Nonstandard Analysis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nonstandard Analysis Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis by Bashir Abdel-Fattah [email protected] Abstract The basic idea of nonstandard analysis is to extend the reals to a field that includes "infinite” and "infinitesimal” elements in order to simplify proofs and con- cepts by replacing limits and epsilon-delta proofs by expressions involving infinites- imals. This paper discusses the construction and properties of the hyperreals and some basic results results in differential calculus before moving on to logic and cul- minating in theL´o^sTheorem/transfer principle. The contents are largely based on the papers (Davis, 2009) and (Rayo, 2015), with lesser contributions from (Fletcher et al., 2017), (Claassens, 2016), (Marker, 2010), (Keef and Guichard, 2015), and (Murnaghan, 2015). Also note that this paper assumes little background knowledge outside of analysis (the first section does begin with a brief high-level overview in terms of abstract algebra, but if the reader is unfamiliar with that material they can safely proceed knowing that everything else they need will be introduced throughout the paper). Contents 1 Basics of Nonstandard Analysis3 1.1 Constructing Infinitesimals........................3 1.1.1 Definitions and Properties of Filters...............3 1.1.2 Ultrafilter Construction of the Hyperreals...........6 1.1.3 Properties of the Hyperreals...................9 1.1.4 Enriching Sets and Functions to the Hyperreal Setting.... 12 1.2 Basic Analysis using the Hyperreals................... 13 2 The Transfer Principle 16 2.1 Formal Language and First-Order Logic................ 16 2.2 Basics of Transfer............................. 19 2.2.1 Ultraproducts and Ultrapowers................. 19 2.2.2L´o^s'Theorem ........................... 21 References 25 2 1 Basics of Nonstandard Analysis 1.1 Constructing Infinitesimals Although there are several different schemes of varying degrees of sophistication and utility in rigorously introducing infinite and infinitesimal elements to analysis, in this paper we will focus on the ultrafilter construction developed by Abraham Robinson in the 1960s. Robinson's method, being both one of the oldest nonstandard schemes and relatively straightforward, is well developed in the mathematical literature, and the basic idea of the method is as follows: for any set X and ring R, the set RX of all function f : X ! R is a ring under pointwise addition and multiplication (f + g)(x) = f(x) + g(x)(f · g)(x) = f(x) · g(x) However, even if R is an integral domain or a field, RX won't be an integral domain in general due to the presence of zero divisors. For example, let X be any set and let R be any ring. Then, for any subset S ⊆ X, let χS(x) denote the characteristic function ( 1R if x 2 S χS(x) = 0R if x 62 S Then, letting A and B are two disjoint nonempty subsets of X, neither χA(x) nor χB(x) are uniformly zero, yet (χA · χB)(x) = χA(x) · χB(x) = χA\B(x) = χ;(x) is uniformly zero. In the case of the hyperreals ∗R, our aim is the quotient the ring RN of real-valued sequences by a maximal ideal MAX so that RN=MAX is a field. In a heuristic sense, this amounts to finding an equivalence relation =MAX that declares two sequences hani and hbni equal if the set fn 2 N : an = bng is "too large", so that if hani · hbni = hanbni =MAX h0i, then at least one of hani and hbni contained "enough" zeros to be equivalent to zero to begin with. This scheme of eliminating zero divisors is accomplished with the notion of filters. 1.1.1 Definitions and Properties of Filters We begin with a definition of filters in terms of their properties. For many of the properties below, there are several equivalent definitions, many of which are more general or more sophisticated than those stated here, but we shall proceed with following in the interests of simplicity. Definition 1.1.1. A filter on a set X is a subset F of the power set P(X) satisfying the following properties: 3 1. Proper Filter: ; 62 F 2. Finite Intersection Property: If A; B 2 F, then A \ B 2 F 3. Superset Property: If A 2 F and B ⊃ A, then B 2 F Additionally, F is said to be a ultrafilter if it also satisfies: 4. Maximality: For any A ⊆ X, either A 2 F or