The Notion of Form in Kant's Critique of Aesthetic Judgment

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Notion of Form in Kant's Critique of Aesthetic Judgment This dissertation has been 65-13,286 microfilmed exactly as received UEHLING, Jr., Theodore Edward, 1935- THE NOTION OF FORM IN KANT'S CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGMENT. The Ohio State University, Ph.D., 1965 Philosophy University Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan Copyright by Theodore Edward Uehling, 1966 THE NOTION OP FORM IN KANT'S CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGMENT DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University Theodore Edward Uehling, Jr., B.A The Ohio State University 1965 Approved by A d v i s e r J Department of Philosophy PREFACE This dissertation is the result of investigations into Kant’s Critique of Aesthetic Judgment begun in the summer of i960. I am especially grateful to Professor John P. Anton of the State University of New York at Buffalo who first suggested to me the crucial importance of the notion of form in Kant’s aesthetics. Our discussions, not only about Kant but about aesthetics in general have, I hope, borne some fruit in this essay, although I am not confident that Professor Anton would find it possible to agree with everything that is in it. Portions of chapter four vrere read in February, 1963 » before a Philosophy Department Colloquium at the Ohio State University. I am grateful to the faculty members and as­ sistants of the Department of Philosophy for their criti­ cisms and helpful suggestions. I am also grateful to Dr. David Campbell of the Uni­ versity of Minnesota, Morris, who read and criticized my translations in chapter tvro and to Mr. Donald W. Spring, Chairman of the Humanities Division at the University of Minnesota, Morris, whose concern during the academic year 1963-6^ expedited the completion of this essay. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Acknowledgments are due to the following for permis­ sion to quote: Harvard University Press for passages from Robert Paul Wolff's Kant's Theory of Mental Activity. The Macmillan Company for passages from H.J. Paton's Kant's Metaphysic of Experience. The Macmillan Company Ltd., St. Martin's Press, Inc., for passages from Norman Kemp-Smith's translation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Oxford University Press, Inc., for passages from J.C. Meredith's translation of Kant's Critique of Judg- ment. iii VITA July 31, 1935 Born - Scranton, Pennsylvania 195^-1957 United States Air Force 1959 B.A., The Ohio State University Columbus, Ohio 1960-1963 Teaching Assistant, Department of Philo­ sophy, The Ohio State University, Colum­ bus, Ohio I963-I965 • • Instructor in Philosophy, University of Minnesota, Morris, Minnesota FIELDS OF STUDY Major Field: Philosophy Studies in the History of Philosophy. Professors Norman Kretzman and Marvin Fox Studies in Metaphysics. Professors Everett J. Nelson and Virgil Hinshaw Studies in Epistemology. Professors Virgil Hinshaw and Herbert Hochberg Studies in Logic. Professors Steven F. Barker and Everett J. Nelson Studies in Ethics. Professors Herbert Hochberg and Carl Ginet Studies in Aesthetics. Professors Morris Weitz and John P . Anton Studies in Kant. Professors John P. Anton, Marvin Fox, Norman Kretzman and Everett J. Nelson iv TABLE OP CONTENTS Page PREFACE .................................................. ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ....................................... iii VITA .................................................. iv Chapter I. INTRODUCTION ............................... 1 II. THE NOTION OP FORM i PRELIMINARY INVESTIGATION ............................... 8 III. FORM, IMAGINATION AND UNDERSTANDING ..... 33 IV. THE NOTION OF FORM AND THINGS-IN- T H E M S 3 L V E S ............................... 92 V. FORM AND KANT'S THEORY OF ART ...........124 VI. CONCLUSION .................. 144 BIBLIOGRAPHY ......................................... 150 v CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION The first half of Kant’s Critique of Judgment has long been looked upon as setting some of the most crucial problems and questions in philosophical aes­ thetics. Margolis, for example, writes: Aesthetics, as a discipline, begins approxi­ mately with Kant's Critique of Judgment. It was Kant . who gave a sense of philo­ sophical importance to aesthetics and set certain of its central questions.1 Ren£ Wellek points out that Kant "must be consid­ ered the first philosopher who clearly and definitely established the peculiarity and autonomy of the aesthetic realm."2 Wellek even goes so far as to say: "One may look upon the whole history of general aesthetics after Kant as a series of discussions, repudiations, and developments of Kant’s thoughts."3 Hegel, in a well-known passage, re­ marks that in Kant’s considerations about form in the 1Philosophy Looks at the Arts, ed. Joseph Margolis (New York: Scribner's, 1962), pp. 5-6• 2Ren£ Wellek, "Aesthetics and Criticism," The Philos­ ophy of Kant and Our Modern World, ed. Charles Hendel (New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1957)» P» 67. 