Altruism Syllabus June 2019.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Altruism Syllabus June 2019.Pdf Stephen G. Post, Ph.D. [email protected] HCB 512 Altruism & Bioethics (Rm 067 Depart of Family, Population and Preventive Medicine, LH3) June 3, 2019 ALTRUISM AND BIOETHICS: Professional, Philosophical, Scientific, and Clinical Perspectives The term “altruism,” which derives from the Latin alter (“the other”), means literally “other-ism.” It was created by the French sociologist and positivist Auguste Comte (d.1798-1857) to displace a plurality of terms, including benevolence, mercy, charity, love, kindness and any notions with a theological history (1975 [1851], p. 556). It was suggested by a French legal expression, le bien d’autrui (“the good of others”). It resonates with compassion, kindness, and many other words. Altruism refers to any action that is primarily motivated by a genuine concern for the well-being and security of another. In essence, altruism (“other-regarding”) is the basis of most ethical motivation and behavior, although there is also a moral duty of self-care that if ignored suggests to some the idea of “pathological altruism.” Altruism stands at the center of professionalism in that the clinician “professes” (professio) by public oath a commitment to the good of patients. Thus, “profession” is something more than “occupation” (occupare or occupy) and “career” (careo or carry). Yet without self-care altruism cannot be sustained. Altruism need not include extreme self-sacrifice, although in its certain intense expressions it might. The balance between care for others and for self is a complex matter, and will vary between individuals, although it is safe to state that contributing to the lives of others is closely associated with well-being, happiness, and flourishing. In the western world, the altruism of medicine and the health professions did not emerge from Greek or Roman times at all, but rather from the influences of the Abrahamic traditions, which gave rise to the idea of a true passion for the good of patients. The writings of Hippocrates, for example, recommend against treating those who are dying, infectious, poor, or noncitizens. Yet altruism does not imply that doctors, nurses and other providers are indefatigable, invincible, and beyond the need for respite and care of the self. No one cares optimally for patients if they are depleted and exhausted. During this course we will be addressing topics in medicine and healthcare, but as a means to reflect on the altruistic impulse and its groundings in evolution, affect, logic, and even spirituality. We will be reading one major general philosophical/scientific text across the entire course, bit by bit. That text is written by one of greatest Buddhist thinkers of our time, Matthieu Ricard. It is Altruism: The Power of Compassion to Change Yourself and the World (2013). 1 READINGS Articles will be sent to students as attachments for each class session. Students will need to purchase (on line via Amazon) two books: TIME Special Edition (2019) The Science of Good & Evil. We are reading this very recent update on good and evil in human nature so as to ground ourselves in a balanced view of the human moral capacity. Matthieu Ricard, Altruism: The Power of Compassion to Change Yourself and the World. 2013. Ricard is probably the most well regarded writer on this topic. SG Post with Jill Neimark, Why Good Things Happen to Good People (this will be given out to students rather than purchased). SCHEDULE Tuesday June 4 (6 a.m. – 8:30 p.m.) TOPIC: THE BASICS OF ALTRUISM What is Altruism and Where Does it Come From? View Video at Home Ricard’s The Altruism Revolution At https://vimeo.com/164267900 Password VIAALTREV44 This video will help you get through Ricard’s book. We will watch parts of it in class to stimulate conversation. Readings Ricard, Parts I & II Wednesday June 5 (6 a.m. – 8:30 p.m.) TOPIC: ALTRUISM & MORAL PSYCHOLOGY/NORMAL & PATHOLOGICAL ALTRUISM Readings Ian Parker, “The Gift,” The New Yorker, Aug. 2, 2004, pp. 54-63. 2 AJ Henderson, MA Landolt, et al., “The Living Anonymous Kidney Donor: Lunatic or Saint? American Journal of Transplantation, Vol. 3, No. 2, 2003, pp. 203-213. Beth J. Seelig and Lisa S. Rosof, “Normal and Pathological Altruism,” Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, Vol. 49, No. 3, 2001, pp. 933-959. Moral Psychology There is no moral life without some degree of concern for others. Every ethical theory has to include some moral psychology that allows some strategy or disposition by which human nature is capable of taking into account the good of others as well as of self. Category I Psychological Egoists: The bleak Contractarians (e.g., Hobbes, Freud) are pessimistic about any significant human capacity for benevolence that goes beyond immediate kin, and deem even parental love as tainted with narcissism. Benevolence is weak and highly myopic, consistent with today’s “selfish gene theory” espoused by Richard