Prolegomena to the Root of Form and the Possibility of Meaning

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Prolegomena to the Root of Form and the Possibility of Meaning PROLEGOMENA TO THE ROOT OF FORM AND THE POSSIBILITY OF 1 MEANING Francis Field PROLEGOMENA TO THE ROOT OF FORM AND THE POSSIBILITY OF MEANING 2013 Francis Field Word Count 11,759 List of Illustrations: Contents fig. 1 Pythagorean Cosmic Morphology? - www. http://missionignition.net/bethe/rings_of_gaia.php fig. 2 The Roundest Sphere in the World -http://www.australiaunlimited.com/science/sphere-eternity fig. 3 A Grammar for the City - Kung, Moritz. (2010). Office Kersten Geers David Van Severen: Seven Rooms, Hatje Cantz; 2 edition 1. Introduction fig. 4 Kartal Pendik Master Plan - http://www.zaha-hadid.com/masterplans/kartal-pendik-masterplan/ fig. 5 Friedrich Theodor Vischer -http://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/e/ed/Vischer.jpg 4. The Origin of Form fig. 6 Mirror Neurones -http://www.pc.rhul.ac.uk/staff/j.zanker/teach/ps2080/l4/ps2080_4.htm fig. 7 The Parthenon - Hitching, Francis. (1980). The World Atlas of Msteries, Book Club Assosiates 14. The Emergence of Form in Architecture fig. 8 Rachel Whiteread - http://farm3.staticflickr.com/2580/4183984903_e1088fc5ff_o.jpg 32. The Meaning of Form fig. 9 I am a Vortex. -http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Vortex fig. 10 George Spencer-Brown - Spencer-Brown, G. (2011). Laws of Form, Spencer-Brown Press 56. Conclusion fig. 11 Black board - http://thisrecording.com/storage/wittgenstein1-big.jpg?__SQUARESPACE_ CACHEVERSION=1316126889850 62. Bibliography fig. 12 A distinction. - Spencer-Brown, G. (2011). Laws of Form, Spencer-Brown Press fig. 13 Oroboros - http://www.stephenlinsteadtstudio.com/Images/ouroborus/Ouroboros.png 65. Appendix fig. 14 Perpetual Motion - Sculpture and Photograph by the author. 2008 fig 15 A part of the foundations of the theatre of Marcellus. - Ficcaci, L. (2000). Piranesi - The Complete Works, Taschen Inside front and back cover - Reliquiae Theatri Pompejani, photographs by the author. The present work was prompted by my infuriation at not being able to talk directly of form without it being confused or misinterpreted as gratuitous formalism. It is very hard to talk about form without the conversation collapsing into matters of programme or function. In most cases my attempts were met with blank looks, though I admit this was a least partly my fault due to my inability to fully articulate the matter. Form is not shape, let us first make this clear - we have the word ‘shape’ to describe shape. Most people seem to be completely comfortable talking about the form of a particular object, or the more general form of, say for example, cities - but are incapable of talking between the two. It seems clear to me that we have an innate understanding of the universal and the particular that we draw on unconsciously, but rarely do we pause to consider 1 Introduction the nature of their relationship in form. The problem of form is that it encapsulates both of these concepts simultaneously in one neat package: 'Form', we can not help but use it all of the time and do so without sufficient recourse to its meaning. This is because it is difficult. The architectural historian Adrian Forty describes it as “the most important, but also the most difficult concept within the architecture of this century.”1 Form, like space is always at the centre of any architectural question but woe betide us if we know what either of those most essential terms actually mean. Despite this we seem content to recklessly describe forms as flowing, emergent, responsive, formal, pure, platonic, symbolic or even spatial, without pausing for a moment to think through the implication (usually contradictory) of the language we use so flippantly. Compounding the issue is the distinct lack of contemporary in active development, and with little curiosity as to what literature on the subject of form. That which purports to be, purposes it may serve.”3 lacks direct critical engagement because it generally fails to define what form actually is and remains dancing inanely Of course he is completely right, having summed up around the great precipice of meaning. Some appeal to exactly what I had observed in practice I could not agree formalism in one way or another to avoid confusion, but more. Though, now having witnessed the death of a term formalism being another complex term tends to present so central to my discipline I could not help but feel a sense its own problems: best understood by what it excludes, of indignation. It is all very well to analyse and dissect, i.e. considerations perceived as beyond and outside of a indeed architecture without its critical faculty is no more particular object, it tends to deny the possibility of meaning. than building, but being a practical, constructive art-form I Peter Eisenman takes this position although still seems felt it was equally