PHIL 1300: Philosophy of Mathematics Josh Schechter MWF 11:00–11:50 AM Fall 2013

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PHIL 1300: Philosophy of Mathematics Josh Schechter MWF 11:00–11:50 AM Fall 2013 PHIL 1300: Philosophy of Mathematics Josh Schechter MWF 11:00–11:50 AM Fall 2013 Course Information Instructor Josh Schechter Office: Corliss-Bracket, 45 Prospect St., Room 307 Office Hours: 1–3 PM Mondays (and by appointment) Email: [email protected] Phone: 863-3225 (office) Course Description This course provides an introduction to the philosophy of mathematics. We will discuss the nature of mathematical objects: Are they mental constructions, do they inhabit some Platonic realm, or are there no mathematical objects at all? We will also discuss the status of our knowledge of mathematics: How is it that we know mathematical truths? How is that we are justified in reasoning as we do in mathematics? The course will be divided into two main parts. The first part will be devoted to discussing the history of the philosophy of mathematics. We will read works by Plato, Kant, Mill, Frege, Russell, Heyting, and Brouwer, among others. This part of the course will culminate in a discussion of the important developments in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, with the emergence of Formalism, Intuitionism, and Logicism. In the second part of the course, we will turn to contemporary debates in the philosophy of mathematics. We will discuss Fictionalism, neo-Fregeanism, Plenituninous Platonism, and Structuralism, among other views. Several sessions of the course will involve discussion of technical issues in logic and mathematics. The relevant results will be explained without presupposing any specific background knowledge. However, it is recommended that students have taken a course in logic, mathematics, or a related subject prior to taking this course. Course Requirements There will be two 4-6 page papers, one 9-12 page paper, and a final exam. Each short paper will be worth 15% of your grade. The final paper will be worth 30% of your grade. The final exam will be worth 30%. Class participation will be worth the remaining 10% of your grade. Required Texts The following required books are available at the bookstore: • (Shapiro) Stewart Shapiro (2000) Thinking about Mathematics: The Philosophy of Mathematics (Oxford, Oxford University Press); • (B&P) Paul Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam, eds. (1983) Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings , 2nd edition (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press); nd • (Frege) Gottlob Frege (1884) The Foundations of Arithmetic . Translated by J. L. Austin, 2 revised edition (Northwestern University Press, 1980). Additional readings will be available on OCRA or distributed in class. The OCRA password is “math”. Texts on Reserve The following books are on reserve at the Rock: • Paul Benacerraf and Hilary Putnam, eds. Philosophy of Mathematics: Selected Readings , 2nd edition • Laurence BonJour, In Defense of Pure Reason • John Burgess and Gideon Rosen, A Subject with No Object • Hartry Field, Science without Numbers • Gottlob Frege, The Foundations of Arithmetic • Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics • Penelope Maddy, Realism in Mathematics • A.W. Moore, The Infinite • Plato, Republic • Stewart Shapiro, Thinking about Mathematics: The Philosophy of Mathematics Tentative Due Dates Paper 1: October 9th Paper 2: November 13th Final Paper: December 20 th Final Exam: Friday, December 20 th at 2 PM PHIL 1300: Philosophy of Mathematics Josh Schechter MWF 11:00–11:50 AM Fall 2013 (Tentative) Schedule of Readings Introduction Wednesday, September 4th Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics Friday, September 6 th No Class Monday, September 9 th Philosophical Puzzles about Mathematics (Shapiro) chapters 1-2 Optional: (OCRA) Mark Balaguer, “A Guide for the Perplexed” Plato, Kant, and Mill Plato Wednesday, September 11 th Plato (OCRA) Plato, Meno [focus on pp. 71 through 78] Friday, September 13th Plato on Mathematics (Shapiro) sections 3.1–3.2 (OCRA) Plato, Republic , book 6 [focus on the bottom of 199 through 207] Monday, September 16th Plato on Mathematics II (Shapiro) section 3.3 (OCRA) Plato, Republic , book 7 Wednesday, September 18th Aristotle on Mathematics (Shapiro) section 3.4 (OCRA) Aristotle, Metaphysics M, parts 1-3 Optional: (OCRA) David Bostock, “Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mathematics” Kant Friday, September 20 th Kant’s Challenge: The Synthetic A Priori (Shapiro) chapter 