-Body Problem and Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism François-Igor Pris [email protected] Erfurt University (Nordhäuserstraße 63, 99089 Erfurt, Germany) Abstract. I propose to solve the hard problem in the philosophy of mind by means of Brandom‟s notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. The explanatory gap between a phenomenal concept and the corresponding theoretical concept is a gap in the pragmatically mediated semantic relation between them. It is closed if we do not neglect the pragmatics. 1 Introduction In the second section, I will formulate the hard problem. In the third section, I will describe a pragmatic approach to the problem and propose to replace the classical non-normative physicalism/naturalism with a normative physicalism/naturalism of Wittgensteinian language games. In subsection 3.1, I will give a definition of a normative naturalism. In subsection 3.2, I will make some suggestions concerning an analytic interpretation of the second philosophy of Wittgenstein. In the fourth section, I will propose a solution to the hard problem within Brandom‟s analytic pragmatism by using the notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. In the fifth section, I will make some suggestions about possible combinatorics related to pragmatically mediated semantic relations. In the sixth section, I will consider pragmatic and discursive versions of the mind-body identity M=B. In the last section, I will conclude that the explanatory gap is a gap in a pragmatically mediated semantic relation between B and M. It is closed if we do not neglect pragmatics. 2 The Hard Problem The hard problem in the philosophy of mind can be formulated as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Theoretical Models of Consciousness: a Scoping Review
    brain sciences Review Theoretical Models of Consciousness: A Scoping Review Davide Sattin 1,2,*, Francesca Giulia Magnani 1, Laura Bartesaghi 1, Milena Caputo 1, Andrea Veronica Fittipaldo 3, Martina Cacciatore 1, Mario Picozzi 4 and Matilde Leonardi 1 1 Neurology, Public Health, Disability Unit—Scientific Department, Fondazione IRCCS Istituto Neurologico Carlo Besta, 20133 Milan, Italy; [email protected] (F.G.M.); [email protected] (L.B.); [email protected] (M.C.); [email protected] (M.C.); [email protected] (M.L.) 2 Experimental Medicine and Medical Humanities-PhD Program, Biotechnology and Life Sciences Department and Center for Clinical Ethics, Insubria University, 21100 Varese, Italy 3 Oncology Department, Mario Negri Institute for Pharmacological Research IRCCS, 20156 Milan, Italy; veronicaandrea.fi[email protected] 4 Center for Clinical Ethics, Biotechnology and Life Sciences Department, Insubria University, 21100 Varese, Italy; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +39-02-2394-2709 Abstract: The amount of knowledge on human consciousness has created a multitude of viewpoints and it is difficult to compare and synthesize all the recent scientific perspectives. Indeed, there are many definitions of consciousness and multiple approaches to study the neural correlates of consciousness (NCC). Therefore, the main aim of this article is to collect data on the various theories of consciousness published between 2007–2017 and to synthesize them to provide a general overview of this topic. To describe each theory, we developed a thematic grid called the dimensional model, which qualitatively and quantitatively analyzes how each article, related to one specific theory, debates/analyzes a specific issue.
    [Show full text]
  • The Knowledge Argument Against Physicalism
    Handout 8 The Knowledge Argument against Physicalism 1. Some Terminology Physicalism – all information is physical information (Another possible formulation: all facts are physical facts) Physical information - The information given by science (note: Jackson doesn’t regard this as a definition, since it’s somewhat vague) A Qualia Freak – Someone who thinks that there are features of bodily sensations and perceptual experiences that no amount of physical information includes. These features are called “qualia”: the hurtfulness of pain, the itchiniess of itches, how it feels to be jealous, taste a lemon, etc. 2. The Knowledge Argument for Qualia Fred – Fred can make all the color discriminations we make plus more. Show him a batch of ripe tomatoes and he’ll sort them into two piles which he says are as different to him in terms of color appearance as yellow is from blue. He calls these calls “red1” and “red2.” 1. We can gain all the physical information about Fred that we like and we still won’t know certain information about Fred: what kind of experience Fred has when he says red1 and red2. 2. Not all information is physical information (This can be dramatized by imagining that Fred donates his body to science and they are able to transplant his optical system into somebody else. After the operation this person will know more about Fred than was known before). Mary – Mary is a brilliant scientist who has spent her whole life in a black and white room. She is an expert on color vision and neurophysiology and knows all the physical information one could possibly know about color vision.