X n A 2 F F is further said to be a free ultrafilter if it satisfies: 5. Freeness: F contains no finite subsets of X Note that ultrafilters actually obey a stronger version of the maximality property (of which the above definition is a special case), which we prove below in order to familiarize the reader with the style of reasoning associated with filters: Lemma 1.1.1. Let U be an ultrafilter on a set X, and let fA1;A2;:::;Ang be a finite Sn collection of disjoint subsets of S such that i=1 Ai = X. Then there is exactly one set Aj 2 fA1;A2;:::;Ang such that Aj 2 U. Proof. First, suppose that U contains none of the sets A1;A2;:::An. Then, by the maximality property of ultrafilters, (X n A1); (X n A2);:::; (X n An) 2 U, so by the finite intersection property n n \ [ (X n Am) = X n ( Am) = X n X = ; m=1 m=1 is an element of U. This is a contradiction since U must be a proper filter, so we must have that at least one of the sets A1;A2;:::An is in U. Now suppose that U contains more than one of the sets A1;A2;:::;An. Let Ai and Aj be two distinct sets such that Ai;Aj 2 U. Then, by the intersection property, we have Ai \ Aj = ; 2 U This is also a contradiction, so we must have that U contains at most one of the sets A1;A2;:::;An. Therefore U contains exactly one of the sets A1;A2;:::;An. Examples of filters on a set X include: 1. The trivial filter F = X. 2. The principle filter FA, which is defined in terms of any set A ⊂ X as FA = fY ⊂ X : Y ⊃ Ag In the case that A = fag contains only a single element, then the principle filter Fa is in fact an ultrafilter. 3. The cofinite/Fr´echet filter F co = fY ⊂ X : X n Y is finiteg. Fr´echet filters are non-principal. 4 All of the above examples are relatively simple and uninteresting for our pur- poses, and it turns out that every free ultrafilter is non-principle, and in fact cannot be explicitly constructed. One might then doubt whether any collection of sets that obeys all five of the given properties even exists, but we can prove the existence of free ultrafilters on any infinite set using Zorn's Lemma. We will proceed to that proof in short order, but first we need the following helpful lemma. Lemma 1.1.2. Let F be a filter on a set X, and let A ⊂ X be a set such that A 62 F and (X n A) 62 F. Then F can be extended to a filter F 0 on X containing both F and A. 0 Proof. To begin with, assume F 6= ; (if F = ;, then we can just take F = FA, the principle filter generated by the set A, and the result follows trivially), and consider the collection F 0 = fY 0 ⊂ X : there exists some Y 2 F such that Y 0 ⊃ (Y \ A)g We will now verify that F 0 satisfies each of the properties of a filter in order. 1. Proper Filter: First, note that X 2 F by the superset property (given any Y 2 F, then X ⊃ Y , so X 2 F). This means that A 6= ;, because in the case that A = ; we have (X n A) = X 2 F, which contradicts the hypotheses of the lemma. Furthermore, for any Y 2 F we have Y \ A 6= ;, because if Y \ A = ; then (X n A) ⊃ Y , which implies that (X n A) 2 F by the superset property of F, a contradiction. Therefore, given any Y 0 2 F 0, then there is some Y 2 F such that Y 0 ⊃ (Y \ A) 6= ;, thus Y 0 6= ;. 0 0 0 2. Finite Intersection Property: Suppose Y1 ;Y2 2 F . Then there exist some 0 0 sets Y1;Y2 2 F such that Y1 ⊃ (Y1 \ A) and Y2 ⊃ (Y2 \ A). Since Y1 \ Y2 2 F 0 0 by the finite intersection property of F, then Y1 \ Y2 ⊃ (Y1 \ Y2) \ A is an element of F 0 by definition. 0 0 3. Superset Property: This follows fairly trivially. Suppose Y1 2 F and that 0 0 0 Y2 ⊃ Y1 . Since there exists some Y1 2 F such that Y1 ⊃ (Y1 \ A), in which 0 0 0 case Y2 ⊃ (Y1 \ A) as well, so Y2 2 F by definition. Therefore F 0 is a filter, and we can readily verify that A 2 F 0 and F ⊂ F 0: for any 0 Y 2 F we have that Y; A ⊃ (Y \ A), hence Y; A 2 F by definition. Note that the above lemma also justifies the choice of terminology for that max- imality property: any set that does not obey the maximality property of ultrafilters is not maximal in the sense that there is a strictly larger filter containing it. We will prove in the following theorem that a maximal filter (in the sense that there is no strictly larger filter containing it) obeys the maximality property of ultrafilters, and thus the two notions are equivalent.
