CONSPIRACIES and LYES: SCEPTICISM and the EPISTEMOLOGY of TESTIMONY Paul R. J. Faulkner

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

CONSPIRACIES and LYES: SCEPTICISM and the EPISTEMOLOGY of TESTIMONY Paul R. J. Faulkner ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– CONSPIRACIES AND LYES: SCEPTICISM AND THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY Paul R. J. Faulkner –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– Doctoral Thesis, June 1998 The Department of Philosophy University College London ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– ABSTRACT In Conspiracies and Lyes I aim to provide an epistemological account of testimony as one of our faculties of knowledge. I compare testimony to perception and memory. Its similarity to both these faculties is recognised. A fundamental difference is stressed: it can be rational to not accept testimony even if testimony is fulfilling its proper epistemic function because it can be rational for a speaker to not express a belief; or, as I say, it can be rational for a speaker to lye. This difference in epistemic function provides the basis for a sceptical argument against testimony. Scepticism is presented as a method rather than a problem: considering how to refute the sceptical argument is taken to be a means of evaluating theories as to how testimonial beliefs are warranted. I consider two strategies for refuting scepticism and, correlatively, two accounts of how testimonial beliefs are warranted. I show these accounts to be neutral across all theories of justification that entertain the project of investigating our faculties of knowledge. A reductionist account explains the warrant supporting our testimonial beliefs in terms of our inductive ground for accepting testimony. An anti-reductionist account explains the warrant supporting our testimonial 2 Abstract –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––-– beliefs in terms of our possessing an entitlement to accept testimony. I show how both positions can be intuitively motivated. In presenting reductionism I appeal to probability theory, empirical psychology and invoke David Hume. In presenting anti-reductionism I invoke John McDowell and Tyler Burge. A refutation of scepticism is provided by a hybrid of reductionism and anti-reductionism. The hybrid is conceived as part social externalism and part individual internalism. In developing this account I provide a means of conceptualising the dynamic that exists between individual knowers and communities of knowledge. 3 ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– CONTENTS 1. The Epistemology of Testimony: an Introduction 7 1. Testimony as a faculty of knowledge 9 1. Testimony as a way of retaining knowledge 11 2. Testimony as a way of acquiring knowledge 14 3. Similarities and Differences 18 2. The Justification of Testimonial Beliefs 20 1. Anti-reductionism and its motivations 22 2. Reductionism and its motivations 24 3. Testimony and Individualism 26 1. Two Sceptical Arguments 29 4. Conclusion: The Programme 35 2. Scepticism and Our Faculties of Knowledge 38 0.1. A Localised Sceptical Argument 44 1. Epistemology and Methodology 48 1. The Application of this Epistemology and Methodology to Testimony 55 2. The Epistemology of Our Faculties of Knowledge 59 1. The Epistemic Neutrality of Reductionism and Anti- reductionism 61 2. Epistemic Difference and Two Short Responses to Scepticism 69 3. Conclusion 87 3. Establishing the Credibility of Testimony 89 0.1. Credibility and Probability 92 1. Prior Reasons for Believing Testimony Credible 95 4 Contents ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 1. The Problem of Type Identity for Probability Calculation 99 2. The Observational Problem 101 3. The Problem of Type Identity for Direct Inference 107 2. David Hume’s Reductionist Epistemology of Testimony 111 1. Coady’s Hume 112 2. Testimony Judged by the Principles of Human Nature 114 3. Contextual Reasons for Believing Testimony Credible 120 1. Monitoring a Speaker 122 2. Our Testimonial Faculty 126 4. Conclusion 134 4. Reductionism as a Response to Scepticism Of Testimony 136 1. Prior Reasons and Acceptance Rules 140 1. The Simple Rule 141 2. An Adequate Acceptance Rule 148 3. The Uniformity of Types of Testimony 151 2. Contextual Reasons and Human Nature 157 1. The Evidence of Miracles 158 2. The Uniformity of Human Nature 164 3. Can Reductionism Provide a Response to Scepticism of Testimony? 