Dawkins. Rationality is relatively powerless to overcome selfishness, and is really a form of rationalization (Freud) rather than anything especially “pure” (Kant). But even self-interested prudential reasoning can allow us to agree “as if by contract” on certain very minimal preventive prohibitions necessary for surviving together in society. Society is an artificial prudential arrangement and there is no serious argument for the ideal of oneness and interconnectivity. Ethically, we can create minimalistic social/legal restrictions on lying, violence, and violations of privacy. As a result, Contractarians are ethically minimalistic, but they can recommend “do no unjustified harm” as a thin principle, enforced and sustained by threats imposed by the state (Hobbes’ “Great Leviathan”). These prohibitions are easily set aside by classism, greed, hostility, and egoism. Thus Freud wrote of civilization as a very thin veneer over a seething cauldron of Id, and as something that leaves humanity discontented. There is no moral idealism at all, no Good Samaritanism expected or required, no motivational altruism that withstands critique. Not all Contractarians are so bleak (e.g. Locke, Daniels, Bok). Some are more hopeful about the self-restraining power of rationality (i.e., of self-controlling “enlightened” self- interest) absent coercive threat and legal punishment. They think that our natural state is a bit more social and wired for reciprocal altruism, but Hobbes’ famous “war of all against all” is never that far away. Category II The Rational Altruists: While there may be all sorts of selfish human tendencies, the Rationalists (e.g., Plato, Kant, Nagel, Rawls) are convinced that reason alone rises above such tendencies in a triumphant clarity of logic that simply by virtue of its clarity can and does motivate us to transcend the baser elements of human nature into a life of equal-regarding universal respect based on universal principles. Whatever affective disposition exists in human nature such as compassion or social emotions are unreliable. We are endowed with reason and through this gift of the mind we can achieve moral enlightenment and abide in it. Reason is not just instrumental, but pure and 3 powerful enough to overcome adverse inclinations. Hence, then, the Enlightenment ideal lives on. Category III The Affective Altruists: There are those who observe and celebrate a biologically natural set of social-moral sentiments such as kindness, compassion, warm altruism and love of humanity. Indeed, natural affective (empathic) dispositions have, through the evolution of group selection at various levels beyond kin, gained a strength that is potentially universal. There is still a bleak side to human nature that is selfish and insular, and the product of individual selection, but at least there is a powerful substrate of compassion and empathy that, with the exception of the occasional sociopath, provides an internal moral sense that is based in our emotional nature. Reason need play only a quite a secondary guiding role, but it can provide perspective and wisdom. These are the affective or psychological altruists. For example, the Dalai Lama refers to this sense as innate compassion, as does Ricard, Adam Smith and David Hume. Darwin wrote of a “natural benevolence” based on group-level selection. Darwin, however, saw that the flip side of the coin of in-group altruism is out-group hostility, and ultimately appealed to the rational altruism of Kant to ensure a sense of a common humanity. After all, the differences between “them” and “us” that we think are morally significant are not. Category IV Virtue Altruists/Theorists: These days, many philosophers are neo- Aristotelians. They simply recognize human nature as a vast mixed bag capable of pretty much anything. However, we human beings are thankfully malleable creatures of habit, and we can be habituated to almost anything, including to benevolence. We learn altruism by observing good role models within families and wider communities, and we are nothing if not inspired by those around us who are worthy of imitation and emulation. Here literature comes into play, as we read about the habits of inspiring people (e.g., Paul Farmer, Cicely Saunders, Gandhi, MLK, etc.) and take them into our core. We take shape in communities of character with symbols, teachings, expectations, role models, rewards, and identity formation over time. We live in symbols and symbols live in us. Category V Metaphysical or Spiritual Altruists: There are those who think of altruism in metaphysical/spiritual terms. Thus the Hassidic artist Marc Chagall, or the poet W.H. Auden, who described his quiet experience as follows: One fine summer night in June 1933 I was sitting on a lawn after dinner with three colleagues, two women and one man. We liked each other well enough but we were certainly not intimate friends, nor had anyone of us a sexual interest in another. Incidentally, we had not drunk any alcohol.
