THE STRUCTURE of BEING in ARISTOTLE's METAPHYSICS the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

THE STRUCTURE of BEING in ARISTOTLE's METAPHYSICS the New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy THE STRUCTURE OF BEING IN ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 52 Managing Editor: SIMO KNuUTTILA, University ofHelsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL ELLIOT GARBER, University ofChicago RICHARD SORABJI, University ofLondon Editorial Consultants: JAN A. AERTSEN, Thorrws-Institut, Universitiit zu Koln, Germany ROGER ARIEW, Virginia Polytechnic Institute E. JENNIFER ASHWORTH, University ofWaterloo MICHAEL AVERS, Wadham College, Oxford GAIL FINE, Cornell University R. 1. HANKINSON, University ofTexas JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University, Finnish Academy PAUL HOFFMAN, University ofCalifornia, Riverside DAVID KONSTAN, Brown University RICHARD H. KRAUT, Northwestern University, Evanston ALAIN DE LIBERA, Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes, Sorbonne JOHN E. MURDOCH, Harvard University DAVID FATE NORTON, McGill University LUCA OBERTELLO, Universita degli Studi di Genova ELEONORE STUMP, St. Louis University ALLEN WOOD, Stanford University The titles published in this series are listed at the end ofthis volume. THESTRUCTURE OF BEING IN ARIS TOTLE , S METAPHYSICS By JlYUANYU State University of New York at Buffalo, U.s.A. SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS :MEDIA, B.V. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data ISBN 978-94-010-3991-8 ISBN 978-94-010-0055-0 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-010-0055-0 Printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved © 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2003 Softcover reprint ofthe hardcover Ist edition 2003 No part of this work may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise, without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use by the purchaser of the work. To Yajie CONTENTS Acknowledgements ix Abbreviations xi Introduction xiii Chapter 1 Per se Being and Potential/actual Being 1 i. Per se being 1 ii. PotentiaVactual being 9 iii. The scope of the focal structure of being 18 Chapter 2 From Being to Substance 21 i. The focal connection ofper se beings 22 ii. PotentiaVactual being and substance 36 iii. The science of being 42 Chapter 3 Hylomorphism and Its Two Approaches 49 i. The composition of substance 51 ii. Two hylomorphic approaches 57 iii. The new start ofMetaphysics vii. 17 65 iv. Re-grouping the central books 76 Chapter 4 Subject, Form~ and Essence 83 i. Substance and subject 85 ii. Form and subject 92 iii. Substance and essence 96 iv. The identity of form and essence 105 Chapter 5 Form: Tode ti and Toionde 113 i. Primary reality and knowledge 115 ii. Separation, tode ti, and toionde 118 iii. Tode ti, particularity, and individuality 122 iv. Separation 127 v. Tode ti and definition 132 vi. Form as toionde 137 vii. The universal and toionde 145 viii. The ending of Metaphysics vii 150 Chapter 6 Substantial Potentiality and Actuality 155 I. Kinesis and energeia 156 vii viii CONTENTS ii. Substantial generation 162 iii. Substantial activity 169 iv. Substantial unity 176 Chapter 7 Actuality and the Prime Mover 181 i. From actual form to the Prime Mover 181 ii. The Prime Mover and eternity 188 iii. The Prime Mover and the world order 197 Chapter 8 The Unity of Aristotle's Metaphysics 201 Bibliography 211 Index of Passages 223 Name Index 231 Subject Index 235 Acknowledgements The central idea of this work is that the distinction that Aristotle draws between per se being and potentiaVactual being should be taken seriously. I argue that a correct application of this distinction to the central books of the Metaphysics leads to a distinct interpretation of these texts and to a better understanding of Aristotle's science of being. Some parts of the book have appeared as journal articles, though in all cases they have been substantially altered or recast. Sections i and iii of Chapter 2 are from Apeiron 34 (2001). Part of Chapter 3 has appeared in Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 15 (1997). Sections iii and iv of Chapter 4 can be found in the Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (2001). A remote ancestor of Chapter 5 was published in the Philosophical Inquiry 16 (1994). Permission to re-use these materials is gratefully acknowledged. I am deeply indebted to Jorge J. E. Gracia, who spent a whole week reading the penultimate version of the manuscript and who provided detailed comments. I am truly fortunate to have a supportive and passionate colleague like him. I am also grateful to Kenneth Dorter, who greatly helped when I worked on the first version of this project. Many other colleagues and friends have read chapters of this book at various stages of its development or versions of papers which have become parts of this book. For their help and encouragement, I