    [Show full text]
  • Brains and Behavior Hilary Putnam
    2 Brains and Behavior Hilary Putnam Once upon a time there was a tough- ism appeared to exhaust the alternatives. minded philosopher who said, 'What is all Compromises were attempted ('double this talk about "minds", "ideas", and "sen- aspect' theories), but they never won sations"? Really-and I mean really in the many converts and practically no one real world-there is nothing to these so- found them intelligible. Then, in the mid- called "mental" events and entities but 1930s, a seeming third possibility was dis- certain processes in our all-too-material covered. This third possibility has been heads.' called logical behaviorism. To state the And once upon a time there was a nature of this third possibility briefly, it is philosopher who retorted, 'What a master- necessary to recall the treatment of the piece of confusion! Even if, say, pain were natural numbers (i.e. zero, one, two, perfectly correlated with any particular three ... ) in modern logic. Numbers are event in my brain (which I doubt) that identified with sets, in various ways, de- event would obviously have certain prop- pending on which authority one follows. erties-say, a certain numerical intensity For instance, Whitehead and Russell iden- measured in volts-which it would be tified zero with the set of all empty sets, senseless to ascribe to the feeling of pain. one with the set of all one-membered sets, Thus, it is two things that are correlated, two with the set of all two-membered not one-and to call two things one thing sets, three with the set of all three-mem- is worse than being mistaken; it is utter bered sets, and so on.
    [Show full text]
  • Global Workspace Theory and Animal Consciousness
    19 August 2020 Global Workspace Theory and Animal Consciousness Jonathan Birch Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science, London School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton Street, London, WC2A 2AE, UK. Email: [email protected] Webpage: http://personal.lse.ac.uk/birchj1 This is a preprint of an article that will appear in Philosophical Topics. 7082 words 1 Abstract: Carruthers has recently argued for a surprising conditional: if a global workspace theory of phenomenal consciousness is both correct and fully reductive, then there are no substantive facts to discover about phenomenal consciousness in non-human animals. I present two problems for this conditional. First, it rests on an odd double-standard about the ordinary concept of phenomenal consciousness: its intuitive non-gradability is taken to be unchallengeable by future scientific developments, whereas its intuitive determinacy is predicted to fall by the wayside. Second, it relies on dismissing, prematurely, the live empirical possibility that phenomenal consciousness may be linked to a core global broadcast mechanism that is (determinately) shared by a wide range of animals. Future developments in the science of consciousness may lead us to reconsider the non-gradability of phenomenal consciousness, but they are unlikely to lead us to accept that there are no facts to discover outside the paradigm case of a healthy adult human. Key words: animal consciousness, phenomenal consciousness, consciousness science, global workspace theory, phenomenal concepts 2 1. Carruthers’ surprising conditional For more than thirty years, scepticism about attributions of phenomenal consciousness1 to (states of) non-human animals has been a major theme in Peter Carruthers’ work (Carruthers 1989, 1992, 1999, 2000, 2004, 2005, 2018a,b, 2019, 2020).
    [Show full text]
  • Russellian Panpsychism: Do We Need It and Is It Enough?
    Russellian Panpsychism: Do We Need It and Is It Enough? By Damian Aleksiev Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy Supervisor: Philip Goff CEU eTD Collection May 2016 Abstract The main aim of this thesis is to clarify the ontological status of phenomenal experience. In order to do this, I first examine how pure physicalism explains phenomenality. Pure physicalism relies on the structural and causal vocabulary of physics, and is compatible with the causal closure of the physical. Nonetheless, I argue that pure physicalism is false since it cannot account for our intuitive understating of phenomenal experience as something beyond-structural. I supplement these intuitions, first with the knowledge and conceivability arguments, and second with my own argument for the transparency of phenomenal concepts called the argument from solipsism. Then, I investigate Russellian panpsychism as a promising alternative to pure physicalism that attempts to solve its problems without any drawbacks. Russellian panpsychism places phenomenal experience at the fundamental ontological level, and at the same time remains compatible with the causal closure of the physical. Finally, I argue against Russellian panpsychism based on the combination problem, as well as my own: reverse conceivability argument, and combination problem for value. The conclusion of this enquiry is that neither pure physicalism nor Russellian panpsychism can provide a satisfactory account of phenomenal experience. CEU eTD Collection I Acknowledgments I would like to thank my supervisor Philip Goff for his continual support and willingness to discuss my ideas during the entire academic year.
    [Show full text]
  • The Phenomenology of the Self-Conscious Mind
    The Phenomenology of the Self-Conscious Mind Robert G. Mays, B.Sc. Suzanne B. Mays Chapel Hill, NC ABSTRACT: The phenomenon of a near-death experiencer's veridical perceptions during the out-of-body experience (OBE) strongly suggests the existence of a self-conscious mind as a "field of consciousness," a region of space where a person's consciousness exists. In the out-of-body state, the mind appears to be nonmaterial and completely independent of the physical body. Ordinarily, though, the self-conscious mind appears as an autonomous entity united with the brain and body. In this united state, the self-conscious mind operates through the mediation of the brain. This view is supported by evidence from neurological phenomena such as subjective antedating of sensory experiences and mental force. This evidence suggests that a nonneural agency induces conscious experience and self-conscious awareness. Phenomena from OBEs, including apparent subtle interactions with physical processes such as light, sound, and physical objects, as well as reported interactions with "in-body" persons, support the view that the self-conscious mind is able to interact in some physical way with the brain. Neurological phenomena such as Benjamin Libet's (1985) delayed awareness of willed action can be reconsidered successfully in light of this view. Such efforts might also prove useful, for example, in explaining phantom limb phenomena. KEY WORDS: near-death experience; out-of-body experience; mind-body problem; self-conscious mind; veridical perception. Robert G. Mays, B.Sc., is a retired senior software engineer and Suzanne B. Mays, A.A., is a Certified Music Practitioner (through the Music for Healing and Transition Program) who provides palliative care to hospitalized patients.