possible that something could be made incapable of escaping the metaphysical implications of his from the worthless husk left to me by Forty. If I could just own theory. Pier Vittorio Aureli has written widely on the define what form is, and space too since it seems to be co- politics of form in the city and has a better understanding incident, I would at least have the raw materials required than most in the contradictions inherent in its use, though for my practice. The most essential components of every 2 3 he too is forced into using the term ‘formal’ to avoid any thing, how could I work in their medium without at least exact definition.2 a basic understanding of what they are? And once I have found out what they are I can tell you what they mean: what The most insightful and important critical evaluation of architecture means. form I have found is Forty’s entry on ‘form’ in his recently published book ‘Words and Buildings’. He guides us though a history of form in architecture through terse commentary. Taking form from the ancient Greeks, it is dragged all the way through to modernism, but not before having been poked, probed and mauled over the preceding pages. Form is laid bare and found to be wanting, no longer suitable for use in architecture we are left to pick up the pieces. The final nails are drawn in his closing remarks: “In a sense, ‘form’ is a concept that has outlived its 1. Forty, Adrian. (2004). Words and Buildings: A Vocabulary of Modern Architecture, Thames & usefulness. People talk of form all the time but they rarely Hudson. 149 talk about it; as a term it has become frozen, no longer 2. Aureli, P.V. (2011). The Possibility of an Absolute Architecture, MIT Press. 30 3. Forty. 2004. 172 “The Latin forma stands for two Greek words with quite different meanings: eidos, or abstract form, and morphe, or visible form. In its very origin the word form seems to contain the dispute between those who give priority to the visibility of things as a fundamental datum of experience and those who give priority to the inner structure of experience itself as the factor that determines how visible things are.”1 According to Adrian Forty “The principle originator of the concept of ‘form’ in antiquity was Plato...Against Pythagoras’s earlier theory that all things could in essence be described as numbers or ratios of numbers, Plato proposed that geometrical figures, triangles and solids underlay the world.”2 This is not strictly true: Plato may have become the namesake of the Platonic forms, but the origin of these 4 5 The Origin of Form five geometric solids has been attributed to various Greek philosophers, conceptually too his use of form is by no means his own. Forty is right in asserting that Plato’s theory is based in Pythagorianism but the credit given does not go far enough. The concept of the supra sensory world constituted of geometrical forms belongs solely to the great mystic and mathematician Pythagoras. Bertrand Russell explains: “He thought of numbers as shapes, as they appear as dice or playing cards. We still speak of squares and cube numbers that are terms we owe to him. He also spoke of oblong numbers, triangular numbers, pyramidal numbers, and so on. These were the numbers of pebbles (or, as we shall more naturally say, shot) required to make the shapes in question.”3 In other words he gave form to the numerical relationships that lay beyond the world as it appears to us. The harmonies he discovered were evidence of a perfect and ideal world that lay beyond our own woven in a fabric of pure geometrical relationships. It has been argued that the first examples of the Platonic solids date back as far as the Neolithic period after the discovery of a number of carved stone polyhedral forms dating to around 2000 BC.4 The purpose of these enigmatic objects remains unknown and whether they constitute proof of an early understanding of mathematics or merely something more banal cannot be said. Irrespective of this it is the persistent influence of Pythagoreanism on western thought that we are interested in here, not the origin of the Platonic solids per se. 6 7 If we recognise Pythagoras, the man who preached to animals, as the principle originator of an expanded concept of form we are better equipped to understand the mystical dimension inherent in mathematics that continues to hold resonance today. It was Pythagoras who first rejected the sensible world on favor of mathematics as the only source of true knowledge. It should be remembered that Greek philosophy actually emerged out of early religions (Orphism) and belief systems (the worship of Dionysus), not separately to them. This is why, says Russell quoting Cornford, all subsequent systems inspired by Pythagoreanism “tend to be other worldly, putting all value in God and condemning the visible world as false and illusive.”5 Plato’s contribution was to use ‘form’ in his theory of universals and thus to implicate it in a philosophical fig.
