In This Lecture We Discuss the Concept of Dualism in Descartes Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

In This Lecture We Discuss the Concept of Dualism in Descartes Philosophy Lecture 7-8 Descartes Philosophy of Mind About the Lecture: In this lecture we discuss the concept of dualism in Descartes philosophy. Rene Descartes scientific inquiry about the nature of substance and foundation of epistemology show that the mind and the body are two substances and ‘thinking’ or the cogito (I think) which is essentially the characteristics of the mental substance is the founding principle of all epistemological discourses. Keywords: Substance Dualism, Mind-Body Problem, Substance, Cogito, Understanding, Res cogitans, Res extensa Descartes formulated the mechanistic explanation of the phenomena of nature by introducing the hypothetical model. For him, hypothesis needs to be formulated to explain the imperceptible causal properties of the perceptible body. The causal properties of the matter include both the material and the sufficient causes. And the combination of the imperceptible particles together would be able to constitute the perceptible body. The imperceptible particles are the micro states of matter and the perceptible particles are the macro states of matter, which could be explained through the basic properties called shape, size, and motion. And the formulation of mechanistic hypothesis for the explanation of natural phenomena is to bridge the gap between our sensory experiences of matter and their causal capacity. As Clarke mentions, “The distinction between our subjective experiences or sensations and their objective causes, between primary and secondary qualities, opens up an epistemic gap that can only be bridged by some other strategy apart from the assumption of resemblance. This strategy is hypothesis, or guesswork. Our guesswork may turn out to be secure and there may eventually be many reasons for thinking that they are as certain as one can hope for ….”1 Secondary qualities are mostly subjective in their appearances whereas primary qualities are objective. Here the primary qualities of the matter are the basic properties of it, such as its shape, size and motion through which matter can be explained. 1 Desmond M. Clarke, “Descartes Philosophy of Science and the Scientific Revolution,” Cambridge Companion to Descartes, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p.261. (Henceforth, CCD) 1 Now one may ask, how do we have the ideas of these imperceptible properties of matter? Descartes elaborates it in his famous example of wax. Wax in its original state (fresh from the hive) possesses qualities such as sweetness, fragrance of honey, colour, size, etc. If the same piece of wax is heated, then its size expands, its sweetness disappears, and the colour changes. That is, a certain transformation takes place between the time period before heating and after heating. However, we still have the common notion of wax. And during the course of transformation, we know that heat operates in the composite structure of the wax. We don’t perceive the movement of the minute parts of the wax during the period of transformation. Still the conception of wax remains because some essential qualities persist and they help us in identifying the wax as wax after its transformation. For Descartes, this notion of wax could be comprehended neither by perception nor by imagination that physics deals with. Rather, the comprehension of this idea is possible by understanding. Understanding deals with “pure intellect”. As Wood describes, “After the exclusion of sensation and imagination there remains one possibility, namely, that understanding, exercising its powers of conception and judgment for the synthesizing and unifying function which constitutes the self identity of the piece of wax.”2 Understanding is a special mode for formulating such ideas as ascribed to the function of the intellect. The intellect has a unique way of judging the observable facts. It is through its intellect alone that material bodies are comprehended. Descartes’ philosophy of mind emerges from his reflections on nature as a mechanistic system. He locates the beginning of this philosophy in our subjective experiences. As Clarke cites, “where the metaphysics is concerned, we begin with such everyday experiences as the experience of thinking, feeling, moving, etc. Among these experiences, Descartes favors the most accessible and widely available experiences because he hopes thereby to find indubitable foundation.” 3 Among these experiences thinking is considered as the most indubitable and simply accessible feature of our knowledge. Thinking or cogito is easily comprehensible, because it is directly accessible to me – the self. Descartes does not conceptualize the notion of self as representation to itself, rather is a self-evident truth. It is perceived by inner sense of the mind. The perception of the mind is also known as introspection which provides certainty to the 2 Ledger Wood, “Descartes Philosophy of Mind”, Philosophical Review, Vol.XLI, (41) No.5, 1932 p475 3 Clarke, op.cit., p.272. 