Recommended publications
  • Altruism in Auguste Comte and Ayn Rand Robert L. Campbell
    A Dialogue on Ayn Rand’s Ethics Reply to Robert H. Bass, “Egoism versus Rights” (Spring 2006) Altruism in Auguste Comte and Ayn Rand Robert L. Campbell Robert H. Bass (2006) emphatically rejects Ayn Rand’s well- known argument that altruism in morality is inconsistent with respect for individual rights in politics. His article raises a multitude of issues. As much needs to be said about its treatment of egoism as its treatment of altruism. A good deal could be said, as well, about Bass’s insensitivity to the ancient ethical tradition to which Rand’s moral theory largely belongs. But here I will target a single point of controversy: Rand’s interpretation of altruism, which Bass declares is such a gross distortion as to invalidate her entire critique of it. Did Rand Misunderstand Altruism? As Bass correctly summarizes, Rand ([1943] 1968; 1957; 1961; 1964) maintained that altruism means placing what is good for others above what is good for oneself. According to Rand, the altruist regards achieving the good of others as essentially unconstrained by any concern for the rights or dignity of mere individuals, whose prime moral obligation is to submerge themselves within the collective and sacrifice themselves for it. This, however, should be no comfort to any Objectivist seriously concerned to address positions that real people hold. For Rand’s conception of altruism was entirely fantastic. It is a doctrine that has never been held by any important moral thinker and, in particular, not by any of the The Journal of Ayn Rand Studies 7, no. 2 (Spring 2006): 357–69.
    [Show full text]
  • Egoism and Altruism: the “Antagonists” Or the “Brothers”?
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by InfinityPress Journal of Studies in Social Sciences ISSN 2201-4624 Volume 7, Number 2, 2014, 164-188 Egoism and Altruism: the “Antagonists” or the “Brothers”? Levit L. Z., Ph. D. The Centre for Psychological Health and Education, Minsk, Belarus Abstract. The article under consideration deals with the theoretical analysis and the practical research of the ratio between the two notions: egoism and altruism. The author shows the inadequacy of the one-sided, morally loaded interpretations of both terms. The scores of two ESM-investigations mostly show the positive correlation between the “egoism” and the “altruism” scales in a person’s everyday activity. The results obtained give the opportunity to replace the inadequate view on egoism and altruism as opposites by a more appropriate metaphor of the older and the younger brother. Such an approach removes the idea of antagonism which is usually ascribed to the egoism-altruism interrelation. Key words: egoism, altruism, meaning, happiness, personal uniqueness, positive psychology. © Copyright 2014 the authors. 164 Journal of Studies in Social Sciences 165 Person-oriented conception of happiness: introduction and the brief explanation. In the years 2006 – 2012 the author (Leonid Levit) elaborated a synthesizing conception of self-realization and happiness, which is based on the ideas of the systemic approach and combines biological, psychological, social and spiritual (the highest) levels of individual life and activity. The results of our seven-year work on the problem are summarized in five monographs (Levit, 2010; 2011a; 2011c; 2012 a; 2013 c) and articles (Levit, 2009; 2011 b, 2012 b, 2012 c; 2013 a; 2013 b; 2013 e; Levit, Radchikova, 2012 a).
    [Show full text]
  • The Palgrave Handbook of Altruism, Morality, and Social Solidarity Formulating a Field of Study
    The Palgrave Handbook of Altruism, Morality, and Social Solidarity Formulating a Field of Study Edited by Vincent Jeffries THE PALGRAVE HANDBOOK OF ALTRUISM, MORALITY, AND SOCIAL SOLIDARITY Copyright © Vincent Jeffries, 2014. All rights reserved. First published in 2014 by PALGRAVE MACMILLAN® in the United States—a division of St. Martin’s Press LLC, 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, NY 10010. Where this book is distributed in the UK, Europe and the rest of the world, this is by Palgrave Macmillan, a division of Macmillan Publishers Limited, registered in England, company number 785998, of Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS. Palgrave Macmillan is the global academic imprint of the above companies and has companies and representatives throughout the world. Palgrave® and Macmillan® are registered trademarks in the United States, the United Kingdom, Europe and other countries. ISBN: 978–1–137–39184–1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The Palgrave handbook of altruism, morality, and social solidarity : formulating a fi eld of study / [edited] by Vincent Jeffries. pages cm Includes index. ISBN 978–1–137–39184–1 (hardcover : alk. paper) 1. Altruism. 2. Ethics. 3. Solidarity. 4. Sociology. I. Jeffries, Vincent. HM1146.P35 2014 301—dc23 2014003318 A catalogue record of the book is available from the British Library. Design by Newgen Knowledge Works (P) Ltd., Chennai, India. First edition: August 2014 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents List of Figures and Tables ix Preface xi Acknowledgments xv Part 1 General Perspectives and Future Directions 1 Altruism, Morality, and Social Solidarity as a Field of Study 3 Vincent Jeffries 2 Virtues and Human Personhood in the Social Sciences 21 Margarita A.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Perspectives