Recommended publications
  • Laws of Form - the Language of the Consciousness and Its Applications - ID: 58298
    This PDF is for review purposes ONLY. This PDF is for review purposes ONLY. Laws of Form - the language of the consciousness and its applications - ID: 58298 Type of Funding Request: Online Funding Inquiry Status of this Funding Request: Draft/Saved Instructions: This PDF document is a read-only version of your funding request as it currently stands. You may print or save this document for your records. However, you should not attempt to edit this document. Any edits made to this PDF will not be saved in the Templeton Portal. If there are further edits that you would like to make to your funding request, please return to the request inside the Templeton Portal, select the appropriate section(s) of the form, make your edits, and save your work. After saving your work in the portal, you will be able to generate a new PDF version of the funding request that includes your recent edits. Below you will find a list of all fields that must be completed before submitting this funding request to the Foundation. To complete these fields, please return to the request inside the Templeton Portal, select the appropriate section(s) of the form, add the required content, and save your work. When all fields are completed and you are satisfied with your description of the proposed project, you may go to the Templeton Portal to submit your request. Please note that all requests must be submitted through the Templeton Portal and the Foundation will not accept this PDF as a valid application for funding. After submitting your request, it will become read-only and you will not be able to make any additional edits.
    [Show full text]
  • LAWS of FORM Alphabetum
    LAWS OF FORM Alphabetum III LAWS OF ALPHABETUM III ▶ — George Spencer-Brown of Form Laws FORM 2019 � � LAWS OF FORM GEORGE SPENCER-BROWN In collaboration with the Liverpool University and the Laws of Form 50th Anniversary Conference. Alphabetum III September 28 — December 31, 2019 West Den Haag, The Netherlands The Yin and Yang of G. Spencer Brown’s Laws of Form R. John Williams I. Changing Consciousness One evening in the fall of 1969, along the picturesque cliffs of Big Sur, California, media gadfly and Whole Earth Catalog editor, Stewart Brand, approached the neuro- physiologist and dolphin researcher, John C. Lilly, with a copy of a strange little book called Laws of Form. They had spent the weekend attending panels, meditating, and dropping acid at a recently established center named Esalen — one of several burgeoning hotspots of what had come to be known as the ‘human potential movement’. Brand needed somebody to review the book, but thus far had had difficulty finding anyone who would dare take on the project. Brand didn’t claim to really understand the book, but he did sense that it was more than a mere exercise in logic. Indeed, as he puzzled over its pages, it seemed to have some kind of occult power — a key, per- haps, for unlocking the doors of perception and entering the incandescent realms that he and so many others were seeking at Esalen and other centers for new age spiritual- ity. 5 For the previous issue of The Whole Earth Catalog, Brand of consciousness dictating our realities. Only by ‘being had asked solar-energy guru and eco-warrior Steve Baer here now’ in the sensory deprivation tank, he thought, to review it, but what Baer turned in was less than helpful could we enter those transcendent realms outside of (even as it confirmed Brand’s intuition that the book time.