thank David Bostock, Lesley Brown, Nicholas Bunnin, Roger Crisp, Michael Frede, John Keams, Gareth Matthews, Christopher Taylor, and Wang Zisong. Ingrid Krabbenbos of Kluwer Academic Publishers deserves special thanks for her patience and encouragement. Jonathan Sanford, Marcus Marenda, and Mark Niswonger, as graduate assistants at different stages of this work, provided valuable assistance. When the manuscript was accepted, the Julian Park Fund at the College of Arts and Sciences, State University of New York at Buffalo, generously provided me a grant to cover the costs of the proofreading and the preparation of the indices. I am grateful to Gerol Petruzella for his careful and critical review ofthe final version and his skillful compilation of the indices. ix Abbreviations of Aristotle's Works APo. Analytica Posteriora APr. Analytica Priora De. De Caelo Cat. Categoriae DA. De Anima D/. De Interpretatione EE. Ethica Eudemia EN. Ethica Nicomachea GA. De Generatione Animalium Ge. De Generatione et Corruptione HA. Historia Animalium MA. De Motu Animalium Meta. Metaphysica Meteor. Meteorologica PA. De Panibus Animalium Ph. Physica PN. Parva Naturalia Pol. Politica Pn. Protrepticus Rh. Rhetorica SE. Sophistici Elenchi Top. Topica Aristotle's works are cited in standard form: abbreviated title, book. chapter, Bekker page, column, and line. Except where it is otherwise stated, quotations of Aristotle are from The Revised Oxford Translations ofThe Completed Works' of Aristotle (abbreviated as "ROT"). When a technical term is the subject of the discussion but is open to various translations, I leave it untranslated both in quotations and in discussions. All necessary Greek is transliterated and explained. xi Introduction In his Metaphysics, Aristotle claims that he is seeking to establish a science of being. Being, at the most general level, is divided by Aristotle into the following four types: 1. Accidental being 2. Being as truth 3. Potential/actual being 4. Per se beingl Per se (kath hauto) being can also be translated as "being in its own right" or "intrinsic being". This type of being has been referred to by Aristotle in different ways. The list of per se beings includes substance, quantity, quality, place, time, etc., and this is also the list of categories. At Meta. ix.l, 1045b28 Aristotle calls this list the "categories of being" (hai kategoriai tou ontos). At Meta. vi.2, 1026a36 and ix.1O, 1051a33-b2 per se being is called "being with reference to the figures of predication" (ta schemata tes kategorias, or "figures ofcategories,,).2 Of these four types of being, accidental being is briefly treated in Meta. vi.2-3 and there Aristotle claims that the study of accidental being can be dismissed on the grounds that accidental being is indeterminate and cannot be the object of knowledge. 3 He also does not pay much attention to being as truth and treats it briefly in two short texts: Meta. viA and ix.1O. His reason is that being as truth depends on combination and separation in thought but not in things, and hence ''that which is in this sense is a different sort of being from the things that are in the full sense (for the thought attaches or removes either the 'what' or quality or quantity or one of the other categories), and that which is accidentally and that which is in the sense of being true must be dismissed." (viA, 1027b30-34) The science of being, then, is mainly concerned with per se being (or categorial being) and potential/actual being. 1 Meta. v.7. cr. also Meta. vi.2, 1026a34-b2, ix.10, 1051a33-b2. 2 The relation between being and category will be discussed in Chapter I, section I. I shall use the term "categorial being" interchangeably with "per se being". 3 Meta. vi.2,1026b4, vi.2, 1027310, viA, 1027b17. xiii xiv THE STRUCTURE OF BEING IN ARISTOTLE'S METAPHYSICS According to the structure ofthe Metaphysics as we have it, the discussion of these two types of beings occupies the central books of the Metaphysics: Meta. vii, viii, and ix. 4 Aristotle himself indicates explicitly that these two kinds of beings are the subject-matter ofthese central books: We have treated of that which is primarily and to which all the other categories of being are referred - i.e., ofsubstance.... Since being is in one way divided into this thing, quality, and quantity, and is in another way distinguished in respect of potentiality and fulfillment, and of function, let us discuss potentiality and fulfillment. (Meta. ix.I, 1045b28-35) This passage singles out per se being and potential/actual being from the four­ fold division of being, and indicates that these two types of being belong to separate investigations. The central books of the Metaphysics have been regarded as the most mature and fundamental texts, but they are notoriously difficult. Indeed, almost everything said in these books is open to various interpretations and debates, and the scholarship on these books is marked by numerous controversies and debates.