    [Show full text]
  • Is the Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness Compatible with Russellian Panpsychism?
    Is the Integrated Information Theory of Consciousness Compatible with Russellian Panpsychism? Hedda Hassel Mørch Erkenntnis (2018) Penultimate draft – please refer to published version for citation. Abstract: The Integrated Information Theory (IIT) is a leading scientific theory of consciousness, which implies a kind of panpsychism. In this paper, I consider whether IIT is compatible with a particular kind of panpsychism known as Russellian panpsychism, which purports to avoid the main problems of both physicalism and dualism. I will first show that if IIT were compatible with Russellian panpsychism, it would contribute to solving Russellian panpsychism’s combination problem, which threatens to show that the view does not avoid the main problems of physicalism and dualism after all. I then show that the theories are not compatible as they currently stand, in view of what I call the coarse-graining problem. After I explain the coarse-graining problem, I will offer two possible solutions, each involving a small modification of IIT. Given either of these modifications, IIT and Russellian panpsychism may be fully compatible after all, and jointly enable significant progress on the mind–body problem. 1 Introduction Panpsychism is the view that every physical thing is associated with consciousness. More precisely, it is the view that every physical thing is either (1) conscious as a whole, (2) made of parts which are all conscious, or (3) itself forms part of a greater conscious whole. Humans and animals (or certain areas of human and animal brains) are conscious in the first sense—our consciousness is unified, or has a single, subjective point of view.
    [Show full text]
  • The Causal Efficacy of Consciousness
    entropy Article The Causal Efficacy of Consciousness Matthew Owen 1,2 1 Yakima Valley College, Yakima, WA 98902, USA; [email protected] 2 Center for Consciousness Science, University of Michigan Medical School, Ann Arbor, MI 48109, USA Received: 10 June 2020; Accepted: 17 July 2020; Published: 28 July 2020 Abstract: Mental causation is vitally important to the integrated information theory (IIT), which says consciousness exists since it is causally efficacious. While it might not be directly apparent, metaphysical commitments have consequential entailments concerning the causal efficacy of consciousness. Commitments regarding the ontology of consciousness and the nature of causation determine which problem(s) a view of consciousness faces with respect to mental causation. Analysis of mental causation in contemporary philosophy of mind has brought several problems to the fore: the alleged lack of psychophysical laws, the causal exclusion problem, and the causal pairing problem. This article surveys the threat each problem poses to IIT based on the different metaphysical commitments IIT theorists might make. Distinctions are made between what I call reductive IIT, non-reductive IIT, and non-physicalist IIT, each of which make differing metaphysical commitments regarding the ontology of consciousness and nature of causation. Subsequently, each problem pertaining to mental causation is presented and its threat, or lack thereof, to each version of IIT is considered. While the lack of psychophysical laws appears unthreatening for all versions, reductive IIT and non-reductive IIT are seriously threatened by the exclusion problem, and it is difficult to see how they could overcome it while maintaining a commitment to the causal closure principle.
    [Show full text]
  • COMPETING MODELS of CONSCIOUSNESS David Rosenthal Philosophy and Cognitive Science Graduate Center, City University of New York
    COMPETING MODELS OF CONSCIOUSNESS David Rosenthal Philosophy and Cognitive Science Graduate Center, City University of New York REVISED PENULTIMATE VERSION Word count: 2,248 Graziano and colleagues (forthcoming) sketch some suggestive ways in which Graziano’s attention-schema theory (AST) of consciousness (Graziano 2013, 2019; Webb and Graziano 2015) connects with three other theories: the global-workspace theory (GWT) of Baars (1997) and Dehaene and Naccache (2001), higher-order-thought (HOT) theory (Rosenthal 2005), and illusionism (Frankish 2016). According to Graziano and colleagues, these “theories should not be viewed as rivals, but as partial perspectives on a deeper mechanism” (1). The deeper mechanism they have in mind is that of AST, which they urge constitutes “a kind of standard model that covers the basics if not the details” of consciousness (1). I’ll raise difficulties for this irenic construal of these four theories, and argue that they are in important ways theoretical competitors. Graziano and colleagues see the term ‘consciousness’ as applying to two distinct phenomena. One is “how select information reaches a state in which it is bundled centrally and can impact output systems.” They call this i-consciousness, in contrast with what they call m-consciousness, “a more mysterious, extra, experiential essence that people claim accompanies the informational content” that occurs in i-consciousness (2). The ‘m’ of ‘m- consciousness’ reflects their view that this notion is inherently mysterious. With that distinction in place, Graziano and colleagues urge that the central issue for a theoretical treatment of consciousness is “whether m-consciousness, the more ethereal notion of consciousness that people intuitively believe they have, is accurate or instead is an imperfect model of i-consciousness” (2).
    [Show full text]