Dembski, Darwin and Devils

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Dembski, Darwin and Devils DEMBSKI, DARWIN AND DEVILS JASON ROSENHOUSE Reviews of The Design Revolution by William Dembski, InterVar- sity Press, Downer’s Grove, Illinois., 2004, 334 Pages; God, the Devil and Darwin, by Niall Shanks, Oxford University Press, New York, NY, 2004, 273 Pages; and Darwinism, Design, and Public Education by John A. Campbell and Stephen Meyer, Michigan State University Press, East Lansing, MI, 2003, 634 Pages. 1. The Design Revolution Since William Dembski’s latest book is subtitled “Answering the Toughest Questions About Intelligent Design”, the naive reader might think that he has taken seriously the numerous criticisms leveled at his ideas. More experienced readers will be unsurprised to learn that Dem- bski mostly just repeats the same fallacious arguments he has always made. None of the major criticisms of his work is adequately addressed. After briefly summarizing his ideas for detecting design in natural phe- nomena, I will discuss two of the most fundamental difficulties with his work. Dembski’s primary contributions to evolution-denial are his ponder- ous, repetitive musings about complex, specified information (CSI). It is his assertion that if you find CSI in some physical structure, you can be sure that lurking somewhere in its causal history is an intelligent designer. He further asserts that animals are replete with instances of CSI, implying they did not emerge from natural processes alone. Dembski’s term “information” refers to some event or phenomenon. “Complex” then indicates the probability of the event occurring by nat- ural causes alone is small, while “specified” means the event embodies some pattern describable without reference to the structure itself. In its application to biology, the events Dembski envisions are certain complex, biomolecular machines. The idea is that the particular sequence of heads and tails that emerges when a fair coin is flipped one thousand times is highly im- probable, but this by itself does not make us suspicious. But if the 1 2 JASON ROSENHOUSE sequence consists of one thousand heads, we now have a pattern that is both complex and specified. Consequently, we suspect there is skull- duggery afoot. There is nothing more to Dembski’s work than that, a fact that is easily overlooked when slogging through his excessively technical scribblings. 2. Probability Calculations How are we to carry out an appropriate probability calculation for events whose occurrence is influenced by more variables than we can plausibly measure? Such calculations begin with an enumeration of all the events that might have occurred in lieu of the one we are consid- ering. We then assign a probability to each of those outcomes, which in any nontrivial, real-life case is likely to require far more information than we have. The problem is especially acute when the events we are considering are the endpoints of four billion years of evolution. Dembski is aware of this problem. He writes: The argument starts by noting that if some natural sys- tem exemplifies specified complexity, then it must be vastly improbable with respect to all purely natural mech- anisms that could be operating to produce it. But that means calculating a probability for each such mechanism. This, so the argument runs, is an impossible task. At best science could show that a given natural system is vastly improbable with respect to known mechanisms op- erating in known ways and for which the probability can be estimated. But this omits, first, known mechanisms operating in unknown ways and for which the probabil- ity cannot be estimated; second, known mechanisms for which the probability cannot be estimated; and third, unknown mechanisms. (P. 110). Well said. It’s the second of the three omissions that is most serious. Biologists say that complex systems evolve gradually as a result of natural selection. That is a known mechanism, but one whose effects are too complicated to be captured in a simple probability calculation. Dembski has exactly one card to play in circumventing this objec- tion: The irreducible complexity (IC) of certain biochemical systems. IC is the brainchild of Michael Behe, who coined the term in his 1996 book Darwin’s Black Box. A system is IC if it is composed of several, well-matched, indispensable parts. Behe and Dembski argue it is im- plausible that such systems could evolve gradually. Though Dembski DEMBSKI, DARWIN AND DEVILS 3 claims to have a general procedure for detecting design in events whose causal history is unknown, in practice he only applies it to biology. He has a few stock examples for illustrating his ideas, but it is only in bi- ology that Dembski presumes to resolve questions of scientific interest. IC is essential for this purpose, because he must preclude the possibil- ity that complex biochemical systems form gradually through natural selection. Which means that Dembski’s entire body of work on complex spec- ified information, amounting to thousands of pages, contributes abso- lutely nothing to the evolution/creation debate. In the end, the whole argument comes down to the legitimacy of Behe’s claims about IC. If Behe’s premise is granted (something no competent biologist is likely to do), then no dubious probability calculation is needed to conclude that evolution as we know it is in trouble. If it is not granted, then the assumptions underlying Dembski’s probability calculations are plainly false. Dembski asserts that, as a matter of logic, IC systems cannot evolve directly. He writes: The logical point is this: Certain artificial structures are provably inaccessible to a direct Darwinian pathway be- cause they have property P (i.e. irreducible complexity). But certain biological structures have property P , so they too must be inaccessible to a direct Darwinian pathway. (P. 293. Emphasis in original). Here is his definition of “direct Darwinian pathway”: A direct Darwinian pathway is one in which a system evolves by