Recommended publications
  • Aristotelian Metaphysics: Essence and Ground
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Helsingin yliopiston digitaalinen arkisto Editorial Aristotelian Metaphysics: Essence and Ground Riin Sirkela, Tuomas Tahkob aDepartment of Philosophy, University of Vermont bDepartment of Philosophy, University of Helsinki is special issue of Studia Philosophica Estonica centers around Aristotelian metaphysics, construed broadly to cover both scholarly research on Aristo- tle’s metaphysics as well as work by contemporary metaphysicians on Aris- totelian themes. Aristotelian metaphysics is a growing tradition. ere are increasingly more metaphysicians identifying themselves as ‘Aristotelians’, and there are more scholars looking at work in contemporary metaphysics to advance scholarship. Indeed, there have already been a number of vol- umes showcasing this ‘Aristotelian turn’, including Daniel D. Novotný’s and Lukáš Novák’s Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics (óþÕ¦), Edward Feser’s Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics (óþÕì), and Tuomas Tahko’s Contempo- rary Aristotelian Metaphysics (óþÕó). e contribution this special issue makes to the ongoing discussion is twofold. First, the special issue promotes a deeper interaction between schol- ars of Aristotle and contemporary metaphysicians. We hope that the pa- pers encourage people working in the history of philosophy to relate to con- temporary discussions and people working in contemporary metaphysics to engage with Aristotle and Ancient scholarship. Second, the special issue is unied in its focus on two themes in Aristotelian metaphysics, essence and grounding. e papers address questions concerning fundamentality and dependence, ontological independence or priority, the causal priority of forms, the unity of grounding, the reduction of grounding to essence, the unity of essence, the roles of essence, and explanation and denition.
    [Show full text]
  • Hendrik Lorenz/Benjamin Morison Aristotle: Metaphysics Z PHI501, Fall/Spring 2018/2019
    Hendrik Lorenz/Benjamin Morison Aristotle: Metaphysics Z PHI501, Fall/Spring 2018/2019 Aims of the course In this class, we aim to go through systematically the 17 chapters of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, book Z (sometimes called book VII), and chapter 1 of book H of the Metaphysics (the one immediately following Z), since we hold, as do many other scholars, that it is best read as a continuation of book Z. The goal is to understand Aristotle’s famous theory of ‘substance’ as presented in book Z. Substances are the central items in Aristotle’s ontology, and there are a cluster of other notions in the vicinity of ‘substance’ which we will also be trying to clarify: ‘being’, ‘account’, ‘form’, ‘this’, ‘subject’, ‘matter’, ‘essence’ or ‘being what it is’, etc. We also want to assess what kind of treatise Metaphysics Z is: its train of thought is notoriously hard to follow, with apparent digressions, or even insertions, so it might not even have been considered a unified treatise by Aristotle. There is also the question of its relation to the science of metaphysics: is it a preliminary contribution to it, or an actual exposition of (a fragment of) it? Is there even a science of metaphysics (in the sense of ‘science’ defined in the Posterior Analytics) to which it could be related? Brief list of some themes of Metaphysics Z Fall: Z1: Being is said in many ways; the central one is being as substance; so the question ‘what is being’ is the question ‘what is substance?’; Z2: Catalogue of some items which philosophers have thought count as substances;