3ibld., p. 77. 1 Critique of Judgment we find "the first reasonable thing said about beauty."^ There is some rather general agree­ ment, then, that the Critique of Judgment holds a rather important place in the history of aesthetics. The agreement on this point does not extend to the interpretations which the Critique has fostered. On the contrary, there is a full panorama of views concerning the meaning of the central notions in Kant's aesthetic theory, as well as the import of the theory as a whole. This panorama of views arises, I think, from four main sources. Moreover, what I think are some errors in inter­ pretation arise from one or more of the same four sources. First, there is the difficulty of various readings in the three editions of the Critique of Judgment published during Kant's lifetime (1790, 1?93» 1799)* One variation in reading, appearing only in the 1799 edition, concerning Kant's views toward the physical theory of light and sound advanced by Euler, is crucial enough to receive consider­ able attention in the sequel. Second, and related to the first, is the general availability of two English translations of the Critique of Judgment (J.H. Bernard's and J.C. Meredith's). Variations in these two translations are sufficient in ^G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, trans. E.S. Haldane and F.H. Simson (New York* Humanities Press, 1963), III. 469. scope to render divergent meaning at some places. In this essay I have made use of both English translations as well as VorlSnder's German edition (Hamburgs Felix Meiner, 192*0 and Hartenstein*s edition (Leipzig: Modes und Baumann, 1839). Third, many writers have approached the Critique of Judgment with a set of presuppositions extensive enough to prohibit a fair interpretation or criticism of Kant's mean­ ing. Croce's comments in his Aesthetic are, I think, a case in point. Now I do not mean to say that Kant's aesthetics should always be approached, regardless of the purpose of the author, without any presuppositions. But I do assert that in so far as one is concerned with an an analytical exposition of meaning, presuppositions should be reduced to the minimum. I hope that in this essay my own presup­ positions have been so reduced. I have no philosophical axe to grind; my foremost concern is to find out what Kant meant. Fourth, the Critique of Judgment ought not be looked at in isolation from the other Critiques. The first half of the Critique of Judgment is not limited to Kant's aes­ thetics but involves the extension and, at times, the modi­ fication of issues raised in the earlier Critiques. For ex­ ample, Kant did not exhaust the notion of the imagination in the Critique of Pure Reason. He has a great deal to say about this notion in his analysis of the apprehension of the form of an object. Other examples are the notions of judgment and the thing-in-itself. The question of the re­ lationship of judgment to understanding and reason receives considerable attention in the Critique of Judgment. Some illumination is shed as well upon the very troublesome thing-in-itself. I suggest, then, that to succeed in any exegesis of the Critique of Judgment, it is necessary to consider it in its reciprocal relationship with the two earlier Critiques. I think that in order to understand and appreciate Kant's aesthetics it is necessary to realize a considerable scope of these relationships. We cannot iso­ late Kant's aesthetics from his theoretical or practical philosophy nor can we isolate the theoretical or practical from the aesthetic. In sum, then, this exegesis will pro­ ceed by considering the Critique of Judgment as part of the Critical Philosophy and not as an isolated statement in aesthetics (or in anything else). There are, of course, many relationships which exist among the Critiques. It is far beyond the scope of this essay to investigate all or even the most significant part of them. Rather, I intend to concentrate primarily upon one notion of great importance in Kant's aesthetics, the notion of "form." I hope to show the development of this notion within the Critical Philosophy and its meaning and role within the first half of the Critique of Judgment. With the investigation and elucidation of this notion seems to me to lie the solution to many of the perplexing difficulties and paradoxes of the Third Critique, Indirectly, the notion of "form** sheds considerable light upon one bother­ some notion in the earlier Critiques, the notion of the thing-in-itself. Moreover, the notion of "form" is central in Kant’s discussions of purposiveness without purpose and the place of the faculties of imagination and understand­ ing in the analysis of the judgment of taste. In what sense or senses pleasure in aesthetic contemplation is derived from the perception of the harmony of the imagination and the understanding in the apprehension of the form of an object is a key question in Kant's aesthetics and within the Critical Philosophy.