166 1. The Motivation for Reductionism and the Parallel with Scepticism of Induction 171 5. The Transmissibility of Knowledge 178 1. Telling the Facts and Commoning Knowledge 181 2. McDowell’s Disjunctive Epistemology of Testimony 184 1. The Disjunctive Conception of Knowledge 186 2. The Disjunctive Conception of Testimony 200 3. Scepticism and Our Entitlement to Acceptance 202 4. Scepticism of Testimony 205 3. Scepticism and Acts of Testifying 209 1. Communication and Our Animal Inheritance 211 2. The Argument from Illusion Reconsidered 223 5 Contents ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– 6. Understanding Our Entitlements: The Epistemology of Acceptance 225 1. Epistemic Justification: Burge’s View 227 2. The Epistemology of Acceptance 232 1. The Epistemic Role of Perception in Interlocution 233 2. Our Entitlement to Seeming-Understanding 242 3. The Acceptance Principle and its Justification 249 3. Our Reliance upon Rational Sources 256 1. Concerning the Possibility of Incompetent and Artful Rational Sources 257 2. The Acceptance Principle and Scepticism of Testimony 266 7. The Social Character of Testimonial Knowledge 272 0.1. The Epistemic Role of Positive and Defeating Reasons in the Acceptance of Testimony 276 1. The Preservation of Warrant and Epistemic Authority 283 1. Our Dependence on Epistemic Authority 285 2. Testimonial Knowledge and Reasons 289 3. The Knowledgeable Community 295 2. Communal Warrant and Individual Justification 302 1. Epistemic Dependence or Reliance? 304 2. An Individual’s Doxastic Responsibility 308 3. The Individual Knower and the Community of Knowledge 314 1. Conclusion: A Hybrid Epistemology of Testimony 321 References 325 6 ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– CHAPTER ONE ––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY: AN INTRODUCTION Testimonial beliefs are central to our lives; through understanding and accepting the utterances of others we form beliefs ranging from the commonplace, our belief in our birth-date or the identity of our parents, to the fanciful, among nineteenth century Norsemen ‘sild’ and ‘herring’ were used as terms for money and fish. Our knowledge of the world and the past, our knowledge of other minds and our own minds are each and all interwoven with testimonial knowledge. My beliefs, for instance, that the highest peak of the Carpathian Mountains is 8788 feet and that the North Atlantic Drift is a major ocean current flowing from the Gulf of Mexico to North West Europe depend upon testimony. I have not scaled these mountains nor seen the entire passage of this ocean current. Many of my beliefs about the past equally depend on testimony. I believe that there have been two world wars in Europe this Century and that the Medici family gave three Popes to the Church, yet these events occurred before my birth. I do not remember their happening. Many of my beliefs about other minds also depend on testimony. If another were to tell me that they are not angry but indignant, I might believe them despite only seeing their displeasure. And my beliefs about my own mental states 7 The Epistemology of Testimony: an Introduction –––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––-– could also depend on testimony. I might believe, for instance, that my intentions were generous but another could demonstrate to me, maybe by offering an alternative description of my actions, that they were solely self- interested.1 Such examples could, obviously, be endlessly enumerated. This is not to suggest that our epistemic dependence on testimony is limited to further enumeration.2 It is to claim that testimony is a faculty or source of knowledge, where our faculties, or sources, of knowledge are those ways by which knowledge is acquired or retained.3 As such to describe a belief as testimonial is to say something about its epistemic status; it is not simply to describe its causal genesis. Thus in seeking to explain how testimony is a source of knowledge and determine the epistemic status of testimonial beliefs, the epistemology of testimony is part of the larger project in the theory of knowledge of investigating our faculties of knowledge. In this introduction to the epistemology of testimony I aim to outline 1 Burge similarly notes, “Of course, much of our self-knowledge ... depends on observation of our own behaviour and reliance on other’s perceptions of us.” Burge (1988), 649. 2 Fricker (1995), 402, suggests that the acquisition of language could also be considered a special case of our epistemic dependence upon testimony. Coady (1992), 169-73, argues that testimony is implicated in the formation of many perceptual beliefs. The belief, for instance, that this “is an eighteenth-century mahogany architect’s desk”. Strawson similarly claims, “perception without the concepts and attendant information which derive from the spoken or written word is, if not blind, pitifully short-sighted.” Strawson (1994), 26. 3 Thus
Recommended publications
  • Ironic Feminism: Rhetorical Critique in Satirical News Kathy Elrick Clemson University, [email protected]