    [Show full text]
  • George Spencer-Brown's Laws of Form Fifty Years On
    MATHEMATICS TEACHING RESEARCH JOURNAL 161 Special Issue on Philosophy of Mathematics Education Summer 2020 Vol 12 no 2 George Spencer-Brown’s laws of form fifty years on: why we should be giving it more attention in mathematics education Steven Watson University of Cambridge Abstract: George Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Forms was first published in 1969. In the fifty years since its publication, it has influenced mathematicians, scientists, philosophers, and sociologists. Its influence on mathematics education has been negligible. In this paper, I present a brief introduction to the theory and its philosophical underpinnings. And I set out an argument why Laws of Form should be given more attention in mathematics education. Introduction Last year (2019) marked the 50th anniversary of the publication of Laws of Form (LoF), written by George Spencer-Brown (1969). Bertrand Russell described Laws of Form as, “a calculus of great power and simplicity. Not since Euclid’s Elements have we seen anything like it” (Homes, 2016). Heinz von Foerster, pioneer of second order cybernetics, offered no reserve in his praise for Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form. The laws of form have finally been written! With a "Spencer-Brown" transistorized power razor (a Twentieth Century model of Occam's razor) G. Spencer-Brown cuts smoothly through two millennia of growth of the most prolific and persistent of semantic weeds, presenting us with his superbly written Laws of Form. This Herculean task which now, in retrospect, is of profound simplicity rests on his discovery of the form of laws. Laws are not descriptions, they are commands, injunctions: "Do!" Thus the first constructive proposition in this book (page 3) is the injunction: "Draw a distinction!" an exhortation to perform the primordial creative act (von Foerster, 1971, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Bayesian Inference and the World Mind
    Bayesian inference and the world mind John O. Campbell Abstract Knowledge is a central concept within both Bayesian inference and the mathematical and philosophical program of logic and semiotics initiated by Charles Sanders Peirce and further developed by George Spencer-Brown and Louis Kauffman. The latter school is more philosophical than is usual with the practitioners of Bayesian inference and claims the existence of a world mind. When these two disciplines inform each other semiotics is provided with mathematical mechanism and Bayesian inference is seen to be closely related to the act of distinction, the fundamental basis of logic in the work of Spencer-Brown. Given that Darwinian processes are physical implementations of Bayesian inference and are utilized within numerous scientific theories across a wide range of disciplines as mechanisms for the creation and evolution of knowledge we may view the conjunction of these theories, within universal Darwinism, as descriptive of a world mind. Introduction Bayesian probability is often defined as representing a state of knowledge (Jaynes 1986) and Bayesian inference is the primary mathematical tool for describing knowledge. Another mathematical and philosophical approach to knowledge is found within the work of Charles Sanders Peirce and George Spencer-Brown. Louis Kauffman observed that Spencer-Brown, with the Laws of Form (1979), completed a program to develop the foundations of mathematical logic which had been begun by Peirce and provides a comment on the significance of this program (Kauffman 2001): It remained for Spencer-Brown (some fifty years after Peirce and Nicod) to see the relevance of an arithmetic of forms underlying his notation and thus putting the final touch on a development that, from a broad perspective, looks like the world mind doing its best to remember the significant patterns that join logic, speech and mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • G. Spencer-Brown's Laws of Form. Abstract
    Title: Some-thing from No-thing: G. Spencer-brown’s Laws of Form. Abstract: G. Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form is summarized and the philosophical implications examined. Laws of Form is a mathematical system which deals with the emergence of anything out of the void. It traces how a single distinction in a void leads to the creation of space, where space is considered at its most primitive, without dimension. This in turn leads to two seemingly self-evident “laws”. With those laws taken as axioms, first an arithmetic is developed, then an algebra based on the arithmetic. The algebra is formally equivalent to Boolean algebra, though it satisfies all 2-valued systems. By following the implications of the algebra to its logical conclusions, self-reference emerges within the system in the guise of re-entry into the system. Spencer-Brown interprets this re-entry as creating time in much the same way in which distinction created space. Finally the paper considers the question of self-reference as seen in Francisco Varela’s Principles of Biological Autonomy, which extended Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form to a 3-valued system. SOME-THING FROM NO-THING: G. SPENCER-BROWN’S LAWS OF FORM The knowledge of the ancients was perfect. How so? At first, they did not yet know there were things. That is the most perfect knowledge; nothing can be added. Next, they knew that there were things, but they did not yet make distinctions between them. Next they made distinctions, but they did not yet pass judgements on them.