Recommended publications
  • Notes on Peirce's Semiotics and Epistemology
    DIAGRAMMATIC THINKING: NOTES ON PEIRCE’S SEMIOTICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY Luis Radford In this paper, I discuss the role of diagrammatic thinking within the larger context of cognitive activity as framed by Peirce’s semiotic theory of and its underpinning realistic ontology. After a short overview of Kant’s scepticism in its historical context, I examine Peirce’s attempt to rescue perception as a way to reconceptualize the Kantian “manifold of senses”. I argue that Peirce’s redemption of perception led him to a se- ries of problems that are as fundamental as those that Kant encountered. I contend that the understanding of the difficulties of Peirce’s epistemol- ogy allows us to better grasp the limits and possibilities of diagrammatic thinking. Keywords: Culture; Diagrammatic thinking; Kant; Peirce; Perception; Semiotics Pensamiento Diagramático: Notas sobre la Semiótica y la Epistemología de Peirce En este artículo se discute el papel que desempeña el concepto de pen- samiento diagramático en el contexto de la actividad cognitiva, tal y como es concebida dentro del marco de la teoría semiótica de Peirce y su subyacente ontología realista. Luego de presentar una visión general del escepticismo kantiano en su contexto histórico, se examina el esfuer- zo de Peirce por rescatar la percepción, esfuerzo que lo lleva a indagar de manera innovadora el “multiespacio de los sentidos” del que habla- ba Kant. Se mantiene que este esfuerzo lleva a Peirce a una serie de problemas que son tan fundamentales como los que Kant encontró en su propio itinerario epistemológico. Se sostiene que la comprensión de las dificultades intrínsecas a la epistemología de Peirce nos permite cernir mejor los límites y posibilidades de su pensamiento diagramático.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Theory of Knowledge and Hegel's Criticism
    U.Ü. FEN-EDEBİYAT FAKÜLTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER DERGİSİ Yıl: 2, Sayı: 2, 2000-2001 KANT’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND HEGEL’S CRITICISM A. Kadir ÇÜÇEN* ABSTRACT Kant inquires into the possibility, sources, conditions and limits of knowledge in the tradition of modern philosophy. Before knowing God, being and reality, Kant, who aims to question what knowledge is, explains the content of pure reason. He formalates a theory of knowledge but his theory is neither a rationalist nor an empiricist theory of knowledge. He investigates the structure of knowledge, the possible conditions of experience and a priori concepts and categories of pure reason; so he makes a revolution like that of Copernicus . Hegel, who is one of proponents of the German idealism, criticizes the Kantian theory of knowledge for “wanting to know before one knows”. For Hegel, Kant’s a priori concepts and categories are meaningless and empty. He claims that the unity of subject and object has been explained in that of the “Absolute”. Therefore, the theory of knowledge goes beyond the dogmatism of the “thing-in- itself” and the foundations of mathematics and natural sciences; and reaches the domain of absolute knowledge. Hegel’s criticism of Kantian theory of knowledge opens new possibilities for the theory of knowledge in our age. ÖZET Kant’ın Bilgi Kuramı ve Hegel’in Eleştirisi Modern felsefe geleneği çerçevesinde Kant, bilginin imkânını, kaynağını, kapsamını ve ölçütlerini ele alarak, doğru bilginin sınırlarını irdelemiştir. Tanrı’yı, varlığı ve gerçekliği bilmeden önce, bilginin neliğini sorgulamayı kendine amaç edinen Kant, saf aklın içeriğini incelemiştir. Saf aklın a priori kavram ve kategorilerini, deneyin görüsünü ve bilgi yapısını veren, fakat ne usçu ne de deneyci * Uludag University, Faculty of Sciences and Letters, Dept.