2 existence of the self. Thus the knowledge of the existence of the self is an indubitable truth. The self evident nature of the experience of this indubitable truth about the existence of the self puts an end to Descartes search for the foundation of knowledge. This is indubitable because doubting presupposes thinking. From doubting we cannot obtain certainty. And, Descartes used doubting as a kind of method to establish truth. Thinking is a conscious activity. To say that I think is to claim that I am conscious of this very activity called thinking. Thus thinking is a self-conscious activity. It is an immediate knowledge to me that I am thinking. It is different from bodily activities. The bodily activities are performed with the self being conscious of them. Consciousness includes all mental activities, like thoughts, sensations, imaginations, and experiences. Hence, the mind exists as an independent substance – res cogitans. “The certainty of my own existence obtains only when I am thinking, when I am conscious, I am, I exist, that is certain.” (Copleston, 1994: 91) The Cartesian metaphysics is based on the principle of cogito (I think) which is most indubitable and certain. As Descartes claims, “I am nothing so long as I think that I am something. So after considering everything very thoroughly, I must finally conclude that proposition, I am, I exist, is necessarily true whenever it is put forward by me and conceived in my mind.”4 Thus thinking or cogito lays down the foundation for any sort of knowledge claims, including the mechanistic explanation of the universe. Consciousness is the basic metaphysical reality in Descartes’ philosophy. For him, the very nature of understanding consciousness is different from the understanding of the nature of the body. The body or matter is usually defined as something extended in space that can be perceived, and also has movement in connection with other bodies. It is different from the mind which is neither perceived no is extended in space. Descartes says, “For according to my judgement, power of self-movement, like the power of sensation or of thought was quite foreign to the nature of the body; indeed it was a source of wonder to me that certain bodies were found to contain faculties of this nature.”5 The self-movement describes the independent function of consciousness. It is not dependent upon the other mechanical functions of the body. Thereby 4 Rene Descartes, Second Meditation, “The Nature of Human Mind is better known than the Body”, Meditations on First Philosophy, trns. John Cottingham, CUP, Cambridge, 1986 pp.17-18. 5 Ibid., p.18 3 consciousness is characterized as a unique feature of human organism. The human organism is not just sensitive to the external world nature but also intelligent enough to think and describe it. Descartes’ metaphysics of mind goes beyond the boundaries of physics and physiology. It situates the mind beyond the finites of mechanism. The physiological structures of a living body, especially of human beings are organized in a certain way so that they bear certain mechanical functions. These functions include digestion, blood circulation and palpitation of the heart, various movements of limbs, etc. Beyond the functions the conscious behaviour of the body is described by the presence of the soul in the living organism. The soul is placed in the small gland in the middle of the brain. The brain is taken as the vital part of the body connected with all other parts of the body through the nerve fibers to carry out the sensations. It is the pineal gland that converts the blood into animal spirits. The sprits are kept in the cavities and further they enter into the muscles through the nerve fibers. The flow of spirits varies depending upon the impressions that are carried to the soul. Descartes also says, “And conversely, the mechanism of the body is so constructed that simply by this gland’s being moved in any way by the soul or by any other cause, it drives the surrounding spirits towards the pores of the brain, which direct them through the nerves of the muscles; and in this way the gland makes the spirit move the limbs.”6 This mechanical composition of the body no doubt has a certain biological capacity to generate the movement. All these movements of the body are not derived from the soul and do not have any necessary relationship with consciousness. The heat generated by the natural composition of the body, for instance, is unique to the function of the body. Descartes says, “it has been believed, without justification, that our natural heat and all the movements of our bodies depend on the soul; whereas we ought to hold, on the contrary, that the soul takes its leave when we die only because the heat ceases and the organs which bring about bodily movement decay.” 7 The decomposition of the physiological feature of the body is a natural phenomenon in biology. The body is unable to generate heat or other physiological functions like digestion, palpitation, etc.