natural selection, incrementally enhancing a given function. As the system evolves, the function does not. (P. 293) Of course, this says nothing about indirect pathways, which biol- ogists believe are quite common in evolution. Dembski dismisses this possibility, but does so only by downplaying the vast literature address- ing biochemical evolution. For a large number of biochemical systems there is quite a lot known about their evolution. More to the point, however, is that IC does not preclude direct Dar- winian pathways. That every part of a machine is currently essential does not imply that it has always been essential. Behe ignored this pos- sibility in Darwin’s Black Box. Dembski tries to evade it by introducing the notion of “minimal complexity (MC),” by which he means that no system less complex than the minimum could perform the function of 4 JASON ROSENHOUSE the full machine. In this formulation it is the combination of IC and MC that rule out direct Darwinian pathways. The problem is that a complex system does not evolve in a vacuum. Rather, its environment evolves along with it. A system may be MC in its present environment, but not be MC in some ancestral environ- ment. Put another way, a simpler system might have been functional in a simpler environment. But including this possibility would make it impossible to apply the concept of MC. As an example, consider the scenario for blood clotting evolution described by Russell Doolittle and others. Every step in its formation was useful for the purpose of blood clotting. This is possible because the nature of the circulatory system in which the system was operat- ing changed over time. The earliest stages of the cascade formed in an ancient invertebrate with a low-pressure circulatory system. Conse- quently, the organism could get by with a relatively slow and primitive clotting mechanism. Our modern blood clotting system evolved in tan- dem with changes in the circulatory system. Consequently, IC is utterly irrelevant to any question of biological significance. 3. Specificity Low probability by itself does not preclude chance as an explanation for an event. To infer design we need something else, and Dembski offers specification for that purpose. The idea is that the event in question should conform to some iden- tifiable pattern. Dembski has offered elaborate statistical justifications for knowing the genuine patterns from the ones imposed by human imagination, but we will lose nothing by ignoring these details. To jus- tify the claim that the bacterial flagellum (the only biological system Dembski considers) is specified, he writes: Certainly the bacterial flagellum is specified. One way to see this is to note that humans developed bi-directional motor-driven propellers well before they figured out that the flagellum was such a machine. This is not to say that for the biological function of a system to constitute a specification, humans must have independently invented a system that performs the same function. Nevertheless, independent invention makes all the more clear that the system satisfies independent functional requirements and therefore is specified. At any rate, no biologist I know DEMBSKI, DARWIN AND DEVILS 5 questions whether the functional systems that arise in biology are specified. (P. 111) I love that last line. Since there are, at present, no biologists at all who use the term “specified” in the peculiar technical sense Dembski envisions, I suspect he is right. Apparently specifying the bacterial flagellum only requires making an analogy between the manner in which it performs its function and some human invention that serves a similar purpose. Nothing technical there. If this is different from looking at a cumulus cloud and seeing a dragon, I do not see how. In illustrating his ideas about specification, Dembski frequently makes reference to Mt. Rushmore. Any particular pattern of cracks and ridges in a mountain is terribly improbable, but the faces on Mt Rushmore fit a clear specification.
Recommended publications
  • Paley's New Clothes. a Review of God, the Devil
    Evolutionary Psychology human-nature.com/ep – 2004. 2: 195-199 ¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯¯ Book Review Paley’s New Clothes A review of God, the Devil, and Darwin by Niall Shanks. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. Sean J. Cunningham, Department of Sociology, University of Washington, Seattle, Wa. 98195, USA. Email: [email protected]. A new creationist offshoot, euphemistically dubbed “Intelligent Design” (ID) by its progenitors, has emerged on the political scene in recent years. Unlike its tactless counterparts (e.g., “Young Earth Creationism”), whose blatant religiosity has spelled almost certain demise, this insidious branch remains publicly agnostic about the nature of the “Intelligent Designer,” and is successfully framing ID as a bona fide scientific alternative to Darwinism. Although it constitutes little more than a souped- up version of theologian William Paley’s classic “argument from design,” the woeful state of America’s scientific literacy has us falling for the ruse. Indeed, the Intelligent Design movement has recently infiltrated several state legislatures, and even tallied its first substantial victory in Ohio (American Institute of Biological Sciences, 2004), where ID devotees were highly influential in convincing the state to require “critical analysis of evolution” as a part of its new public school science curriculum. Although this stops short of a legal mandate to teach ID, it smacks of smuggling it in through the back door. This suspicion was confirmed in March of this year when Ohio approved a 10th grade biological science lesson plan, referencing seminal ID texts and directing students to ID websites (Ohio Citizens for Science, 2004). Even worse, legislation that specifically mandates “equal-time” for ID in public schools was proposed (but died) in Missouri, and is still currently pending in Michigan (American Institute of Biological Sciences, 2004).