    [Show full text]
  • Peirce's Theory of Communication and Its Contemporary Relevance
    Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen Peirce’s Theory of Communication and Its Contemporary Relevance Introduction The mobile era of electronic communication has created a huge semi- otic system, constructed out of triadic components envisaged by the American scientist and philosopher Charles S. Peirce (1839–1914), such as icons, indices and symbols, and signs, objects and interpretants. Iconic signs bear a physical resemblance to what they represent. Indices point at something and say “there!”, and symbols signify objects by conven- tions of a community.1 All signs give rise to interpretants in the minds of the interpreters. It is nonetheless regrettable that the somewhat simplistic triadic ex- posé of Peirce’s theory of signs has persisted in semiotics as the some- how exhaustive and final description of what Peirce intended. The more fascinating and richer structure of signs emerging from their intimate relation to intercommunication and interaction (Peirce’s terms) has been noted much less frequently. Despite this shortcoming, the full Peircean road to inquiry – per- formed by the dynamic community of learning inquirers, or the com- 1 In fact, according to Peirce (2.278 [1895]): “The only way of directly communi- cating an idea is by means of an icon; and every indirect method of communicating an idea must depend for its establishment upon the use of an icon.” Peirce’s chef d’œuvre came shortly after these remarks into being as his diagrammatic system of existential graphs, a thoroughly iconic representation of and a way of reasoning about “moving pictures of thought”, which encompassed not only propositional and predicate logic, but also modalities, higher-order notions, abstraction and category-theoretic notions.
    [Show full text]
  • Retrieving Kant's Aesthetics for Art Theory After
    8 Retrieving Kant’s Aesthetics for Art Theory After Greenberg Some Remarks on Arthur C. Danto and Thierry de Duve Diarmuid Costello The Fate of Aesthetics in Contemporary Art Theory In art theory since the early 1980s the discourse of aesthetics has been notable by its absence. Th is suggests that the majority of art theorists believe that the historical or conceptual limits of aesthetic theory have been breached by the internal development of art after modernism. But why would art theorists believe this? I n a n s w e r t o t h i s q u e s t i o n I s u g g e s t — I t a k e i t n o n c o n t r o v e r s i a l l y — t h a t the widespread marginalization of aesthetics in postmodern art theory may be attributed to the success of the art critic and theorist Clement Greenberg. In co- opting the discourse of (particularly Kantian) aesthetics to underwrite modernist theory, Greenberg mediated the art world’s sub- sequent rejection of both aesthetics in general and Immanuel Kant’s aes- thetics in par tic u lar. But one need only refl ect on the centrality for postmodern theory of anti- aesthetic fi gures like Marcel Duchamp or of movements (such as surrealism), marginalized in Greenberg’s account of “the best modern art,” to see that for all their antipathy to Greenberg, many postmodernist art theorists continue to operate with a broadly Greenbergian view of aesthetics—which is why, of course, they are forced to reject it.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter
    Kant’s Critique of Judgment and the Scientific Investigation of Matter Daniel Rothbart, Irmgard Scherer Abstract: Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle relationships between the experimental scientist, the modern instrument, and nature’s atomic particles. The principle of purposive- ness which governs judgment has also a role in implicitly guiding modern experimental science. In Part 1 we explore Kant’s philosophy of science as he shows how knowledge of material nature and unobservable entities is possible. In Part 2 we examine the way in which Kant’s treatment of judgment, with its operating principle of purposiveness, enters into his critical project and under- lies the possibility of rational science. In Part 3 we show that the centrality given to judgment in Kant’s conception of science provides philosophical in- sight into the investigation