4.1–2 (OCRA) Immanuel Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics (excerpts) Monday, September 23rd Kant on Geometry and Arithmetic and Geometry (OCRA) Lisa Shabel, “Kant's Philosophy of Mathematics” Optional: (OCRA) Philip Kitcher, “Kant and the Foundations of Mathematics” Optional: (OCRA) Michael Friedman, “Kant’s Theory of Geometry” Mill Wednesday, September 25th Mill’s Empiricism (Shapiro) chapter 4.3 (OCRA) J. S. Mill, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive , Book II: V–VI Friday, September 27 th No Class Monday, September 30 th Challenges for Mill (Frege) sections 1–17, 23–25. The Big Three: Logicism, Formalism, and Intuitionism Logicism – Frege and Russell Wednesday, October 2 nd Frege’s Logicism (Shapiro) section 5.1 (Frege) sections 55–67 Friday, October 4th Frege’s Logicism II Monday, October 7th The Julius Caesar Problem (Frege) sections 68–83 Wednesday, October 9 th Set Theory and Russell’s Paradox Notes on Set Theory Friday, October 11th Russell’s Logicism (Shapiro) section 5.2 (B&P) Russell, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (excerpts) (OCRA) Soames, Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century , vol. 1, ch. 6 Monday, October 14 th No Class Wednesday, October 16th Logicism Assessed Formalism and Hilbert’s Program Friday, October 18th Term Formalism and Game Formalism (Shapiro) sections 6.1–6.2 Frege, Grundgesetze der Arithmetik , 86-137 Monday, October 21 st Hilbert’s Programme (Shapiro) section 6.3 (B&P) John von Neumann, “The Formalist Foundations of Mathematics” (B&P) David Hilbert, “On the Infinite” Wednesday, October 23rd Formalism and Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems (Shapiro) section 6.4 Notes on the Incompleteness Theorems Optional: (OCRA) Richard Zach, “Hilbert’s Program” Friday, October 25th Hilbert’s Programme II Monday, October 28th Formalism Assessed Intuitionism – Brouwer, Heyting, and Dummett Wednesday, October 30 th Introduction to Intuitionism (Shapiro) sections 7.1–7.2 Friday, November 1st Brouwer’s Intuitionism (B&P) L. E. J. Brouwer, “Intuitionism and Formalism” (B&P) L. E. J. Brouwer, “Consciousness, Philosophy, and Mathematics” Optional: (OCRA) Michael Detlefsen, “Brouwerian Intuitionism” Monday, November 4th Heyting’s Intuitionism (Shapiro) section 7.3 (B&P) Arend Heyting, “The Intuitionist Foundations of Mathematics” Notes on Intuitionist Real Analysis Wednesday, November 6th Dummett’s Intuitionism (Shapiro) section 7.4 (B&P) Michael Dummett, “The Philosophical Basis of Intuitionistic Logic” Friday, November 8th Intuitionism Assessed Logical Positivism Monday, November 11th Verificationism and Conventionalism (Shapiro) section 5.3 (B&P) A. J. Ayer, “The Apriori” (B&P) Rudolf Carnap, “Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology” Wednesday, November 13th Quine against Positivism (B&P) W. V. Quine, “Truth by Convention” Optional: Paul Horwich, “Conventionalism” Recent Developments Friday, November 15th The Benacerraf-Field Problem (B&P) Paul Benacerraf, “Mathematical Truth” (OCRA) Hartry Field, Introduction to Realism, Mathematics and Modality Monday, November 18 th Responses to the Benacerraf-Field Problem (OCRA) John Burgess and Gideon Rosen, A Subject with No Object (excerpts) Wednesday, November 20th Rational Insight (Shapiro) section 8.1 (B&P) Kurt Gödel, “What is Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis?”, pp. 482–5 Optional: (OCRA) Charles Parsons, “Reason and Intuition” Friday, November 22 nd Rational Insight II (OCRA) Lawrence BonJour, In Defense of Pure Reason, chapters 4 and 6 Monday, November 25 th The Indispensability Argument; Quine’s Naturalism (Shapiro) section 8.2 (OCRA) Mark Colyvan, “Indispensability Arguments” W.V. Quine, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” Optional: W. V. Quine, Word and Object (excerpts) Optional: Hilary Putnam, “Philosophy of Logic” Wednesday, November 27 th Maddy’s Naturalism (Shapiro) section 8.3 Penelope Maddy, Realism in Mathematics (excerpts) Friday, November 29 th No Class Monday, December 2 nd Fictionalism (Shapiro) section 9.1 Hartry Field, Science without Numbers (excerpts) OCRA: Stephen Yablo, “Go Figure: A Path through Fictionalism” Wednesday, December 4th Neo-Logicism (Shapiro) section 5.4 Bob Hale and Crispin Wright, The Reason’s Proper Study (excerpts) Optional: (OCRA) Richard Heck, “The Julius Caesar Objection” Friday, December 9th Structuralism (Shapiro) chapter 10 (B&P) Paul Benacerraf, “What Numbers Could Not Be” (OCRA) Charles Parsons, “The Structuralist View of Mathematical Objects” Monday, December 11 th Wrap Up .