    [Show full text]
  • God As Both Ideal and Real Being in the Aristotelian Metaphysics
    God As Both Ideal and Real Being In the Aristotelian Metaphysics Martin J. Henn St. Mary College Aristotle asserts in Metaphysics r, 1003a21ff. that "there exists a science which theorizes on Being insofar as Being, and on those attributes which belong to it in virtue of its own nature."' In order that we may discover the nature of Being Aristotle tells us that we must first recognize that the term "Being" is spoken in many ways, but always in relation to a certain unitary nature, and not homonymously (cf. Met. r, 1003a33-4). Beings share the same name "eovta," yet they are not homonyms, for their Being is one and the same, not manifold and diverse. Nor are beings synonyms, for synonymy is sameness of name among things belonging to the same genus (as, say, a man and an ox are both called "animal"), and Being is no genus. Furthermore, synonyms are things sharing a common intrinsic nature. But things are called "beings" precisely because they share a common relation to some one extrinsic nature. Thus, beings are neither homonyms nor synonyms, yet their core essence, i.e. their Being as such, is one and the same. Thus, the unitary Being of beings must rest in some unifying nature extrinsic to their respective specific essences. Aristotle's dialectical investigations into Being eventually lead us to this extrinsic nature in Book A, i.e. to God, the primary Essence beyond all specific essences. In the pre-lambda books of the Metaphysics, however, this extrinsic nature remains very much up for grabs.
    [Show full text]
  • Dio Chrysostom's Charidemus and Aristotle's Eudemus
    Dio Chrysostom’s Charidemus and Aristotle’s Eudemus Katarzyna Jażdżewska IO CHRYSOSTOM’S DIALOGUE Charidemus exhibits a rich intertextual network, and recent scholarship has D explored Dio’s interaction with Plato’s Phaedo, with Hellenistic philosophy (particularly Stoicism and Cynicism), and with consolation, λόγος παραµυθητικός.1 In this note I would like to add to the literary background of the dialogue by arguing that, so far as extant evidence allows us to judge, Dio’s Charidemus seems to have been particularly closely associated with Aristotle’s lost dialogue Eudemus in respect to format, overall character, and themes covered. Aristotle’s Eudemus was a dialogue written to commemorate Eudemus of Cyprus, a deceased friend and a member of the Academy, who died in Syracuse around 354 B.C.E.2 Ps.- Plutarch’s Consolation to Apollonius 115B (= Arist. fr.44) informs us that Aristotle’s work was known under the title Eudemus, or On the soul. We do not know who the interlocutors were; Aristotle may have been one of the speakers.3 From Cicero’s De 1 For Plato see J. Moles, “The Dionian Charidemus,” 187–210, and M. Trapp, “Plato in Dio,” 213–239, in S. Swain (ed.), Dio Chrysostom. Politics, Letters, and Philosophy (Oxford 2000); K. Jażdżewska, “Dio Chrysostom’s Charidemos: A Study,” Eos 101 (2014) 67–81, at 69–76. For consolatory topoi, M. C. Giner Soria, “Acotaciones a un diálogo consolatorio,” Faventia 12–13 (1990) 293–305. For an overview of various influences on the Charidemus, M. Menchelli, Dione di Prusa. Caridemo (Or. XXX) (Naples 1999) 37–75.