    [Show full text]
  • The BF Calculus and the Square Root of Negation
    The BF Calculus and the Square Root of Negation Louis H. Kauffman Arthur M. Collings Department of Mathematics, Statistics and Computer Science Independent Researcher University of Illinois at Chicago P.O. Box 114 Chicago, IL USA Red Hook, NY USA Department of Mechanics and Mathematics [email protected] Novosibirsk State University, Novosibirsk, Russia [email protected] Abstract—The concept of imaginary logical values was intro- to BF. Section IV introduces the BF Calculus, stressing the duced by Spencer-Brown in Laws of Form, in analogy to the following important points: square root of -1 in the complex numbers. In this paper, we develop a new approach to representing imaginary values. The • Every consequence in Spencer-Brown's Primary Algebra resulting system, which we call BF, is a four-valued generalization can be represented and formally demonstrated in BF. of Laws of Form. Imaginary values in BF act as cyclic four- • Consequences exist and can be demonstrated in BF that valued operators. The central characteristic of BF is its capacity do no exist in the Primary Algebra. to portray imaginary values as both values and as operators. • All values (real and imaginary) can be viewed as being We show that the BF algebra is an stronger, axiomatically complete extension to Laws of Form capable of representing other both a value and an operation. four-valued systems, including the Kauffman/Varela Waveform • Imaginary values act as cyclic operators, in exact analogy Algebra and Belnap's Four-Valued Bilattice. We conclude by to a clock marked at the four quarter hours. showing a representation of imaginary values based on the Artin Section IV concludes with a proof that the BF algebra is braid group.
    [Show full text]
  • General Morphological Analysis, 2018
    To appear in: Technological Forecasting & Social Change: Special Issue on General Morphological Analysis, 2018. Pre-publication version. ____________________________________________________________________________________ Special Issue on: General Morphological Analysis: Modelling, Forecasting, Innovation Editors’ Introduction Tom Ritchey & Tomasz Arciszewski 1. Background The term morphology (from the Greek μορφή, morphé = form) is used in science in a number of different contexts and on a number of different conceptual levels. On the most general level, it refers to nothing less than a philosophy of science, or at least what Lakatos (1968) calls a basic scientific research program, i.e. a set of theoretical (or ontological) assumptions and methodological ground rules upon which to approach scientific enquiry in general. Although the term “morphology” was only coined at the end of the 1700’s, the scientific tradition it represents dates back to antiquity (see below). On another level, we find morphology and morphological analysis denoting a general methodological approach used in a wide range of scientific disciplines concerning the study of structural inter-relationships within the context of a developing systemic whole. For example, geomorphology is the study of landforms and the processes that shape them. Urban morphology is the study of human settlements and the process of their formation. In linguistics, morphological analysis is the branch of grammar that studies the structure of word forms and their development over time. However, it is in the field of biology – for which the term was originally coined by Goethe – that it developed into a method for the study of organic form in general, both in its structural and developmental (morphogenetic) sense (Russell, 1916; Thompson, 1917).