of atomic substances in modern chemistry. Keywords : Kant , judgment , purposiveness , experimentation , investigation of matter . Introduction Kant’s philosophy of science centers on the problem of how it is possible to acquire genuine knowledge of unobservable entities, such as atoms and molecules. “What and how much can the understanding and reason know apart from all experience?” ( CPuR , Axvii). This raises the question of the role of experiments in the knowability ( Erkennbarkeit ) and the experientiality (Erfahrbarkeit ) of nature. Kant’s insights into the character of scientific experimentation are not given the hearing they deserve. We argue that Kant’s theory of judgment establishes the conceptual framework for understanding the subtle inter- actions between the experimental chemist, the modern chemical instrument, and molecular substance.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethical Reasoning
    9781405170987_4_001.qxd 8/8/08 7:18 PM Page 9 PART I ETHICAL REASONING 1 A Brief Overview of Basic Ethical Theory David R. Keller 2 A Framework for Moral Reasoning Eric H. Gampel 9781405170987_4_001.qxd 8/8/08 7:18 PM Page 10 9781405170987_4_001.qxd 8/8/08 7:18 PM Page 11 1 A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF BASIC ETHICAL THEORY David R. Keller Ethics is the philosophical study of morality. Although we use the words syn- onymously in everyday discourse, in philosophy it is important to distinguish the two. Morality is the behavior of making value judgments regarding how we should best live our lives. Two points follow. First, judgments presuppose freedom of choice; the entire edifice of ethics is erected on the assumption that value judg- ments are made by moral agents voluntarily, who therefore are responsible for those choices. This assumption leads into a whole debate about determinism versus free will that I cannot address here.1 Second, value judgments differ from judgments of ordinary preference, such as how spicy we like our food or what color of clothing we prefer to wear. Moral judgments involve interconnected conceptions of goodness, rightness, the class of beings worthy of moral consid- eration, and virtue. Moral judgments presuppose the acceptance of some highest moral good (summum bonum). This might be obedience to God, acting in accordance with duty, realizing one’s unique individual potential, affirming relationships based on care and empathy, or maximizing overall collective happiness. Humans live their lives and make daily choices with an eye to some ideal of moral goodness.
    [Show full text]
  • Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art Perception∗
    From: Pierre Bordieu The Field of Cultural Production: Essays on Art and Literature ©1984, Columbia University Press Part III: The Pure Gaze: Essays on Art, Chapter 8 Outline of a Sociological Theory of Art Perception∗ PIERRE BOURDIEU 1 Any art perception involves a conscious or unconscious deciphering operation. 1.1 An act of deciphering unrecognized as such, immediate and adequate ‘comprehension’, is possible and effective only in the special case in which the cultural code which makes the act of deciphering possible is immediately and completely mastered by the observer (in the form of cultivated ability or inclination) and merges with the cultural code which has rendered the work perceived possible. Erwin Panofsky observes that in Rogier van der Weyden’s painting The Three Magi we immediately perceive the representation of an apparition’ that of a child in whom we recognize ‘the Infant Jesus’. How do we know that this is an apparition? The halo of golden rays surrounding the child would not in itself be sufficient proof, because it is also found in representations of the nativity in which the Infant Jesus is ‘real’. We come to this conclusion because the child is hovering in mid-air without visible support, and we do so although the representation would scarcely have been different had the child been sitting on a pillow (as in the case of the model which Rogier van der Weyden probably used). But one can think of hundreds of pictures in which human beings, animals or inanimate objects appear to be hovering in mid-air, contrary to the law of gravity, yet without giving the impression of being apparitions.