Recommended publications
  • An Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis 11
    AN INTRODUCTION TO NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS ISAAC DAVIS Abstract. In this paper we give an introduction to nonstandard analysis, starting with an ultrapower construction of the hyperreals. We then demon- strate how theorems in standard analysis \transfer over" to nonstandard anal- ysis, and how theorems in standard analysis can be proven using theorems in nonstandard analysis. 1. Introduction For many centuries, early mathematicians and physicists would solve problems by considering infinitesimally small pieces of a shape, or movement along a path by an infinitesimal amount. Archimedes derived the formula for the area of a circle by thinking of a circle as a polygon with infinitely many infinitesimal sides [1]. In particular, the construction of calculus was first motivated by this intuitive notion of infinitesimal change. G.W. Leibniz's derivation of calculus made extensive use of “infinitesimal” numbers, which were both nonzero but small enough to add to any real number without changing it noticeably. Although intuitively clear, infinitesi- mals were ultimately rejected as mathematically unsound, and were replaced with the common -δ method of computing limits and derivatives. However, in 1960 Abraham Robinson developed nonstandard analysis, in which the reals are rigor- ously extended to include infinitesimal numbers and infinite numbers; this new extended field is called the field of hyperreal numbers. The goal was to create a system of analysis that was more intuitively appealing than standard analysis but without losing any of the rigor of standard analysis. In this paper, we will explore the construction and various uses of nonstandard analysis. In section 2 we will introduce the notion of an ultrafilter, which will allow us to do a typical ultrapower construction of the hyperreal numbers.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Introduction in a Topological Space, the Closure Is Characterized by the Limits of the Ultrafilters
    Pr´e-Publica¸c˜oes do Departamento de Matem´atica Universidade de Coimbra Preprint Number 08–37 THE ULTRAFILTER CLOSURE IN ZF GONC¸ALO GUTIERRES Abstract: It is well known that, in a topological space, the open sets can be characterized using filter convergence. In ZF (Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without the Axiom of Choice), we cannot replace filters by ultrafilters. It is proven that the ultrafilter convergence determines the open sets for every topological space if and only if the Ultrafilter Theorem holds. More, we can also prove that the Ultrafilter Theorem is equivalent to the fact that uX = kX for every topological space X, where k is the usual Kuratowski Closure operator and u is the Ultrafilter Closure with uX (A) := {x ∈ X : (∃U ultrafilter in X)[U converges to x and A ∈U]}. However, it is possible to built a topological space X for which uX 6= kX , but the open sets are characterized by the ultrafilter convergence. To do so, it is proved that if every set has a free ultrafilter then the Axiom of Countable Choice holds for families of non-empty finite sets. It is also investigated under which set theoretic conditions the equality u = k is true in some subclasses of topological spaces, such as metric spaces, second countable T0-spaces or {R}. Keywords: Ultrafilter Theorem, Ultrafilter Closure. AMS Subject Classification (2000): 03E25, 54A20. 1. Introduction In a topological space, the closure is characterized by the limits of the ultrafilters. Although, in the absence of the Axiom of Choice, this is not a fact anymore.