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Constructivism and the Epistemic Significance Of
    Cognitive Constructivism and the Epistemic Significance of Sharp Statistical Hypotheses in Natural Sciences Julio Michael Stern IME-USP Institute of Mathematics and Statistics of the University of S~aoPaulo Version 2.31, May 01, 2013. arXiv:1006.5471v8 [stat.OT] 26 Oct 2020 2 3 A` Marisa e a nossos filhos, Rafael, Ana Carolina, e Deborah. 4 5 \Remanso de rio largo, viola da solid~ao: Quando vou p'ra dar batalha, convido meu cora¸c~ao." Gentle backwater of wide river, fiddle to solitude: When going to do battle, I invite my heart. Jo~aoGuimar~aesRosa (1908-1967). Grande Sert~ao,Veredas. \Sert~ao´eonde o homem tem de ter a dura nuca e a m~aoquadrada. (Onde quem manda ´eforte, com astucia e com cilada.) Mas onde ´ebobice a qualquer resposta, ´ea´ıque a pergunta se pergunta." \A gente vive repetido, o repetido... Digo: o real n~aoest´ana sa´ıdanem na chegada: ele se disp~oempara a gente ´eno meio da travessia." Sertao is where a man's might must prevail, where he has to be strong, smart and wise. But there, where any answer is wrong, there is where the question asks itself. We live repeating the reapeated... I say: the real is neither at the departure nor at the arrival: It presents itself to us at the middle of the journey. 6 Contents Preface 13 Cognitive Constructivism . 14 Basic Tools for the (Home) Works . 16 Acknowledgements and Final Remarks . 16 1 Eigen-Solutions and Sharp Statistical Hypotheses 19 1.1 Introduction . 19 1.2 Autopoiesis and Eigen-Solutions .
    [Show full text]
  • Laws of Form
    Cybernetics and Human Knowing. Vol. 24 (2017), nos. 3-4, pp. 5-15 Foreword: Laws of Form Louis H. Kauffman The theme of this book is that a universe comes into being when a space is severed or taken apart. The skin of a living organism cuts off an outside from an inside. So does the circumference of a circle in the plane. By tracing the way we represent such a severance, we can begin to reconstruct, with an accuracy and coverage that appear almost uncanny, the basic forms underlying linguistic, mathematical, physical, and biological science, and can begin to see how the familiar laws of our own experience follow inexorably from the original act of severance.—George Spencer-Brown, 1969, p. v of Laws of Form, a note on the mathematical approach This special issue devoted to George Spencer-Brown (April 2, 1923 – August 25, 2016) and his seminal work Laws of Form (Spencer-Brown, 1969). Spencer-Brown has been a key figure in the foundations of second-order cybernetics initially through the work of Humberto Maturana, Francisco Varela and Louis H. Kauffman (Varela, Maturana, & Uribe, 1974; Varela, 1979; Kauffman & Varela, 1980). Spencer-Brown’s work has been the subject of much cybernetic musing by many workers including Ranulph Glanville, Nicolas Luhmann and many others. His work strikes a deep chord for all scholars by pointing to the fundamental role of the act of making a distinction or imagining a distinction in the formation of knowledge of any kind. As the reader will see, this work of Spencer-Brown comes as a particular culmination of many aspects of epistemology.