    [Show full text]
  • ROBERT T. PENNOCK, PH.D. Michigan State University Curriculum Vitae (August 13, 2019)
    ROBERT T. PENNOCK, PH.D. Michigan State University Curriculum Vitae (August 13, 2019) OFFICE: HOME: 919 E. Shaw Lane, Rm. E35 227 Clarendon Rd. East Lansing, MI 48825-1107 East Lansing MI 48823 (517) 432-7701 (517) 324-9994 E-mail: [email protected] WEB: <www.msu.edu/~pennock5> CURRENT APPOINTMENTS: • Michigan State University. University Distinguished Professor. (2019 – present). - History, Philosophy & Sociology of Science. Lyman Briggs College. - Philosophy. Department of Philosophy. - Computer Science, Department of Computer Science & Engineering - Ecology & Evolutionary Biology and Behavior (EEBB) Graduate Program. - Associate Faculty, Center for Ethics and Humanities in the Life Sciences. PREVIOUS APPOINTMENTS: • Michigan State University. Professor. (2005 – 2019) • University of Michigan, Institute for Social Research. Visiting Scholar (2014 – 2018) • American Association for the Advancement of Science. Visiting Scholar (2015) • Duke University, National Evolutionary Synthesis Center. Sabbatical Fellow (2008) • Michigan State University. Associate Professor (2000 – 2005) • The College of New Jersey. Assistant Professor of Philosophy. (1999 – 2000) • The University of Texas at Austin, Assistant Professor of Philosophy. (1991 – 1999) • Pennsylvania Governor’s School for the Sciences (P.G.S.S.), Faculty member. Carnegie-Mellon University (Summers, 1987-1991) EDUCATION: • B.A. w/ Honors, Biology/Philosophy, Earlham College, 1980. • Ph.D., History & Philosophy of Science. University of Pittsburgh, 1991. “Causally Licensed Inference and the Confirmation Relation.” Advisor: Wesley Salmon Committee: John Earman, Clark Glymour, Kenneth Schaffner, Herbert Simon Robert T. Pennock, Curriculum Vitae Page 2 ACADEMIC AWARDS / HONORS: • International Society for Artificial Life Education & Outreach Award as lead for Avida-ED. 2017. • MSU Phi Kappa Phi Excellence Award in Interdisciplinary Scholarship. For Avida-ED Project.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Experimentation: the Legacy of Claude Bernard
    INTERNATIONAL STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, VOL. 8, NO. 3, 1994 195 Animal Experimentation: the legacy of Claude Bernard Hugh LaFollette & Niall Shanks Abstract Claude Bernard, the father of scientific physiology, believed that if medicine was to become truly scientific, it would have to be based on rigorous and controlled animal experiments. Bernard instituted a paradigm which has shaped physiological practice for most of the twentieth century. In this paper we examine how Bernard's commitment to hypothetico-deductivism and determinism led to (a) his rejection of the theory of evolution; (b) his minimalization of the role of clinical medicine and epidemiological studies; and (c) his conclusion that experiments on non- human animals were, "entirely conclusive for the toxicology and hygiene of man". We examine some negative consequences of Bernardianism for twentieth century medicine, and argue that physiology's continued adherence to Bernardianism has caused it to diverge from the other biological sciences which have become increasingly infused with evolutionary theory. But when we reach the limits of vivisection we have other means of going deeper and dealing with the elementary parts of organisms where the elementary properties of vital phenomena have their seat. We may introduce poisons into the circulation, which carry their specific action to one or another histological unit . Poisons are veritable reagents of life, extremely delicate instruments which dissect vital units. (Claude Bernard, 1949)1 Introduction In 1988 the American Medical Association (AMA) issued a White Paper defending biomedical experimentation on animals.2 Although they trace the history of animal experimentation to the ancient world, it was the nineteenth century physiologist Claude Bernard who set out the principles of experimental medicine.