    [Show full text]
  • Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics
    Found Sci DOI 10.1007/s10699-012-9316-5 Tools, Objects, and Chimeras: Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics Vladimir Kanovei · Mikhail G. Katz · Thomas Mormann © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 Abstract We examine some of Connes’ criticisms of Robinson’s infinitesimals starting in 1995. Connes sought to exploit the Solovay model S as ammunition against non-standard analysis, but the model tends to boomerang, undercutting Connes’ own earlier work in func- tional analysis. Connes described the hyperreals as both a “virtual theory” and a “chimera”, yet acknowledged that his argument relies on the transfer principle. We analyze Connes’ “dart-throwing” thought experiment, but reach an opposite conclusion. In S, all definable sets of reals are Lebesgue measurable, suggesting that Connes views a theory as being “vir- tual” if it is not definable in a suitable model of ZFC. If so, Connes’ claim that a theory of the hyperreals is “virtual” is refuted by the existence of a definable model of the hyperreal field due to Kanovei and Shelah. Free ultrafilters aren’t definable, yet Connes exploited such ultrafilters both in his own earlier work on the classification of factors in the 1970s and 80s, and in Noncommutative Geometry, raising the question whether the latter may not be vulnera- ble to Connes’ criticism of virtuality. We analyze the philosophical underpinnings of Connes’ argument based on Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, and detect an apparent circularity in Connes’ logic. We document the reliance on non-constructive foundational material, and specifically on the Dixmier trace − (featured on the front cover of Connes’ magnum opus) V.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis
    An Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis Jeffrey Zhang Directed Reading Program Fall 2018 December 5, 2018 Motivation • Developing/Understanding Differential and Integral Calculus using infinitely large and small numbers • Provide easier and more intuitive proofs of results in analysis Filters Definition Let I be a nonempty set. A filter on I is a nonempty collection F ⊆ P(I ) of subsets of I such that: • If A; B 2 F , then A \ B 2 F . • If A 2 F and A ⊆ B ⊆ I , then B 2 F . F is proper if ; 2= F . Definition An ultrafilter is a proper filter such that for any A ⊆ I , either A 2 F or Ac 2 F . F i = fA ⊆ I : i 2 Ag is called the principal ultrafilter generated by i. Filters Theorem Any infinite set has a nonprincipal ultrafilter on it. Pf: Zorn's Lemma/Axiom of Choice. The Hyperreals Let RN be the set of all real sequences on N, and let F be a fixed nonprincipal ultrafilter on N. Define an (equivalence) relation on RN as follows: hrni ≡ hsni iff fn 2 N : rn = sng 2 F . One can check that this is indeed an equivalence relation. We denote the equivalence class of a sequence r 2 RN under ≡ by [r]. Then ∗ R = f[r]: r 2 RNg: Also, we define [r] + [s] = [hrn + sni] [r] ∗ [s] = [hrn ∗ sni] The Hyperreals We say [r] = [s] iff fn 2 N : rn = sng 2 F . < is defined similarly. ∗ ∗ A subset A of R can be enlarged to a subset A of R, where ∗ [r] 2 A () fn 2 N : rn 2 Ag 2 F : ∗ ∗ ∗ Likewise, a function f : R ! R can be extended to f : R ! R, where ∗ f ([r]) := [hf (r1); f (r2); :::i] The Hyperreals A hyperreal b is called: • limited iff jbj < n for some n 2 N.
    [Show full text]
  • SELECTIVE ULTRAFILTERS and Ω −→ (Ω) 1. Introduction Ramsey's
    PROCEEDINGS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 127, Number 10, Pages 3067{3071 S 0002-9939(99)04835-2 Article electronically published on April 23, 1999 SELECTIVE ULTRAFILTERS AND ! ( ! ) ! −→ TODD EISWORTH (Communicated by Andreas R. Blass) Abstract. Mathias (Happy families, Ann. Math. Logic. 12 (1977), 59{ 111) proved that, assuming the existence of a Mahlo cardinal, it is consistent that CH holds and every set of reals in L(R)is -Ramsey with respect to every selective ultrafilter . In this paper, we showU that the large cardinal assumption cannot be weakened.U 1. Introduction Ramsey's theorem [5] states that for any n !,iftheset[!]n of n-element sets of natural numbers is partitioned into finitely many∈ pieces, then there is an infinite set H ! such that [H]n is contained in a single piece of the partition. The set H is said⊆ to be homogeneous for the partition. We can attempt to generalize Ramsey's theorem to [!]!, the collection of infinite subsets of the natural numbers. Let ! ( ! ) ! abbreviate the statement \for every [!]! there is an infinite H ! such−→ that either [H]! or [H]! = ." UsingX⊆ the axiom of choice, it is easy⊆ to partition [!]! into two⊆X pieces in such∩X a way∅ that any two infinite subsets of ! differing by a single element lie in different pieces of the partition. Obviously such a partition can admit no infinite homogeneous set. Thus under the axiom of choice, ! ( ! ) ! is false. Having been stymied in this naive−→ attempt at generalization, we have several obvious ways to proceed. A natural project would be to attempt to find classes of partitions of [!]! that do admit infinite homogeneous sets.