    [Show full text]
  • Laws of Form and the Logic of Non-Duality Louis H. Kauffman, UIC
    Reflexivity - Laws of Form and the Logic of Non-Duality Louis H. Kauffman, UIC www.math.uic.edu/~kauffman The Mind-Body Problem A Mobius Strip Marginal Note: The previous slide shows a Mobius brought to you from the fourth dimension. We take three dimensional sphere as the points at unit distance from the origin in four dimensional space. (These are complex numbers. Two planes of complex numbers make four dimensional space.) The Mobius band is given by the equations below, and “seen” via stereographic projection. Klein Bottle Available from ACME KLEIN BOTTLE, Oakland California Topological Thoughts Torus + Mobius Klein + Mobius Topological Thoughts TOPO - LOGICAL THOUGHTS Epimenides Paradox of the Liar The fictional speaker Epimenides, a Cretan, reportedly stated: The Cretans are always liars. L = Not(L) From the point of view of logic, the Liar is in an imaginary state that is neither true nor false. From the point of view of topology, the Liar has the shape of a Mobius band. The boundary of the Mobius band is One, and yet it is Two. APPLIED MOBIUS INC. Problem: Design a switching circuit (with an economical simplicity of design) that can control a single light from an arbitrary number of locations. This problem can be analysed by Boolean algebra. The following non-dual solution is the invention/discovery of cyberneticist Ricardo Uribe. Non-Dual Engineering Solutions Inc. Applications - The Mobius Belt The Mobius Shoe Mobius Fence - The inside is the outside is the inside ... Fence Mobius Fence DISTINCTION Laws of Form G. Spencer-Brown “We take as given the idea of distinction and the idea of indication, and that one cannot make an indication without drawing a distinction.” “We take, therefore, the form of distinction for the form.” The circle “makes” a distinction in the plane.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematics of Charles Sanders Peirce
    Cybernetics & Human Knowing, Vol.8, no.1–2, 2001, pp. 79–110 The Mathematics of Charles Sanders Peirce Louis H. Kauffman1 I. Introduction This essay explores the Mathematics of Charles Sanders Peirce. We concentrate on his notational approaches to basic logic and his general ideas about Sign, Symbol and diagrammatic thought. In the course of this paper we discuss two notations of Peirce, one of Nicod and one of Spencer-Brown. Needless to say, a notation connotes an entire language and these contexts are elaborated herein. The first Peirce notation is the portmanteau (see below) Sign of illation. The second Peirce notation is the form of implication in the existential graphs (see below). The Nicod notation is a portmanteau of the Sheffer stroke and an (overbar) negation sign. The Spencer-Brown notation is in line with the Peirce Sign of illation. It remained for Spencer-Brown (some fifty years after Peirce and Nicod) to see the relevance of an arithmetic of forms underlying his notation and thus putting the final touch on a development that, from a broad perspective, looks like the world mind doing its best to remember the significant patterns that join logic, speech and mathematics. The movement downward to the Form (“we take the form of distinction for the form.”[9, Chapter 1, page 1]) through the joining together of words into archetypal portmanteau Signs can be no accident in this process of return to the beginning. We study a system of logic devised by Peirce based on a single Sign for inference that he calls his ‘Sign of illation".
    [Show full text]
  • ICONIC and SYMBOLIC CONTAINMENT in LAWS of FORM William Bricken December 2009
    ICONIC AND SYMBOLIC CONTAINMENT IN LAWS OF FORM William Bricken December 2009 Overview At the turn of the twentieth century, the mathematical community adopted a radical plan to put mathematics on a firm foundation. The idea was symbolic formalization, the representation of concepts using encoded symbols that bear no resemblance to what they mean. At the same time, C.S. Peirce developed Existential Graphs, an iconic representation of logic that is drawn rather than written [ref]. Iconic forms are images that look like what they mean. In 1967, G. Spencer Brown reintroduced Peirce's iconic system in a more general algebraic style as Laws of Form [ref]. Today, mathematics remains symbolic, while other communication media have evolved into visual and interactive experiences. This essay explores the possibility of an iconic mathematics. Laws of Form (LoF) is an algebraic system expressed in an iconic notation. We interpret LoF as a calculus of containment relations, and develop intuitive, symbolic, and iconic descriptions of the Contains relation. The representation of the LoF calculus is analyzed from both the iconic and the symbolic formal perspectives, with a focus on the descriptive structures necessary to align the two representational techniques. An iconic notation resembles its interpretation, which is at variance with modern mathematical conventions that strictly separate syntax from semantics. Iconic form is displayed in two and three dimensions, while symbolic form unfolds as encoded one-dimensional strings of tokens. Iconic variables stand in place of arbitrary patterns of zero, one, or many objects, while symbolic variables stand in place of single expressions. Symbols conform to speech, while icons conform to vision.
    [Show full text]