    [Show full text]
  • The Protrepticus of Clement of Alexandria: a Commentary
    Miguel Herrero de Jáuregui THE PROTREPTICUS OF CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA: A COMMENTARY to; ga;r yeu'do" ouj yilh'/ th'/ paraqevsei tajlhqou'" diaskedavnnutai, th'/ de; crhvsei th'" ajlhqeiva" ejkbiazovmenon fugadeuvetai. La falsedad no se dispersa por la simple comparación con la verdad, sino que la práctica de la verdad la fuerza a huir. Protréptico 8.77.3 PREFACIO Una tesis doctoral debe tratar de contribuir al avance del conocimiento humano en su disciplina, y la pretensión de que este comentario al Protréptico tenga la máxima utilidad posible me obliga a escribirla en inglés porque es la única lengua que hoy casi todos los interesados pueden leer. Pero no deja de ser extraño que en la casa de Nebrija se deje de lado la lengua castellana. La deuda que contraigo ahora con el español sólo se paliará si en el futuro puedo, en compensación, “dar a los hombres de mi lengua obras en que mejor puedan emplear su ocio”. Empiezo ahora a saldarla, empleándola para estos agradecimientos, breves en extensión pero no en sinceridad. Mi gratitud va, en primer lugar, al Cardenal Don Gil Álvarez de Albornoz, fundador del Real Colegio de España, a cuya generosidad y previsión debo dos años provechosos y felices en Bolonia. Al Rector, José Guillermo García-Valdecasas, que administra la herencia de Albornoz con ejemplar dedicación, eficacia y amor a la casa. A todas las personas que trabajan en el Colegio y hacen que cumpla con creces los objetivos para los que se fundó. Y a mis compañeros bolonios durante estos dos años. Ha sido un honor muy grato disfrutar con todos ellos de la herencia albornociana.
    [Show full text]
  • Advancing the Aristotelian Project in Contemporary Metaphysics a Review Essay
    Philosophia Christi Vol. 21, No. 2 © 2019 Advancing the Aristotelian Project in Contemporary Metaphysics A Review Essay Robert C. Koons University of Texas at Austin Abstract: In a recent book, Substance and the Fundamentality of the Familiar, Ross Inman demonstrates the contemporary relevance of an Aristotelian approach to metaphysics and the philosophy of nature. Inman successfully applies the Aristotelian framework to a number of outstanding problems in metaphysics, philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of physics. Inman tackles some intriguing questions about the ontological status of proper parts, questions which constitute a central focus of ongoing debate and investigation. Ross D. Inman. Substance and the Fundamentality of the Familiar: A Neo- Aristotelian Mereology. New York: Routledge, 2018. 304 pages. $140.00. Ross Inman’s book is an excellent new installment in the ongoing renais- sance of Aristotelian metaphysics in analytic philosophy. Central Aristote- lian notions, such as substance, essence, causal powers, dependent parts, and matter/form combination, have reemerged in recent years, beginning with the work of Teodore Scaltsas, Peter van Inwagen, Kit Fine, David Oderberg, and Michal Rea in the 1990s.1 Te movement began to develop and fourish afer the turn of the millennium. Kit Fine, David Oderberg, Michael Loux, and E. J. Lowe built upon their own earlier work,2 while new collaborators 1. See Peter van Inwagen, “Material Beings,” Philosophy 67 (1990): 126–7; Teodore Scalt- sas, Substances and Universals in Aristotle’s Metaphysics (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994); Kit Fine, “Tings and Teir Parts,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23 (1999): 61–74; David S.