    [Show full text]
  • Adequate Ultrafilters of Special Boolean Algebras 347
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 174, December 1972 ADEQUATEULTRAFILTERS OF SPECIAL BOOLEANALGEBRAS BY S. NEGREPONTIS(l) ABSTRACT. In his paper Good ideals in fields of sets Keisler proved, with the aid of the generalized continuum hypothesis, the existence of countably in- complete, /jf^-good ultrafilters on the field of all subsets of a set of (infinite) cardinality ß. Subsequently, Kunen has proved the existence of such ultra- filters, without any special set theoretic assumptions, by making use of the existence of certain families of large oscillation. In the present paper we succeed in carrying over the original arguments of Keisler to certain fields of sets associated with the homogeneous-universal (and more generally with the special) Boolean algebras. More specifically, we prove the existence of countably incomplete, ogood ultrafilters on certain powers of the ohomogeneous-universal Boolean algebras of cardinality cl and on the a-completions of the ohomogeneous-universal Boolean algebras of cardinality a, where a= rc-^ > w. We then develop a method that allows us to deal with the special Boolean algebras of cardinality ct= 2""". Thus, we prove the existence of an ultrafilter p (which will be called adequate) on certain powers S * of the special Boolean algebra S of cardinality a, and the ex- istence of a specializing chain fC«: ß < a\ for oa, such that C snp is /3+- good and countably incomplete for ß < a. The corresponding result on the existence of adequate ultrafilters on certain completions of the special Boolean algebras is more technical. These results do not use any part of the generalized continuum hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • Ultraproducts (Handout April, 2011) G
    Ultraproducts (Handout April, 2011) G. Eric Moorhouse, University of Wyoming Let Mξ ξ∈X be an indexed collection of structures over a common language L. The { } product Π = Qξ∈X Mξ is also a structure over this same language L. Example. Suppose each Mξ is a field. We take for L the language of rings (which serves also as the common language of fields). Thus L has constants 0 and 1, and two binary operations: + and . (Possibly other symbols as well: a unary function × symbol for additive inverses, and a unary function for multiplicative inverses, per- − haps represented by the superscript symbol −1. Let’s not worry about these for now.) Then Π is a structure over the same language L: addition and multiplication are de- fined componentwise. We interpret the symbol 0 in Π as the element having 0 in each component (or more correctly, in component ξ we take the zero element of Mξ, as the interpretation of the symbol 0 may vary from component to component. Similarly 1 is interpreted in Π as the element whose ξ-component is interpreted as the identity element of Mξ. If each Mξ is a field, then it is easily checked that Π = Qξ∈X Mξ is a ring; but not a field for X > 1, since Π has zero divisors. To correct this we need | | ultrafilters. Let U be an ultrafilter on X. Then M = Π/U is also a structure over L; this is known as an ultraproduct of the Mξ’s. Elements of M = Π/U are equivalence classes of Π where two elements x = (xξ )ξ∈X and y = (yξ )ξ∈X in Π are equivalent if ‘almost all’ coordinates agree (relative to U).