    Clemson University TigerPrints All Dissertations Dissertations 12-2016 Ironic Feminism: Rhetorical Critique in Satirical News Kathy Elrick Clemson University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://tigerprints.clemson.edu/all_dissertations Recommended Citation Elrick, Kathy, "Ironic Feminism: Rhetorical Critique in Satirical News" (2016). All Dissertations. 1847. https://tigerprints.clemson.edu/all_dissertations/1847 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Dissertations at TigerPrints. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TigerPrints. For more information, please contact [email protected]. IRONIC FEMINISM: RHETORICAL CRITIQUE IN SATIRICAL NEWS A Dissertation Presented to the Graduate School of Clemson University In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy Rhetorics, Communication, and Information Design by Kathy Elrick December 2016 Accepted by Dr. David Blakesley, Committee Chair Dr. Jeff Love Dr. Brandon Turner Dr. Victor J. Vitanza ABSTRACT Ironic Feminism: Rhetorical Critique in Satirical News aims to offer another perspective and style toward feminist theories of public discourse through satire. This study develops a model of ironist feminism to approach limitations of hegemonic language for women and minorities in U.S. public discourse. The model is built upon irony as a mode of perspective, and as a function in language, to ferret out and address political norms in dominant language. In comedy and satire, irony subverts dominant language for a laugh; concepts of irony and its relation to comedy situate the study’s focus on rhetorical contributions in joke telling. How are jokes crafted? Who crafts them? What is the motivation behind crafting them? To expand upon these questions, the study analyzes examples of a select group of popular U.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Defense of Reductionism About Testimonial Justification of Beliefs
    Page 1 Forthcoming in Noûs A Defense of Reductionism about Testimonial Justification of Beliefs TOMOJI SHOGENJI Rhode Island College Abstract This paper defends reductionism about testimonial justification of beliefs against two influential arguments. One is the empirical argument to the effect that the reductionist justification of our trust in testimony is either circular since it relies on testimonial evidence or else there is scarce evidence in support of our trust in testimony. The other is the transcendental argument to the effect that trust in testimony is a prerequisite for the very existence of testimonial evidence since without the presumption of people’s truthfulness we cannot interpret their utterances as testimony with propositional contents. This paper contends that the epistemic subject can interpret utterances as testimony with propositional contents without presupposing the credibility of testimony, and that evidence available to the normal epistemic subject can justify her trust in testimony. I. Introduction There has recently been a considerable interest in anti-reductionism about testimonial justification of beliefs, according to which we cannot justify our trust in testimony by perceptual and memorial evidence.1 The reason for the interest is not the enticement of skepticism. Recent anti-reductionists hold that we are prima facie justified in trusting testimony simply because it is testimony. This means that there is a presumption in favor of testimony that it is credible unless contrary evidence is available. I will use the term “anti-reductionism” to refer to this non-skeptical version of anti-reductionism about testimonial justification. The more traditional position is reductionism, of which the most prominent advocate is David Hume.
    [Show full text]
  • You Are Not Your Brain: Against Teaching to the Brain
    You Are Not Your Brain: Against Teaching to the Brain Gregory M. Nixon Gregory Nixon is an Assistant Professor in the School of Education at the University of Northern British Columbia in Prince George. He took his doctorate with William F. Pinar at Louisiana State University and taught at various universities in the USA for 12 years before returning home to Canada. He publishes widely on learning theory and philosophy of mind. He is editor-at-large for the Journal of Consciousness Exploration & Research. Abstract Since educators are always looking for ways to improve their practice, and since empirical science is now accepted in our worldview as the final arbiter of truth, it is no surprise they have been lured toward cognitive neuroscience in hopes that discovering how the brain learns will provide a nutshell explanation for student learning in general. I argue that identifying the person with the brain is scientism (not science), that the brain is not the person, and that it is the person who learns. In fact the brain only responds to the learning of embodied experience within the extra-neural network of intersubjective communications. Learning is a dynamic, cultural activity, not a neural program. Brain-based learning is unnecessary for educators and may be dangerous in that a culturally narrow ontology is taken for granted, thus restricting our creativity and imagination, and narrowing the human community. [keywords: selfhood, neuroscience, cognitive science, brain-based learning, intersubjectivity, consciousness, philosophy of mind, explanatory gap, cultural construction, reductionism, scientism, education, learning theory, curriculum theory] Brain-Based Scientism 2 Introduction Human experience is a dance that unfolds in the world and with others.