    [Show full text]
  • Greek and Latin Roots, Prefixes, and Suffixes
    GREEK AND LATIN ROOTS, PREFIXES, AND SUFFIXES This is a resource pack that I put together for myself to teach roots, prefixes, and suffixes as part of a separate vocabulary class (short weekly sessions). It is a combination of helpful resources that I have found on the web as well as some tips of my own (such as the simple lesson plan). Lesson Plan Ideas ........................................................................................................... 3 Simple Lesson Plan for Word Study: ........................................................................... 3 Lesson Plan Idea 2 ...................................................................................................... 3 Background Information .................................................................................................. 5 Why Study Word Roots, Prefixes, and Suffixes? ......................................................... 6 Latin and Greek Word Elements .............................................................................. 6 Latin Roots, Prefixes, and Suffixes .......................................................................... 6 Root, Prefix, and Suffix Lists ........................................................................................... 8 List 1: MEGA root list ................................................................................................... 9 List 2: Roots, Prefixes, and Suffixes .......................................................................... 32 List 3: Prefix List ......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics of Soul and Self in Plotinus Gwenaëlle Aubry
    Metaphysics of soul and self in Plotinus Gwenaëlle Aubry To cite this version: Gwenaëlle Aubry. Metaphysics of soul and self in Plotinus. P. Remes; S. Slaveva-Griffin. The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism, pp.310-323, 2014. hal-02387195 HAL Id: hal-02387195 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02387195 Submitted on 29 Nov 2019 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. 20 Metaphysics of soul and self in Plotinus Gwenaëlle Aubry One of the great singularities of the philosophy of Plotinus consists in thinking of the self1 for its own sake and, in particular, in producing a concept of it diff erent from that of soul.2 Th is philosophical breakthrough is inseparable from the discovery of immedi- ate refl exivity, that is, the subject’s ability to apprehend itself independently of its rela- tion to an object or to another subject.3 In Plotinus, however, this refl exivity occurs only in an interrogative form, which can be read, in particular, in Enn. I.1[53] and Enn. VI.4[22]. In other words, it does not, as in Descartes, assume the form of an intuition by means of which the subject, grasping itself as consciousness, would, at the same time, have an evident revelation of its essence.
    [Show full text]
  • Daniel Jugrin
    Studia Philosophiae Christianae UKSW 52(2016)2 DanIel JuGrIn THE WAY OF ἈΝΆΛΥΣΙΣ: CLEMENT OF ALEXANDRIA AND THE PLATONIC TRADITION Abstract. In Clement of Alexandria, the three ways of knowing God appear implicitly in the form: the way of analogy, the way of negation (in the mathematical version), and the way of eminence. A basic aspect of the negation appears as an expression of Clementine criticism on anthropomorphism. The Platonic traditional model of via negativa is related to the mathematical theory of abstraction and is defined as a denial of the material things in order to reach the contemplation of God through pure mind: “we start by abstracting the surface, and we are left with the line; we abstract the line, and we are left with the point; we abstract the point, or strictly speaking the monad, and we are then precipitated into the greatness of Christ” (Stromateis V.11.71.2). Clement of Alexandria is, also, one of the authors who emphasize silence and prayer as having great importance in the knowledge process. The cessation of the activity of the senses leads to the supreme state of contemplation with a pure mind. Silence becomes, in this way, a symbol of God, and knowledge – not a matter of speaking, but of being. Keywords: Clement of Alexandria, Platonic Tradition, knowledge of God, abstractive way, analysis, aphairesis, silence 1. The geometrical method of ἀνάλυσις . 2. Via negativa and the theme of silence in Clement of Alexandria. 3. The origin of the mathematical model of via negativa. St. Justin, martyr and philosopher (103 – 165 AD), was the first Christian thinker who claimed that God can be characterized only in negative terms.1 His vision was familiar in the context of Helle- nistic Judaism: Philo of Alexandria (20 BC – 50 AD)2 had already established the ideas put forward by Justin.