    01-Johnson(Ethics)-45065.qxd 10/25/2006 3:51 PM Page 3 1 Ethical Perspectives Chapter Preview Utilitarianism: Do the Greatest Good for the Greatest Number Evaluation Kant’s Categorical Imperative: Do What’s Right No Matter What the Consequences Are Evaluation Rawls’s Justice as Fairness: Balancing Freedom and Equality Evaluation Communitarianism: Promoting Shared Moral Values Evaluation Altruism: Concern for Others Evaluation Implications Application Projects Chapter End Case: Truro’s DNA Dragnet Endnotes thical theories are critical to organizational transformation. We will Eemploy them repeatedly throughout the remainder of this text. Ethical per- spectives help us identify and define problems, force us to think systematically, encourage us to view issues from many different vantage points, and provide us with decision-making guidelines. In this chapter I’ll introduce five widely used ethical approaches. I’ll briefly summarize each perspective and then offer an evaluation based on the theory’s advantages and disadvantages. Resist the temptation to choose your favorite approach and ignore the rest. Use a variety of theories when possible. Applying all five approaches to the same problem (practicing ethical pluralism) is a good way to generate new 3 01-Johnson(Ethics)-45065.qxd 10/25/2006 3:51 PM Page 4 4—LAYING AN ETHICAL FOUNDATION insights about the issue. You can discover the value of ethical pluralism by using each theory to analyze the Chapter End Case (see Application Project 7 on page 24). You may find that some perspectives are more suited to this prob- lem than others. Combining insights from more than one theory might help you come up with a better solution.
    [Show full text]
  • Ayn Rand's Philosophy “Objectivism” and Her Idea of “The Ideal Man”
    Ayn Rand’s philosophy “Objectivism” and her idea of “the ideal man” in comparison to modern approaches Diplomarbeit Zur Erlangung des Magistergrades An der Kultur- und Gesellschaftswissenschaftlichen Fakultät Der Universität Salzburg Fachbereich: Anglistik und Amerikanistik Gutachter: Dr. Ralph Poole Eingereicht von: Simone Koch Salzburg: 2018 1 Inhalt Abstract ......................................................................................................................................... 3 Introduction ................................................................................................................................... 4 1. Objectivism ........................................................................................................................... 6 1.1. Ayn Rand’s novels ........................................................................................................ 7 1.1.1 The Fountainhead (1943) ............................................................................................. 7 1.1.2. Atlas Shrugged (1957) .............................................................................................. 10 1.2. Reality ......................................................................................................................... 12 1.2.1. Reason ....................................................................................................................... 13 1.3. Capitalism – the economic system .............................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical Core of Effective Altruism
    Forthcoming in Journal of Social Philosophy The Philosophical Core of Effective Altruism Brian Berkey 1. Introduction In his recent book on the effective altruism movement, Peter Singer approvingly cites a definition according to which effective altruism is “a philosophy and social movement which applies evidence and reason to working out the most effective ways to improve the world” (2015, 4-5). Effective altruism’s identity as both a philosophy, or, more precisely, a set of core philosophical commitments, and a social movement places effective altruists in a position in which they must consider the question of which philosophical commitments are essential, such that one must embrace them in order to count as an effective altruist, at least in part in the light of the goal of building a robust social movement capable of advancing its aims. On the one hand, the goal of building a social movement provides a strong reason for effective altruists to embrace a set of core commitments that is as ecumenical as possible, so that no one is excluded who might otherwise identify with the movement and contribute to advancing its central aims. On the other hand, there are a number of risks involved in adopting a broadly ecumenical approach to social movement building. Such an approach can, for example, limit a movement’s ability to challenge conventional wisdom by publicly defending controversial claims, including claims the acceptance of which may have helped to bring together and motivate many early members of the movement. More generally, it can undermine the distinctiveness of a movement, making it less clear how it should be distinguished from other sufficiently similar movements, and why it might represent an important and unique way of thinking about and attempting to address the social problems on which it is focused.