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Compactness and Constraint Satisfaction Problems
    Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 13(1:1)2017, pp. 1–11 Submitted Jan. 21, 2016 https://lmcs.episciences.org/ Published Jan. 23, 2017 LOGICAL COMPACTNESS AND CONSTRAINT SATISFACTION PROBLEMS DANNY RORABAUGH a, CLAUDE TARDIF b, AND DAVID WEHLAU c a Department of Mathematics and Statistics, Queen’s University, Kingston, Ontario, Canada b,c Department of Mathematics and Computer Science, Royal Military College of Canada, Kingston, Ontario, Canada Abstract. We investigate a correspondence between the complexity hierarchy of con- straint satisfaction problems and a hierarchy of logical compactness hypotheses for finite relational structures. It seems that the harder a constraint satisfaction problem is, the stronger the corresponding compactness hypothesis is. At the top level, the NP-complete constraint satisfaction problems correspond to compactness hypotheses that are equiva- lent to the ultrafilter axiom in all the cases we have investigated. At the bottom level, the simplest constraint satisfaction problems correspond to compactness hypotheses that are readily provable from the axioms of Zermelo and Fraenkel. 1. Introduction A relational structure A is said to be compact if for any structure B of the same type, B admits a homomorphism to A whenever every finite substructure B′ of B admits a ho- momorphism to A. The compactness theorem of logic implies that every finite structure is compact. However, the compactness theorem is equivalent to the ultrafilter axiom, a consequence of the axiom of choice that is not provable from the axioms of Zermelo and Fraenkel. In this paper, we restrict our attention to the case where A is finite, but we do not assume the ultrafilter axiom.
    [Show full text]
  • Ultrafilters and Tychonoff's Theorem
    Ultrafilters and Tychonoff's Theorem (October, 2015 version) G. Eric Moorhouse, University of Wyoming Tychonoff's Theorem, often cited as one of the cornerstone results in general topol- ogy, states that an arbitrary product of compact topological spaces is compact. In the 1930's, Tychonoff published a proof of this result in the special case of [0; 1]A, also stating that the general case could be proved by similar methods. The first proof in the gen- eral case was published by Cechˇ in 1937. All proofs rely on the Axiom of Choice in one of its equivalent forms (such as Zorn's Lemma or the Well-Ordering Principle). In fact there are several proofs available of the equiv- alence of Tychonoff's Theorem and the Axiom of Choice|from either one we can obtain the other. Here we provide one of the most popular proofs available for Ty- chonoff's Theorem, using ultrafilters. We see this approach as an opportunity to learn also about the larger role of ultra- filters in topology and in the foundations of mathematics, including non-standard analysis. As an appendix, we also include an outline of an alternative proof of Tychonoff's Theorem using a transfinite induction, using the two-factor case X × Y (previously done in class) for the inductive step. This approach is found in the exercises of the Munkres textbook. The proof of existence of nonprincipal ultrafilters was first published by Tarski in 1930; but the concept of ultrafilters is attributed to H. Cartan. 1. Compactness and the Finite Intersection Property Before proceeding, let us recall that a collection of sets S has the finite intersection property if S1 \···\ Sn 6= ? for all S1;:::;Sn 2 S, n > 0.
    [Show full text]
  • NETS There Are a Number of Footnotes, Which Can Safely Be Ignored
    NETS There are a number of footnotes, which can safely be ignored, especially on the first reading. 1. Nets, convergence, continuity Nets are generalization of sequences needed to deal with convergence in general topological spaces, where convergent sequences are not enough to describe the topology. The idea is to replace the set of natural numbers, which is used to index elements of sequences, by arbitrary sets such that it makes sense to talk about \large" elements. Recall that a partial order on a set I is a binary relation ≺ such that (a) i ≺ i; (b) if i ≺ j and j ≺ i; then i = j; (c) if i ≺ j and j ≺ k; then i ≺ k: Definition 1.1. A set I with a partial order1 ≺ is called directed if for any i; j 2 I there exists k 2 I such that i ≺ k and j ≺ k. The following example will be our main source of directed sets. Example 1.2. Let X be a set and I be a collection of subsets of X closed under finite intersections, so if A; B 2 I then A \ B 2 I. Define a partial order on I by A ≺ B iff B ⊂ A: Then I is a directed set: for any A; B 2 I, we have A ≺ A \ B and B ≺ A \ B. Definition 1.3. A net in a set X is a collection (xi)i2I of elements of X indexed by a nonempty directed set I, or in other words, it is a map I ! X. Definition 1.4.