    [Show full text]
  • Bertrand Russell on Sensations and Images Abdul Latif Mondal Aligarh Muslim University SUMMARY INTRODUCTION
    Bertrand Russell on Sensations and Images Abdul Latif Mondal Aligarh Muslim University SUMMARY In his Theory of Mind, Russell tries to explain the mind in positive terms of sensations and images. All the mental phenomena like imagination, belief, memory, emotion, desire, will, even consciousness etc. are attempted to be established as entities, subjects, or acts by Russell. In his works The Analysis of Mind and An Outline of Philosophy, Russell offers the explanations of each mental phenomena with reference to neutrality of sensations and images, Russell does not treat them as neutral in his book The Analysis of Mind. However, in his later work, he treats them to be neutral. Russell relates especially the images to ―mnemic‖ causation. Firstly, he declares them as concerned with action in time. Subsequently, he explains them as permanent modification of the structure of the brain. He also explains sensations and images as stuff of our brain. In his book The Analysis of Mind, Russell tries to explain various mental phenomena. Firstly, he contends that all types of mental phenomena is a mix up of sensations and images and does not imply a special entity designated as ‗consciousness.‘ Secondly, Russell considers how combinations of sensations and images do, in a sense, imply consciousness in the sense of awareness. For Russell, a single sensation and image cannot in itself be deemed to be cognitive. When we try to explain a conscious mental occurrence, we do analyse it into non-cognitive constituents. We also need to show what constitutes consciousness or awareness in it. In this paper, our contention is that Russell‘s explanation of mental phenomena is especially related to these two claims.
    [Show full text]
  • What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(S): Hans Halvorson Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol
    What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(s): Hans Halvorson Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 79, No. 2 (April 2012), pp. 183-206 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/664745 . Accessed: 03/12/2012 10:32 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.52.67 on Mon, 3 Dec 2012 10:32:52 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions What Scientific Theories Could Not Be* Hans Halvorson†‡ According to the semantic view of scientific theories, theories are classes of models. I show that this view—if taken literally—leads to absurdities. In particular, this view equates theories that are distinct, and it distinguishes theories that are equivalent. Furthermore, the semantic view lacks the resources to explicate interesting theoretical relations, such as embeddability of one theory into another.
    [Show full text]
  • Reductionism in Education R.T
    Reductionism in Education R.T. Alien, Loughborough Leicestershire, England 1. Reductionism as a Metaphysical Issue In an earlier article, I demonstrated the necessary ingredients of metaphysics in education1• I propose now to show how Reductionism, some­ times called 'Reductivism', is a metaphysical issue, has serious consequences for human life, and can gravely affect educational practice and theory.2 Firstly, we need to distinguish Reductionism from the reduction of one set of laws to another within the same science, whereby the former set are shown to be special cases of the latter. Such reductions are legitimate simplifications. Reductionism, in contrast, is to be understood as the claim that one whole set of things is or can be wholly explained in terms of another set. It is, therefore, a reduction in the number of types of entity or the regions of the world. In particular, Reductionism today operates with a stratified conception of the universe--for example, mind, life, matter or energy--and claims to be able to eliminate the higher levels or to explain them completely in terms of the lower. Familiar examples are the claims that mind is observable behaviour and that people's beliefs and attitudes can be entirely explained in terms of their upbring­ ing or social class. Reductionism, therefore, is to be understood as the claim that a given set of things are either illusory or epiphenomenal: they have either no reality or no independent power. Three types of Reductionism have been distinguished3: a. Methodological--breaking down presently unintelligible wholes into their component parts, which can be managed, fmding their structures and func­ tions, and working thence back to an understanding of the whole.