    [Show full text]
  • Doing Justice to Traditional Aesthetic Theories: Weitz Reconsidered
    TRAMES, 2002, 6(56/51), 3, 266–279 DOING JUSTICE TO TRADITIONAL AESTHETIC THEORIES: WEITZ RECONSIDERED Marek Volt University of Tartu Abstract. In the very first lines of his famous article – ‘The Role of Theory is Aesthetics’ – Morris Weitz tells us that each of the great art theories (Emotionalism, Voluntarism, Formalism, Intuitionism, Organicism) converges in a logically vain attempt to provide the defining properties of art. He tries to examine some of the aesthetic theories in order to see if they include adequate statements about the nature of art. But instead of giving us exact descriptions of these theories, he provided us with only a very scant summary. Thus, even if Weitz were correct in thinking that all theories converged in an essential definition of art, he does not provide any further arguments for his conviction. Some aestheticians (Diffey, Tilghman, Matthews, Snoeyenbos) have tried to do justice to the traditional theories by suggesting that aesthetic theories were not attempting to offer essentialist definitions of art. Unfortunately, those critics left untouched the aesthetic theories offered by Weitz. Therefore, in order to evaluate (1) Weitz’s account of aesthetic theories and (2) to see if the criticisms concerning his account strike home, it is necessary to consider just theories mentioned by Weitz. My paper confirms a view that within aesthetic theories a variety of purposes can be recognised. For instance, the explanation and re-evaluation of art, and the completion of metaphysical system. I. Weitz and his critics The famous article of Morris Weitz (1968) – ‘The Role of Theory in Aesthetics’ – has raised many objections since it was published.1 Perhaps the chief objection is that Weitz did not take into account the possibility that art can be defined in terms of non-manifest properties.
    [Show full text]
  • JACOBI and FICHTE on PHILOSOPHY and LIFE Rolf Ahlers
    VITALISM AND SYSTEM: JACOBI AND FICHTE ON PHILOSOPHY AND LIFE Rolf Ahlers Abstract: This paper thematizes the crucial agreement and point of depar- ture between Jacobi and Fichte at the height of the “atheism controversy.” The argument on the proper relationship between philosophy and existence or speculation and life had far-reaching consequences in the history of thought after Jacobi and Fichte in German Idealism on the one hand, primarly advo- cated by Schelling and Hegel, and on the other hand by existentialism and vitalism. The essay focuses first on Jacobi’s philosophy of life, which cen- trally influenced and attracted Fichte to Jacobi. Jacobi’s dualism between speculation, of which he was skeptical, and life, became Fichte’s dualism. Fichte’s transcendentalism, however, prioritized, contrary to Jacobi, both speculation and systematicity. Both of these elements became central for later forms of German Idealism. In the last part of the essay Hegel’s absolute idealism becomes the platform affording a critical perspective on Fichte’s transcendental philosophy. The immediacy of life could for Fichte in 1799 not have any reality without the abstraction from life accomplished by speculative philosophy. Both “speculation” and “life” do not really have any common ground between them—a position which Reinhold attempted to find—because both oppose each other but are also dependent upon another. As “life” could not be had without speculation, so “speculation” is impossible without life, for it needs life to be able to abstract from it. Fichte made this very clear at the height of the “atheism-controversy,” in a letter to Jacobi of April 22, 1799,1 in which he says this (1799:61):2 The original duality, which traverses through the whole system of reason, and which is grounded in the duality of the subject-object is here on its highest plateau.