Recommended publications
  • From Locke to Berkeley
    From Locke to Berkeley How Berkeley rejects Locke’s Metaphysical Realism in favor of what he calls “Idealism” Locke Summary Like Descartes, Locke believes that we perceive the “real” world only indirectly. • We do not directly perceive material objects, – Just as we do not directly perceive people we see on T.V.; • Rather, we directly perceive only ideas (sensations, things “in” our minds) that are caused by and represent material objects, – Just as, when watching T.V., we directly see only images on the screen. Locke’s Causal Theory of Perception: Indirectly Sensation aware of Matter Do our sensations resemble their objects? • Recall that Descartes’ big worry was whether or not there were any objects outside our minds. – (By the end of the 6th Meditation, he assures that there are.) • But he said we also make mistakes in thinking that our ideas always resembled the objects in the real world that caused us to have those sensations. Why should we believe that the ideas in our minds actually resemble the objects outside our minds that cause them? Mind’s Eye Idea Object Idea Object Mind In Locke’s Terms • Even if we accept that the ideas in our mind are caused by real objects that exist outside our minds – (Locke never really questions this) • Is it true that our ideas always resemble the qualities in the objects that caused us to have those ideas? Locke’s Answer • Only sometimes. Some of our ideas do resemble qualities in the objects, but some of them do not. • Our ideas of primary qualities resemble those qualities.
    [Show full text]
  • Research Note Bourdieu and Leibniz: Mediated Dualisms
    Research Note Bourdieu and Leibniz: Mediated Dualisms Abstract The research note discusses similarities in theory construction between Bourdieu and Leibniz. Instead of ‘overcoming’ the Cartesian dualisms, both authors find a way to mediate between the dualistic concepts by introducing a third concept. In Leibniz’ case, this is God, in Bourdieu’s case, history. Reading Bourdieu thus from a Leibnizian angle, the note seeks to clarify some issues in Bourdieu’s theory construction. Keywords: Bourdieu, Descartes, dualisms, Leibniz Author : Elke Weik University of Leicester School of Management Leicester LE1 7RH UK phone: 0044-116-252 5318 email: [email protected] 1 The present research note wants to show linkages and similarities in theory construction between Bourdieu and the 17th century philosopher Leibniz. The aim is to explore to which extent Bourdieu (most explicitly stated in Bourdieu, 1980/1990, Bourdieu and Wacquant, 1996) overcomes the traditional dualisms formed by Cartesian philosophy: subjective-objective, mind-body as well as the subsequently developed dichotomy of structure and agency1. Among the many concepts Bourdieu introduces for that purpose, I should like to focus on the special relationship of two: the habitus and the field. The habitus is Bourdieu’s major concept to portray how institutions, conventions and other practices influence and shape the individual human being with regard to its body, preferences, attitudes, etc. Through socialisation and biography, the habitus attains a historical dimension. Its hysteresis guarantees a certain stability as it retains the habitus malleable but only ‘reluctantly” and in a slow process of re-socialisation (Bourdieu and Wacquant, 1996). The field, on the other hand, is the dynamic situation actors live in.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes' Arguments for Distinguishing Mind and Body
    © Michael Lacewing Descartes’ arguments for distinguishing mind and body THE KNOWLEDGE ARGUMENT In Meditation II, having argued that he knows he thinks, Descartes then asks what kind of thing he is. Discussions of identity seek to establish the essential properties of something, what makes it the thing that it is. The question ‘what am I?’ can be answered by considering the question of what it is for me to exist. Descartes is trying to identify his essence, those properties which, if he lost them, would mean he was no longer what he is. (An island, for instance, must be surrounded by water. If the water dried up, joining it to the mainland, it would cease to be an island.) He remarks that he can continue to doubt whether he has a body; after all, he only believes he has a body as a result of his perceptual experiences, and so the demon could be deceiving him about this. But he cannot doubt that he has a mind, i.e. that he thinks. So he knows he exists even though he doesn’t know whether or not he has a body. From this Descartes concludes that it is possible for him to exist without a body. He is essentially a mind, not a body. He would not necessarily cease to be himself if he ceased to have a body, but he would necessarily cease to be himself if he didn’t have a mind. APPEAL TO GOD’S OMNIPOTENCE Descartes’ argument so far is that minds can exist without bodies. However, on its own, it doesn’t establish dualism.