    [Show full text]
  • Vol 18, No 3, July
    THE LINNEAN 2002 VOLUME 18 I Editorial In our last issue we introduced the contentious subject of creationism by publishing a lecture given by the late Colin Patterson which was primarily about cladistics as a method for classification, but was, unfortunately, taken by anti-evolutionists to support their cause. In response, a good deal of correspondence has been received by The Linnean, some of which is reproduced in this issue, along with articles by Randy Moore and John Cloudsley-Thompson which defend the evolutionary view. More will be included in subsequent issues, as will the lecture given by Professor Dawkins when last year he unveiled a plaque commemorating the Darwin-Wallace lecture of 1858. In this issue we note how, throughout the United States, anti-evolutionists presently undermine the teaching of science by villifying evolution and demanding time in the schools to teach “creation science” and “intelligent design”. Much of the impetus for the movement against evolution was intitiated in 1925 when a Tennessee Democratic congressman and lay preacher named John Butler proposed a law which stated: “It shall be unlawful for any teacher in any of the universities, normals, and in all other public schools of the State, which are supported in whole or in any part by the public school funds of the State, to teach any theory that denies the story of the Divine Creation of Man as taught in the Bible, and to teach that man has descended from a lower order of animals.” The bill passed in the House, seventy-one to five and in the Senate, twenty-four to six, and the Governor, a Southern Baptist, signed it into law on the 2 1st March 1925.
    [Show full text]
  • Critique of Intelligent Design: Materialism Versus Creationism from Antiquity to the Present
    Critique of intelligent design: materialism versus creationism from antiquity to the present MORE OPTIONS Books Critique of Intelligent Design: Materialism versus Creationism from Antiquity to the Present by John Bellamy Foster, Brett Clark, Richard York Critique of Intelligent Design is a direct reply to the criticisms of intelligent design proponents and a compelling account of the long debate between materialism and religion in the West. It provides an overview of the contemporary fight concerning nature, science, history, morality, and knowledge. Separate chapters are devoted to the design debate in antiquity, the Enlightenment and natural theology, Marx, Darwin, and Freud, and to current scientific debates over evolution and design. It offers empowering tools to understand and defend critical and scientific reasoning in both the natural and social sciences and society as a whole. Search CSI: Creationism’s Trojan Horse: The Wedge of Intelligent Design Custom Search by Barbara Carroll Forrest, Paul R. Gross In Creationism’s Trojan Horse, Forrest and Gross examine in full I.D. Watch detail the claims and operations of the "Intelligent Design" movement, the most recent manifestation of American creationism. Explaining and analyzing what "design theorists" call ARTICLES their "Wedge Strategy," they document the Wedge’s aggressive political and public relations campaign. BOOKS LINKS Why Intelligent Design Fails: A Scientific Critique of the New Creationism NEWS Edited by Matt Young and Taner Edis Why Intelligent Design Fails assembles a team of physicists, biologists, computer scientists, mathematicians, and Tweets by @SkeptInquiry archaeologists to examine intelligent design from a scientific News & Announcements perspective. They consistently find grandiose claims without merit.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ethics of Science
    THE ETHICS OF SCIENCE “If anyone still believes that scientific research is a value-free zone, The Ethics of Science will disabuse them. David B.Resnik uses a wealth of actual and hypothetical examples in a clear philosophical discussion that illuminates the range of ethical concerns that scientists need to face. This is one area where philosophical argument can serve a practical need: the more scientists who think carefully about the issues Resnik raises, the better.” Peter Lipton Professor of History and Philosophy of Science University of Cambridge “Science faculty and students—and an interested public—will find The Ethics of Science admirably clear, balanced, and richly comprehensive. Resnik’s clarity shows itself not only in his unpretentious, straight-forwardness, but by being philosophically sophisticated yet avoiding jargon. An extremely useful aspect of the book is that virtually every kind of ethical question that arises in and about science is addressed.” Hans Oberdiek Swarthmore College David B.Resnik is an Associate Professor of Philosophy and the Director of the Center for the Advancement of Ethics at the University of Wyoming. This is his first book. Philosophical Issues in ScienceEdited by W.H.Newton-Smith Balliol College, Oxford Real HistoryMartin Bunzl Brute ScienceHugh LaFollette and Niall Shanks Living in a Technological CultureMary Tiles and Hans Oberdiek The Rational and the SocialJames Robert Brown The Nature of the DiseaseLawrie Reznek The Philosophical Defence of PsychiatryLawrie Reznek Inference to the Best ExaminationPeter Lipton Time, Space and PhilosophyChristopher Ray Mathematics and the Image of ReasonMary Tiles Evil or Ill?Lawrie Reznek The Ethics of Science: An IntroductionDavid B.Resnik THE ETHICS OF SCIENCE An Introduction David B.Resnik London and New York First published 1998 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005.
    [Show full text]