    [Show full text]
  • DICTIONARY of PHILOSOPHY This Page Intentionally Left Blank
    A DICTIONARY OF PHILOSOPHY This page intentionally left blank. A Dictionary of Philosophy Third edition A.R.Lacey Department of Philosophy, King’s College, University of London First published in 1976 by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd Second edition 1986 Third edition 1996 by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE 29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2005. “To purchase your own copy of this or any of Taylor & Francis or Routledge’s collection of thousands of eBooks please go to www.eBookstore.tandf.co.uk.” © A.R.Lacey 1976, 1986, 1996 All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Lacey, A.R. A dictionary of philosophy.—3rd edn. 1. Philosophy—Dictionaries I. Title 190′.3′21 B41 ISBN 0-203-19819-0 Master e-book ISBN ISBN 0-203-19822-0 (Adobe eReader Format) ISBN 0-415-13332-7 (Print Edition) Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data A catalog record for this book is available on request Preface to the first edition This book aims to give the layman or intending student a pocket encyclopaedia of philosophy, one with a bias towards explaining terminology. The latter task is not an easy one since philosophy is regularly concerned with concepts which are unclear.
    [Show full text]
  • Daoist/Taoist Altruism and Wateristic Personality: East and West1
    Daoist/Taoist Altruism and Wateristic Personality: East and West1 Yueh-Ting Lee Dean of the College of Arts and Sciences, Minot State University, Minot, North Dakota 58707 USA [email protected] Vinai Norasakkunkit Department of Psychology, Minnesota State University Li Liu School of Psychology, Beijing Normal University Jian-Xin Zhang Institute of Psychology, Chinese Academy of Sciences Min-Jie Zhou Institute of Psychology, Chinese Academy of Sciences Based on the Daoist/Taoist model of water-like (or wateristic) personality features (Lee, 2003, 2004), four hypotheses were derived with a focus on altruism and modesty. A total of 122 Chinese college students and 106 American college students participated in this cross-cultural study. It was found (1) that American college students were more altruistic than Chinese counterparts; (2) that levels of modesty were more trait-specific than culture-specific; and (3) that Chinese participants were more altruistic and receptive toward outgroup members or outsiders (e.g., aliens) than American counterparts in uncertain situations. Theoretical implications are also discussed. 1. Introduction: Rationale for Studying Daoist/Taoist Altruism Cross-Culturally In this introduction we will address three major issues. First, how do western and Eastern scholars see altruistic behavior and human nature? What do we mean by altruism? How is altruism related to love? Next we will discuss the connections between altruism and Daoism (Taoism) as well as a Daoist/Taoist model of water-like (or wateristic) personality features, which involve altruism. Finally, we shall review cross-cultural evidence with regard to self- sacrificing altruism, modesty, and religion and also present our major research questions based on the Daoist/Taoist model.
    [Show full text]
  • The Value of Limited Altruism*
    The Value of Limited Altruism* by Charles Blackorby, Walter Bossert, and David Donaldson August 1998 revised December 1998 Charles Blackorby: University of British Columbia and GREQAM Walter Bossert: University of Nottingham David Donaldson: University of British Columbia * Research support from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada is gratefully acknowledged. The paper was presented at the University of Southampton. We thank seminar participants for their comments and criticisms and we are especially indebted to Peter Vallentyne for comments on two earlier drafts. December 14, 1998 Abstract Discounting the utilities of future people or giving smaller weights to groups other than one’s own is often criticized on the grounds that the resulting objective function differs from the ethically appropriate one. This paper investigates the consequences of changes in the discount factor and weights when they are moved toward the warranted ones. Using the utilitarian value function, it is shown that, except in restrictive special cases, those moves do not necessarily lead to social improvements. We suggest that limitations to altruism are better captured by maximizing the appropriate value function subject to lower bounds on some utilities. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Nos.: D63, D71. Keywords: Social Choice, Altruism, Consequentialism. The Value of Limited Altruism by Charles Blackorby, Walter Bossert, and David Donaldson 1. Introduction When economists investigate policies that affect the well-being of several generations, they often employ objective functions that discount the well-being (utility) of future people. This common practice has been criticized by many, either on the grounds that the implied ethics are not impartial, or on the grounds that the absence of discounting is a consequence of the axiom Pareto indifference.1 Alternatively, some argue that, although discounting is ethically warranted, the levels chosen are too high.2 If these views are correct, a natural recommendation is to use the appropriate value function.