    [Show full text]
  • René Descartes' Philosophy As a Forming
    WORLD SCIENCE ISSN 2413-1032 PHILOSOPHY RENÉ DESCARTES’ PHILOSOPHY AS A FORMING ELEMENT OF GREGORY SKOVORODA’S WORLD- VIEW INTUITION Shuvalov V. S. Ukraine, Ternopil, Ternopil Higher Theology Seminary DOI: https://doi.org/10.31435/rsglobal_ws/30042020/7035 ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Received: 17 February 2020 Skovoroda’s philosophy is considered through the prism of philosophical Accepted: 20 April 2020 ideas and features of the scientific discourse presented by the modern Published: 30 April 2020 philosophers, in particular René Descartes. Special attention is paid to the similarity of these philosophers’ views, who focus their attention of the KEYWORDS method of self-cognition. However, Descartes engages in the gnosiological Descartes, aspect and pays attention to the process of cognition and on the correctness Skovoroda, of conclusions. Whereas Skovoroda is concentrated on ontology or even on self-cognition, metaphysics speaking not so much about the process of cognition, but about intuition, the essence of existence. Besides this it is important that both thinkers have Cogito. the same world-view intuition, in particular Skovoroda, akin to Descartes, considers God to be the only source of final and absolute truth. Citation: Shuvalov V. S. (2020) René Descartes’ Philosophy as a Forming Element of Gregory Skovoroda’s World-View Intuition. World Science. 4(56), Vol.2. doi: 10.31435/rsglobal_ws/30042020/7035 Copyright: © 2020 Shuvalov V. S. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Transparency of Mind: the Contributions of Descartes, Leibniz, and Berkeley to the Genesis of the Modern Subject
    Transparency of Mind: The Contributions of Descartes, Leibniz, and Berkeley to the Genesis of the Modern Subject Gary Hat! eld Philosophers often use classical positions as paradigms for de! ning their own views, usually in contrast. In the philosophy of mind, the notion of the Cartesian subject is one such paradigm. This notion is often used to represent tendencies in the conception of the subject that today’s philosophers wish to avoid. John McDowell and Hilary Putnam 1, among others, portray the Cartesian subject – and speci! cally the Cartesian mind – as a step backward from an earlier, preferable Aristotelianism, whose concept of mind might be made serviceable today if adjusted to ! t modern science. Such paradigms, whose use is unavoidable, are typically caricatures, whether slight or gross. The Cartesian mind as standardly portrayed by McDowell, Putnam, and oth- ers 2 is a gross caricature. This would be important enough for its potential to mislead us about the actual historical development of philosophy. But even more crucially for the philosophy of mind, the use of a caricatured picture as a counterparadigm against which one de! nes one’s own, comparatively better position, can lead to a pyrrhic vic- tory that avoids or misrepresents the real problems. If the opponent has been tailored to one’s desired virtues as conquering hero, one may give the impression that one’s own position solves great problems, deeply embedded in the tradition, when in fact one has simply rejected a fairly recent problematic position, which one has perhaps also misun- derstood and misidenti! ed. 3 The Cartesian mental paradigm is frequently de! ned in terms of four factors: con- sciousness as essence, intentionality as exclusively mental, the veil of perception, and the transparency of mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Richard Swinburne's Arguments for Substance Dualism
    Richard Swinburne’s arguments for substance dualism. MA by Research in Theology and Religion David Horner September 2018 Richard Swinburne’s arguments for substance dualism. Submitted by David Horner to the University of Exeter as a dissertation for the degree of MA by Research in Theology and Religion in September 2018 This dissertation is available for Library use on the understanding that it is copyright material and that no quotation from the dissertation may be published without proper acknowledgement. I certify that all material in this dissertation which is not my own work has been identified and that no material has previously been submitted and approved for the award of a degree by this or any other University. 1 Acknowledgements. I would like to thank my supervisors, Dr Jonathan Hill and Dr Joel Krueger for their support and encouragement in the writing of this dissertation and for their patience in trying to keep me on the straight and narrow. I want to acknowledge the many conversations, on this and other topics, I have had with my friend and philosopher, Dr Chris Boyne, who sadly died in June of this year. I thank all my other chums at The Bull, Ditchling, for listening to my metaphysical ramblings. And finally, I thank my wife, Linda, for once more putting up with this kind of thing. 2 Abstract This dissertation is a contribution to debates in the philosophy of mind and of personal identity. It presents a critical account of arguments for substance dualism to be found in Richard Swinburne’s Mind, Brain, and Free Will (2013).