    [Show full text]
  • The New Role of Theory in Aesthetics
    RECOGNITION AND RECONCILIATION: THE NEW ROLE OF THEORY IN AESTHETICS by Kristin Amber Hrehor A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Queen’s University Kingston, Ontario, Canada (September, 2007) Copyright © Kristin Amber Hrehor, 2007 Abstract George Dickie’s institutional theory of art has been subject to extensive debate over the past 30 years. It has been both revered and deplored, garnering such attention for the seemingly controversial way in which Dickie answers the question, “What is art?” In Dickie’s view, an object derives its existence as a work of art in the context of the informal institution of the “artworld,” a concept which was borrowed from Arthur Danto’s earlier work on the theoretical context surrounding works of art. Whether one finds the idea appealing or appalling, it is one that quite simply cannot be ignored, since the empirical validity of the institutional structure of art and the sorts of problems it can cause, especially in our particular time, are so remarkably clear. Another significant feature of Dickie’s institutional theory is that it provides a definition of art, a problem that philosophers of art have attempted to solve for the past few centuries. Dickie’s theory inclines one to dismiss other candidates for definitions as implausible, such as those put forth by R.G. Collingwood and Leo Tolstoy, since, as Dickie insists, an acceptable definition of art must be able to account for the many different kinds of practices that are all referred to as “art.” Both Collingwood and Tolstoy advance restricted conceptions of art that are meant to confine the use of the term “art” to a specific kind of creative activity.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2014 Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Bradley Taylor University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Taylor, Bradley, "Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy" (2014). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 1468. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/1468 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Human Beings and the Moral Law: Moral Precariousness in Kant's Ethical Philosophy Abstract ABSTRACT HUMAN BEINGS AND THE MORAL LAW: MORAL PRECARIOUSNESS IN KANT'S ETHICAL PHILOSOPHY Bradley M. Taylor Dr. Paul Guyer This dissertation is an examination of human moral precariousness in Kant's ethics. Human beings are in a state of moral precariousness insofar as they are ever-capable of transgressing the moral law and are often uncertain of the moral worth of their actions. Put another way, in this dissertation I argue that the basic relationship between human beings and the moral law, in Kant's moral philosophy, is, most fundamentally, one of tenuousness and vacillation. This relation is the fundamental characteristic of the human moral condition because such a relation is built into Kant's account of human moral agency. We have a tenuous relation to the moral law because we always have at least the possibility of conflict between our desire for happiness (i.e. the satisfaction of our inclinations) and the requirements of the moral law.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: Towards a Reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-03257-6 - New Approaches to Neo-Kantianism Edited by Nicolas De Warren and Andrea Staiti Excerpt More information Introduction: towards a reconsideration of Neo-Kantianism Nicolas de Warren and Andrea Staiti In the summer of 1914, T. S. Eliot arrived in Marburg from Harvard University to attend a summer course in philosophy before taking up residency at Merton College, Oxford, for a year of study with Harold Joachim, F. H. Bradley’s successor. At the University of Marburg, Eliot met Paul Natorp, who assisted him in finding affordable accommodation and lectured in his course on philosophy. The outbreak of the First World War would cut short Eliot’s stay in Marburg, but not before he had the chance to sketch a portrait of the venerable Neo-Kantian Professor. Natorp strikes a professorial pose, one arm tucked behind his back, the other slung across his waist. With elven ears and bald cranium, the philosopher appears endearing in his otherworldliness. Natorp’s face is hidden behind oval glasses, so large that they seem to constitute a hindrance rather than an aid to seeing reality. Eliot’s sketch can be seen as a visual epitome for how Neo-Kantianism appeared to a younger generation of intellectuals and philosophers who would come of age in the aftermath of a Europe laid waste through the cataclysm of the Great War. Eliot’s amusing sketch is an apt illustration for what Hans-Georg Gadamer, who wrote his PhD dissertation on Plato under Natorp in 1922, characterized as the Neo-Kantian “calm and 1 confident aloofness” engrossed in “complacent system-building.” With slightly more bite, Hannah Arendt charged Neo-Kantianism with drown- ing philosophy “in a sea of boredom,” thereby offering a softer version of the same hostility that spirited Martin Heidegger’s confrontation with 2 Ernst Cassirer at Davos in 1929.
    [Show full text]