    [Show full text]
  • Phil 252S Seminar on Meta-Metaphysics
    Phil 252S Seminar on Meta-metaphysics Professor: Sara Bernstein ([email protected]) Special Guest: Peter van Inwagen Metaphysics concerns questions about what exists: for example, do chairs really exist, or are there merely particles arranged chair-wise? What are the criteria for their existence? Meta-metaphysics concerns questions about the methodology and substantivity of metaphysics. For example, does reality furnish answers to metaphysical questions? If so, do we have epistemic access to the answers? Or is it our language and social conventions that give us answers to metaphysical questions? Do answers to these questions determine the substantivity of metaphysical debates? Required Texts: Metametaphysics (ed. Wasserman and Chalmers) Requirements: For undergraduate students: weekly well-formed questions due on Tuesdays at 6pm (20%) one in-class presentations on a course reading (20%) one 6-8 page term paper (40%) class participation (20%) For graduate students: weekly well-formed questions due on Tuesdays at 6pm (10%) one in-class presentation on a course reading (10%) one presentation on your own term paper and term paper (60%) class participation (20%) Schedule: Wednesday, January 19: Introduction to Metametaphysics Ted Sider, “Ontology” (chapter 9) and “Metametaphysics” (chapter 5) from Writing the Book of the World (unpublished draft) (Blackboard) 1 January 26: First-Order Ontological Debates Peter van Inwagen, Material Beings, Chapters 2 and 3 (Blackboard) David Lewis and Stephanie Lewis, “Holes” (Blackboard) February 2:
    [Show full text]
  • The Univocity of Substance and the Formal Distinction of Attributes: the Role of Duns Scotus in Deleuze's Reading of Spinoza Nathan Widder
    parrhesia 33 · 2020 · 150-176 the univocity of substance and the formal distinction of attributes: the role of duns scotus in deleuze's reading of spinoza nathan widder This paper examines the role played by medieval theologian John Duns Scotus in Gilles Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza’s philosophy of expressive substance; more generally, it elaborates a crucial moment in the development of Deleuze’s philosophy of sense and difference. Deleuze contends that Spinoza adapts and extends Duns Scotus’s two most influential theses, the univocity of being and formal distinction, despite neither appearing explicitly in Spinoza’s writings. “It takes nothing away from Spinoza’s originality,” Deleuze declares, “to place him in a perspective that may already be found in Duns Scotus” (Deleuze, 1992, 49).1 Nevertheless, the historiographic evidence is clearly lacking, leaving Deleuze to admit that “it is hardly likely that” Spinoza had even read Duns Scotus (359n28). Indeed, the only support he musters for his speculation is Spinoza’s obvious in- terests in scholastic metaphysical and logical treatises, the “probable influence” of the Scotist-informed Franciscan priest Juan de Prado on his thought, and the fact that the problems Duns Scotus addresses need not be confined to Christian thought (359–360n28). The paucity of evidence supporting this “use and abuse” of history, however, does not necessarily defeat the thesis. Like other lineages Deleuze proposes, the one he traces from Duns Scotus to Spinoza, and subsequently to Nietzsche, turns not on establishing intentional references by one thinker to his predecessor, but instead on showing how the borrowings and adaptations asserted to create the connec- tion make sense of the way the second philosopher surmounts blockages he faces while responding to issues left unaddressed by the first.
    [Show full text]
  • The Distinction Between Reason and Intuitive Knowledge in Spinoza's
    The Distinction between Reason and Intuitive Knowledge in Spinoza’s Ethics Sanem Soyarslan Duke University While both intuitive knowledge (scientia intuitiva) and reason (ratio) are adequate ways of knowing for Spinoza, they are not equal. Intuitive knowledge has greater power over the passive affects than reason, and appreciating the nature of this superiority is crucial to understanding Spinoza‘s ethical theory. However, due to Spinoza‘s notoriously parsimonious treatment of the distinction between reason and intuitive knowledge in the Ethics, there has been little consensus in the literature regarding the nature of this distinction. Instead, several candidate interpretations have emerged, which can be broadly grouped under two categories: Form Interpretations (FI) and Content Interpretations (CI). According to the FI, which is held by scholars such as Yirmiyahu Yovel1 and Steven Nadler2, reason and intuitive knowledge are different only in terms of their form—that is, the process by which they are attained. Thus, the FI attributes the above epistemic asymmetry entirely to differences in the methods of cognition between intuitive knowledge and reason. By contrast, the CI, embraced by scholars such as Henry Allison3 and Edwin Curley4, holds that the two kinds of adequate knowledge differ not only in terms of their form, but also with regard to their content. More specifically, the CI maintains that reason involves the universal knowledge of the properties of things, whereas intuitive knowledge relates to the essence of things. I agree with the CI that reason and intuitive knowledge differ not only in form but also with respect to their content. Nevertheless, I believe there is an important gap in the CI: namely, although it maintains that adequate knowledge of the essences of things is limited to intuitive knowledge, it fails to flesh out precisely what these essences are taken to be.
    [Show full text]