    [Show full text]
  • Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices Managing Editor
    Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices Managing Editor: M. HAZEWINKEL Centre for Mathematics and Computer Science, Amsterdam, The Netherlands Volume 525 Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices Edited by S.S. Kutateladze Sobolev Institute of Mathematics. Siberian Division of the Russian Academy of Sciences. Novosibirsk. Russia SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS MEDIA, B. V. A C.LP. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 978-94-010-5863-6 ISBN 978-94-011-4305-9 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-94-011-4305-9 This is an updated translation of the original Russian work. Nonstandard Analysis and Vector Lattices, A.E. Gutman, \'E.Yu. Emelyanov, A.G. Kusraev and S.S. Kutateladze. Novosibirsk, Sobolev Institute Press, 1999. The book was typeset using AMS-TeX. Printed an acid-free paper AII Rights Reserved ©2000 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht Originally published by Kluwer Academic Publishers in 2000 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner. Contents Foreword ix Chapter 1. Nonstandard Methods and Kantorovich Spaces (A. G. Kusraev and S. S. Kutateladze) 1 § 1.l. Zermelo-Fraenkel Set·Theory 5 § l.2. Boolean Valued Set Theory 7 § l.3. Internal and External Set Theories 12 § 1.4. Relative Internal Set Theory 18 § l.5. Kantorovich Spaces 23 § l.6. Reals Inside Boolean Valued Models 26 § l.7. Functional Calculus in Kantorovich Spaces 30 § l.8.
    [Show full text]
  • Infinitesimal Methods in Mathematical Economics
    Infinitesimal Methods in Mathematical Economics Robert M. Anderson1 Department of Economics and Department of Mathematics University of California at Berkeley Berkeley, CA 94720, U.S.A. and Department of Economics Johns Hopkins University Baltimore, MD 21218, U.S.A. January 20, 2008 1The author is grateful to Marc Bettz¨uge, Don Brown, Hung- Wen Chang, G´erard Debreu, Eddie Dekel-Tabak, Greg Engl, Dmitri Ivanov, Jerry Keisler, Peter Loeb, Paul MacMillan, Mike Magill, Andreu Mas-Colell, Max Stinchcombe, Cathy Wein- berger and Bill Zame for their helpful comments. Financial sup- port from Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft, Gottfried-Wilhelm- Leibniz-F¨orderpreis is gratefully acknowledged. Contents 0Preface v 1 Nonstandard Analysis Lite 1 1.1 When is Nonstandard Analysis Useful? . 1 1.1.1 Large Economies . 2 1.1.2 Continuum of Random Variables . 4 1.1.3 Searching For Elementary Proofs . 4 1.2IdealElements................. 5 1.3Ultraproducts.................. 6 1.4InternalandExternalSets........... 9 1.5NotationalConventions............. 11 1.6StandardModels................ 12 1.7 Superstructure Embeddings . 14 1.8AFormalLanguage............... 16 1.9TransferPrinciple................ 16 1.10Saturation.................... 18 1.11InternalDefinitionPrinciple.......... 19 1.12 Nonstandard Extensions, or Enough Already with the Ultraproducts . 20 1.13HyperfiniteSets................. 21 1.14 Nonstandard Theorems Have Standard Proofs 22 2 Nonstandard Analysis Regular 23 2.1 Warning: Do Not Read this Chapter . 23 i ii CONTENTS 2.2AFormalLanguage............... 23 2.3 Extensions of L ................. 25 2.4 Assigning Truth Value to Formulas . 28 2.5 Interpreting Formulas in Superstructure Em- beddings..................... 32 2.6TransferPrinciple................ 33 2.7InternalDefinitionPrinciple.......... 34 2.8NonstandardExtensions............ 35 2.9TheExternalLanguage............. 36 2.10TheConservationPrinciple.......... 37 3RealAnalysis 39 3.1Monads..................... 39 3.2OpenandClosedSets............. 44 3.3Compactness.................
    [Show full text]