    [Show full text]
  • Socratic Reductionism in Ethics
    Socratic Reductionism in Ethics Nicholas Smyth, Fordham University Genealogy is the study of the ways in which concepts, ideas, values and norms have emerged, persisted, and developed over time. Recently, philosophers have begun to argue that the method is of great importance for analytic philosophy, which has traditionally shown some resistance to historical inquiry.i Arguably, genealogy can be particularly fruitful in ethics, where there is notably wide cultural and historical variation across conceptual schemes. To understand where our ethical concepts come from is to gain insight into their social function(s), as well as to envision ways in which they might be improved, revised, or perhaps even eliminated. One of the more striking claims in the genre was made by Bernard Williams, and I shall take it as my point of departure in this paper. Williams argued that modern life in certain Western countries was characterized by the increasing prominence of certain forms of reflection, and that this reflectiveness has actually resulted in the declining influence of thick ethical concepts (such as courage and honesty), which, he claimed were de-prioritized in favor of the use of thin concepts (such as good and right). Williams suggested that the growing influence of reductionist moral theories was a sign that thinner concepts were acquiring more and more currency (Williams, 1986, p. 163). While these claims can certainly seem both puzzling and ambitious, in what follows, I’ll argue that Plato’s ‘Socratic’ dialogues actually contain a genealogical key to the nature and origin of the process Williams describes. In attempting to explain why we use the concepts we do, there is no more profitable figure than that of Socrates, who has exerted enormous influence over the methodological self-image of Western philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Myth of the Superuser: Fear, Risk, and Harm Online
    The Myth of the Superuser: Fear, Risk, and Harm Online ∗ Paul Ohm Fear of the powerful computer user, the “Superuser,” dominates debates about online conflict. He is a mythic figure: difficult to find, immune to technological constraints, and aware of legal loopholes. Policymakers, fearful of his power, too often overreact by passing overbroad, ambiguous laws intended to ensnare the Superuser but which are instead used against inculpable, ordinary users. This response is unwarranted because the Superuser is often a marginal figure whose power has been greatly exaggerated. The exaggerated focus on the Superuser reveals a pathological characteristic of the study of power, crime, and security online, which springs from a widely held fear of the Internet. Building on the social science fear literature, this Article challenges the conventional wisdom and ∗ Associate Professor of Law and Telecommunications, University of Colorado Law School. Thanks to Tim Wu, Orin Kerr, Phil Weiser, Julie Cohen, Pierre Schlag, Brett Frischmann, Victor Fleischer, Miranda Fleischer, Viva Moffat, and Jean Camp for their helpful comments. Thanks also for suggestions and support from participants in the University of Colorado Law School Faculty Workshop, including Clare Huntington, Nestor Davidson, Scott Peppett, Mimi Wesson, Amy Schmitz, Sarah Krakoff, and Brad Bernthal; the Intellectual Property Scholars Conference; and the Telecommunications Policy Research Conference. Thanks also to Todd Blair and Michael Beylkin for outstanding research assistance. 1327 1328 University of California, Davis [Vol. 41:1327 standard assumptions about the role of experts. Unlike dispassionate experts in other fields, computer experts are as susceptible as laypeople to exaggerate the power of the Superuser.
    [Show full text]
  • "Reductionism in Ethics" In
    1 Reductionism in Ethics Chris Heathwood What Is Reductionism in Ethics? Ethical reductionism is a doctrine in metaethics, the area of ethics in which we ask not what the facts are concerning our moral obligations, or concerning what things in life are worth pursuing, but, among other things, questions about the nature (or even the very existence) of such facts. One such question is whether moral facts are, to put it roughly, identical to facts of another kind. Reductionism in ethics is the view that they are. That is, reductionists hold that moral facts, or moral properties, are identical to facts or properties that can be expressed using nonmoral vocabulary. Moral reductionism (i) demystifies moral properties – it tells us what they are. It promises further advantages in (ii) explaining how we can come to know moral facts (see epistemology, moral), (iii) explaining why moral facts necessarily depend upon nonmoral facts (see supervenience, moral), and (iv) rebutting charges of the explanatory idleness of moral facts (see explanations, moral). Critics complain, however, that explaining the moral in other terms leaves out what is essential to and important about it: its evaluative or normative nature (see normativity). Two simple examples of reductionist views are the following: the property of being morally wrong just is the property of being generally disapproved of; and the fact that some life is a good life is the very same fact as the fact that that life is an enjoyable life. These theses are said to reduce a moral or evaluative property or fact to a nonmoral, nonevaluative property or fact, in the way that a reductive thesis in the philosophy of mind might reduce psychological facts to neurological facts.