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to the Philosophy of Cognitive Science by Dr
    Introduction to the Philosophy of Cognitive Science By Dr. Charles Wallis Last revision: 1/23/2013 Chapter 2 Greek Metaphysical Speculation: Philosophical Materialisms and Dualisms 2.1 Introduction It may seem odd to the contemporary thinker to suppose that people did not always have a clear conception of the mind and of mental phenomena. Nevertheless, like most contemporary western concepts the development of the notion of the mind and of mental phenomena actually occurs over the course of centuries. Indeed, the development of the notion of “the mind” arguably traces back to the development of the Greek notion of the soul. For most of Greek history the conception of the soul bears little resemblance to its contemporary western counterpart. In fact, the Greeks develop their notion of the soul as part of the development of general ontological frameworks for scientific and metaphysical speculation. Three features of the development of the Greek notion of the soul figure prominently in this rather superficial history. First, the development of the Greek notion of the soul represents a slow accretion of properties and processes associated with three different contemporary distinctions into a single ontological entity; living vs non-living, animate vs inanimate, and mental vs non-mental. Second, as the soul becomes more distinct both in its nature and in its functions, the Greeks begin to more actively debate whether the soul constitutes a fundamental kind of stuff (a distinct substance) or merely one of many permutations of more fundamental kinds of stuff (substances). For instance, early Greek thinkers often supposed that the universe consists of various permutations of one or more fundamental elements.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical Roots of the Ecological Crisis
    The Philosophical Roots of the Ecological Crisis The Philosophical Roots of the Ecological Crisis: Descartes and the Modern Worldview By Joshtrom Isaac Kureethadam The Philosophical Roots of the Ecological Crisis: Descartes and the Modern Worldview By Joshtrom Isaac Kureethadam This book first published 2017 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2017 by Joshtrom Isaac Kureethadam All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-0343-7 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-0343-4 The time is coming when the struggle for dominion over the earth will be carried on. It will be carried on in the name of fundamental philosophical doctrines. —Friedrich Nietzsche We cannot solve a problem with the same mind-set that created it in the first place. —Albert Einstein CONTENTS Preface ......................................................................................................... x Abbreviations ............................................................................................ xii Acknowledgements .................................................................................. xiii Introduction ................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Two Varieties of Skepticism
    1 2 3 4 Two Varieties of Skepticism 5 6 James Conant 7 8 This paper distinguishes two varieties of skepticism and the varieties of 9 philosophical response those skepticisms have engendered. The aim of 10 the exercise is to furnish a perspicuous overview of some of the dialec- 11 tical relations that obtain across some of the range of problems that phi- 12 losophers have called (and continue to call) “skeptical”. I will argue that 13 such an overview affords a number of forms of philosophical insight.1 14 15 16 I. Cartesian and Kantian Varieties of Skepticism – A First Pass 17 at the Distinction 18 19 I will call the two varieties of skepticism in question Cartesian skepticism 20 and Kantian skepticism respectively.2 (These labels are admittedly conten- 21 tious.3 Nothing of substance hangs on my employing these rather than 22 23 1 The taxonomy is meant to serve as a descriptive tool for distinguishing various 24 sorts of philosophical standpoint. It is constructed in as philosophically neutral a 25 fashion as possible. The distinctions presented below upon which it rests are 26 ones that can be deployed by philosophers of very different persuasions regard- 27 less of their collateral philosophical commitments. A philosopher could make use of these distinctions to argue for any of a number of very different conclu- 28 sions. Some of the more specific philosophical claims that I myself express sym- 29 pathy for in the latter part of this part (e.g., regarding how these varieties of 30 skepticism are related to one another) do, however, turn on collateral philo- 31 sophical commitments.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza on Extension Physical Not Mere Extension in Space, for Spinoza, but It Is Not Part of the Essence of Something Physical to Be Extended in Space at All