    [Show full text]
  • An Analysis of the Objectivist Ethics in Educational Leadership Though Ayn Rand’S the Virtues of Selfishness (1964)
    1 The Lamar University Electronic Journal of Student Research Spring 2007 An Analysis of the Objectivist Ethics in Educational Leadership Though Ayn Rand’s The Virtues of Selfishness (1964) Karen Dupre Jacobs PhD Student in Educational Leadership College of Education Prairie View A & M University Teacher Alief Independent School District Houston, Texas William Allan Kritsonis, PhD Professor Faculty Mentor PhD Program in Educational Leadership Prairie View A&M University Member of the Texas A&M University System Visiting Lecturer Oxford Round Table University of Oxford, Oxford, England Distinguished Alumnus Central Washington University College of Education and Professional Studies ABSTRACT Educational leadership is vital to sustain quality educational institutions. It is the role of the school leader to indoctrinate stakeholders with the objectivist ethic- embracing egoism and relinquishing altruistic ideals when it comes to invigorating the system with sustainable change. Ayn Rand’s timeless piece of literature The Virtue of Selfishness (1964) is the foundation for incorporating these ideals into the educational arena around the world. 1 2 Introduction Ayn Rand’s beliefs are instrumental in developing and nurturing objectivist ideals. She embraces the importance of being selfish in order to restore individualism and objectivism. Ms. Rand stresses that people often disregard their own individualism in order to concede with the prevailing thoughts of society. Individuals, in an effort to be a part of the status quo, often go against their own ideals. The prevalence of this common occurrence by school leaders in schools around the world must end. School leaders, as individuals, must challenge themselves to practice egoism and disregard the ideals of altruism.
    [Show full text]
  • Apriorist Self-Interest: How It Embraces Altruism and Is Not Vacuous
    COMMENTARY Apriorist Self-Interest: How it Embraces Altruism and is Not Vacuous J. C. Lester Introduction This essay is part of an attempt to reconcile two extreme views in economics: the (neglected) subjective, apriorist approach and the (standard) objective, scientific (i.e., falsifiable) approach. The Austrian subjective view of value, building on Carl Menger’s theory of value, was devel- oped into a theory of economics as being entirely an a priori’ theory of action.2 This probably finds its most extreme statement in Ludwig von Mises’ Human Action (1949). In contrast, the standard economic view has developed into making falsifiable predictions about economic phe- nomena whereby the truth of the assumptions, especially about economic agents, is relatively unimportant: predictive fecundity is all. This finds an extreme statement in Milton Friedman’s introductory essay in his Essays in Positive Economics (1953). However, many economists fall somewhere between the two extremes, such as McKenzie and Tullock ( 1978).3 As a consequence, Austrian economics has fallen out of favor with most economists for not being scientific (falsifiable), while standard economics has fallen out of favor with many non-economists for being insufficiently linked with the real subjective aspects of human val- ues, especially welfare, liberty, and morality. I generally view Austrians as correct on an a priori core. It is also quite valid to argue by drawing out the logical consequences of, say, rent control or minimum wage laws ceteris paribus. It is absurd to dismiss such arguments com- pletely in favor of empirical tests. But I shall not here be attempting the immense project of adjudicating between (or, perhaps, marrying the best parts of each of) the two approaches to economics in areas other than the self-interest aspect of the rationality assumptionP We need to look at the problem in more detail.
    [Show full text]
  • Four Motives for Community Involvement ∗ C
    Journal of Social Issues, Vol. 58, No. 3, 2002, pp. 429--445 Four Motives for Community Involvement ∗ C. Daniel Batson and Nadia Ahmad University of Kansas Jo-Ann Tsang Southern Methodist University A conceptual analysis is offered that differentiates four types of motivation for community involvement: egoism, altruism, collectivism, and principlism. Differentiation is based on identification of a unique ultimate goal for each motive. For egoism, the ultimate goal is to increase one’s own welfare; for al- truism, it is to increase the welfare of another individual or individuals; for col- lectivism, to increase the welfare of a group; and for principlism, to uphold one or more moral principles. As sources of community involvement, each of these four forms of motivation has its strengths; each also has its weaknesses. More effective efforts to stimulate community involvement may come from strategies that orchestrate motives so that the strengths of one motive can overcome weak- nesses of another. Among the various possibilities, strategies that combine ap- peals to either altruism or collectivism with appeals to principle may be especially promising. In The Prince, Machiavelli (1513/1908) imagined himself offering counsel to a public official who wished to provide the best life for his people. The worldly wisdom that Machiavelli provided has stood the test of time. We have no illusions that we can give advice that is as wise or enduring, but we borrowed Machiavelli’s literary device and tried to imagine ourselves in a similar situation. A local civic leader—the mayor, let us say—comes to us for help.
    [Show full text]