    [Show full text]
  • To Be a Reductionist in a Complex Universe
    How (not) to be a reductionist in a complex universe Karola Stotz Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, A14, Sydney NSW 2006, Australia. Email: [email protected] Word count: 3000 1. Introduction In the last 10 years the reductionism debate has shifted to the idea of reduction as a relation not between theories, but between explanations. A reductionist explains a system’s phenomenon by the properties and interactions of its components. Through this move Sahotra Sarkar attempted to shift attention from a discussion of the logical form of scientific theories to questions regarding the interpretation of scientific explanations (Sarkar 1998). During this time there has been a spate of publications on what has variously been termed 'causal', 'proximal', or 'experimental' biology, including Sahotra Sarkar’s Molecular Models of Life, Marcel Weber’s Philosophy of Experimental Biology, William Bechtel’s Discovering Cell Mechanisms and Alexander Rosenberg’s Darwinian Reductionism (Sarkar 2005; Weber 2005; Bechtel 2006; Rosenberg 2006). Among the emergent themes in the recent literature on proximal biology are: 1. Does proximal biology discover 'mechanisms' rather than laws or theories? 2. What is the relationship between physicalism and antireductionism? 3. How does proximal biology deal with levels of organization, complexity and non-trivial emergence? In the light of these and other themes this paper discusses to what extent should we expect biological phenomena to be reduced to the molecular level. While most philosophers of biology, and arguably biologists as well, subscribe to some kind of physicalism they also belief that biological phenomena in principle cannot be reduced to physical ones.
    [Show full text]
  • Transcendence of the Ego: the Non-Existent
    © Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2004, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. Ratio (new series) XVII 4 December 2004 0034–0006 TRANSCENDENCE OF THE EGO (THE NON-EXISTENT KNIGHT) Bas C. van Fraassen Abstract I exist, but I am not a thing among things; X exists if and only if there is something such that it = X. This is consistent, and it is a view that can be supported. Calvino’s novel The Non-Existent Knight can be read so as to illustrate this view. But what is my relation to the things there are if I am not identical with any of them – things such as my arms, my garden, the city I live in? I name this the Gur- duloo problem, after the Knight’s page. This relation must be one that admits of degrees; I suggest that we say that I manifest myself through the things thus associated with me. Several pseudo- problems, pertaining to volitional action, supervenience, observ- ability, and the emergence of consciousness, dissolve upon inspection.1 I am as inseparable from the world as light, and yet exiled as light is, gliding over the surface of stones and water, never gripped nor held.2 I exist, but I am not a thing among things. I am neither a physi- cal object nor a mental substance or abstract entity, nor a com- pound thereof. I am not animal, mineral, or vegetable. Nor am I a thing constituted by or composed of things of that sort taken together. I am not some piece of furniture of the universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Biases Cognitive Biases and Heuristics Are Mental Shortcuts That Aid in Processing of Information, but Can Lead to Suboptimal Decisions
    Cognitive Biases Cognitive biases and heuristics are mental shortcuts that aid in processing of information, but can lead to suboptimal decisions. List of Biases and Heuristics Bias/Effect Description Business Problem Category Advice Ambiguity bias Preference for known Need to We favor options that appear simple risks over unknown risks Act Fast or that have more complete information over more complex, ambiguous options. Anchoring Overreliance on initial Think of each Too Much We notice when something has information piece of Information changed. information as independently as possible, then review them collectively Anecdotal fallacy Overvaluing personal Not We find stories and patterns even in experience when Enough sparse data. compared to data Meaning Anthropomorphism Mistakenly imbuing things Not We find stories and patterns even in with human traits Enough sparse data. Meaning Appeal to novelty Belief that something new Need to In order to stay focused, we favor the is inherently superior to Act Fast immediate, relatable thing in front of status quo us over the delayed and distant. Appeal to probability Mistaking probability for Even the best Not We simplify probabilities and fallacy certainty laid plans can Enough numbers to make them easier to think fail, even when Meaning about. they are more likely than not to succeed Argument from Mistaken belief that a Some Not We fill in characteristics from fallacy fallacious argument arguments are Enough stereotypes, generalities, and prior implies that the better than Meaning histories
    [Show full text]