    Philosophers’ volume 15, no. 14 §1 Introduction1 Imprint april 2015 Spinoza indicates in the Ethics that there is at least one “extended thing (res extensa)”, which is God, or nature (e. g., EIIp2), and that there are bodies, which are “modes of Extension (modi Extensionis)” (e. g., EIIp7). This is very naturally taken to mean that there are things — substances, modes, or both — that are extended in three dimensions, or that take up space. In this paper, however, I argue that this is not what Spinoza means. When Spinoza discusses the attribute of extension, he does not mean dimensionality, and by “an extended thing” he does not mean to describe something that takes up space. Not only is the essence of the Spinoza on Extension physical not mere extension in space, for Spinoza, but it is not part of the essence of something physical to be extended in space at all. The argument proceeds in two parts. First, in §2, I argue that when Spinoza writes that God, corporeal substance, or nature is “an Extended thing”, he does not mean that this substance is extended in length, breadth and depth. In other words, substance is neither space nor something that takes up space. I argue for this by showing that Spinoza allows that substance can be characterized by a certain conception of quantity, contrasts that with another conception of quantity that cannot be attributed to substance, and associates three-dimensional extension with the second kind of quantity, and not the first. I go on in §3 to make the more controversial case that finite Alison Peterman bodies, or modes of the “extended” substance, are also not properly University of Rochester 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein, Gadamer and Bernstein
    Eight HERMENEUTICS, PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY AND THE ONTOLOGY OF COMMUNITY: WITTGENSTEIN, GADAMER AND BERNSTEIN Núria Sara Miras Boronat 1. Introduction. How Modern Philosophy Became a House of Horrors A spectre has been haunting Modern European thought: the Spectre of “Cartesian Anxiety”. This spectre has multiple faces and reappears in unsuspected forms, often thought to have been left behind. Yet in all its disguises, Cartesian anxiety has always had the same effect. It paralyses philosophers, it blocks their creative resources and even the bravest of them feel imprisoned in their own philosophical system much like a frightened child would feel in a house of horrors. As Bernstein has pointed out, it was Descartes himself in Meditations who described the horrible emotions that accompanied his philosophical journey. There is a myriad of criticisms of Descartes’s strategy to seek the ultimate foundations of certainty. I think most critics would agree with Bernstein’s diagnosis that Cartesian anxiety is caused by the profound conviction held by modern philosophers that their main task must be “the search for an Archimedean point upon which we can ground our knowledge.”1 In my opinion, Bernstein offers us the most exquisite and precise description of this pathology: The terrifying quality of the journey is reflected in the allusions to madness, darkness, the dread of waking from a self-deceptive dream world, the fear of having “all of a sudden fallen into very deep water” where “I can neither make certain of setting my feet on the bottom, nor can I swim and so support myself on the surface”, and the anxiety of imagining that I may be nothing more than a plaything of an all- powerful evil demon.2 The diagnosis and therapy against the issues caused by modern epistemology can be found in what I consider to be Bernstein’s masterpiece, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism (1983).
    [Show full text]
  • Swinburne on Substance Dualism
    SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCE DUALISM LYNNE RUDDER BAKER University of Massachusetts Amherst Richard Swinburne’s Mind, Brain and Free Will is a tour de force. Beginning with basic ontology, Swinburne formulates careful definitions that support his mature philosophy. He is well-known for his views on free will and substance dualism. In Mind, Brain and Free Will, he revisits these issues among others, because he now has ‘deeper and stronger’ arguments for his position. Here I want to discuss substance dualism. The first sentence of the book says that its focus is ‘the nature of human beings – whether we are merely complicated machines or souls interacting with bodies’1 (Swinburne 2013: 1). Since I do not believe that this dichotomy is exhaustive, I shall first examine Swinburne’s argument for the claim that human beings are ‘souls interacting with bodies’, which he interprets as substance dualism. Then, I shall offer a sketch of a different view – my own – which is materialistic in the sense that it makes reference neither to any immaterial concrete objects nor to any immaterial properties (whatever that might mean). I do not say that my materialistic view is a complete metaphysics, inasmuch as that it pertains only to the natural world. I leave it open whether there is a supernatural world. Since I am going to offer an alternative to Swinburne’s substance dualism, let me begin by enumerating ways in which I am in full agreement with him. I fully agree with Swinburne that it is not the case that ‘mental events are merely brain events’, and it is not the case that ‘I am the same thing as my body’ (Baker 1995; Baker 2000).
    [Show full text]