Recommended publications
  • The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History
    The Oberlin Colloquium in Philosophy: Program History 1960 FIRST COLLOQUIUM Wilfrid Sellars, "On Looking at Something and Seeing it" Ronald Hepburn, "God and Ambiguity" Comments: Dennis O'Brien Kurt Baier, "Itching and Scratching" Comments: David Falk/Bruce Aune Annette Baier, "Motives" Comments: Jerome Schneewind 1961 SECOND COLLOQUIUM W.D. Falk, "Hegel, Hare and the Existential Malady" Richard Cartwright, "Propositions" Comments: Ruth Barcan Marcus D.A.T. Casking, "Avowals" Comments: Martin Lean Zeno Vendler, "Consequences, Effects and Results" Comments: William Dray/Sylvan Bromberger PUBLISHED: Analytical Philosophy, First Series, R.J. Butler (ed.), Oxford, Blackwell's, 1962. 1962 THIRD COLLOQUIUM C.J. Warnock, "Truth" Arthur Prior, "Some Exercises in Epistemic Logic" Newton Garver, "Criteria" Comments: Carl Ginet/Paul Ziff Hector-Neri Castenada, "The Private Language Argument" Comments: Vere Chappell/James Thomson John Searle, "Meaning and Speech Acts" Comments: Paul Benacerraf/Zeno Vendler PUBLISHED: Knowledge and Experience, C.D. Rollins (ed.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1964. 1963 FOURTH COLLOQUIUM Michael Scriven, "Insanity" Frederick Will, "The Preferability of Probable Beliefs" Norman Malcolm, "Criteria" Comments: Peter Geach/George Pitcher Terrence Penelhum, "Pleasure and Falsity" Comments: William Kennick/Arnold Isenberg 1964 FIFTH COLLOQUIUM Stephen Korner, "Some Remarks on Deductivism" J.J.C. Smart, "Nonsense" Joel Feinberg, "Causing Voluntary Actions" Comments: Keith Donnellan/Keith Lehrer Nicholas Rescher, "Evaluative Metaphysics" Comments: Lewis W. Beck/Thomas E. Patton Herbert Hochberg, "Qualities" Comments: Richard Severens/J.M. Shorter PUBLISHED: Metaphysics and Explanation, W.H. Capitan and D.D. Merrill (eds.), University of Pittsburgh Press, 1966. 1965 SIXTH COLLOQUIUM Patrick Nowell-Smith, "Acts and Locutions" George Nakhnikian, "St. Anselm's Four Ontological Arguments" Hilary Putnam, "Psychological Predicates" Comments: Bruce Aune/U.T.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Cite Complete Issue More Information About This Article
    THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN: 0495-4548 ISSN: 2171-679X [email protected] Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España Miguel Sagüillo, José Hilary Putnam on the philosophy of logic and mathematics* [1] THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, vol. 33, no. 2, 2018, pp. 183-200 Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España DOI: https://doi.org/10.1387/theoria.17626 Available in: https://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=339755528003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System Redalyc More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America and the Caribbean, Spain and Journal's webpage in redalyc.org Portugal Project academic non-profit, developed under the open access initiative THEORIA ESTABLISH E D IN 1952 BY MIGU E L SÁNCH E Z -MAZAS Vol. 33/2 • May 2018 Second Series An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science CALIJ Centro de Análisis, Lógica e Informática Jurídica (CALIJ) http://www.ehu.eus/theoria T H E O R I A REVISTA DE TEORÍA, HISTORIA Y FUNDAMENTOS DE LA CIENCIA AN INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL FOR THEORY, HISTORY AND FOUNDATIONS OF SCIENCE ESTABLISH E D in 1952 by MIGUEL SÁNCHEZ-MAZAS Second Series EDITORIAL BOARD Editor-in-chief: Andoni IBARRA (University of the Basque Country, UPV/EHU) Editors: Cristina CORREDOR (Universidad de Valladolid), Antonio DIÉGUEZ (Universidad de Málaga) Logic and philosophy of logic and mathematics: José Luis ZALABARDO (University College
    [Show full text]
  • Mcevoy on Benacerraf's Problem and the Epistemic Role Puzzle
    McEvoy on Benacerraf’s problem and the epistemic role puzzle Jody Azzouni Tufts University [email protected] Forthcoming in New Perspectives on the Philosophy of Paul Benacerraf: Truth, Objects, Infinity (ed. Fabrice Pataut). Springer: Logic, Epistemology And the Unity of Science, 2015. 1. Benacerraf’s problem. Benacerraf’s problem is justly famous. It’s had a major influence on the philosophy of mathematics right from its initial appearance,1 an influence that continues up through the present moment. In its author’s supernaturally elegant prose, it lays out a tension between the possibility of an epistemic access to abstracta and the apparent semantics (truth conditions) of mathematical statements about those entities. Given a causal construal of epistemic access, on the one hand, it seems that we can’t have any epistemic access to the objects that our true mathematical statements must be about because those objects are causally inefficacious and causally insensitive; on the other hand, the mathematical truths in question are genuinely about those objects, and somehow we are adept at identifying some of the true mathematical statements and some of the false ones. Benacerraf’s problem long outlasted the faddish “causal theory of knowledge” that he originally couched it in terms of. Field (1989, 26), among others, generalized Benacerraf’s problem by writing: Benacerraf’s challenge … is to provide an account of the mechanisms that explains how our beliefs about these remote entities can so well reflect the facts about them. The idea is that if it appears in principle impossible to explain this, then that tends to undermine the 1 Benacerraf 1973.
    [Show full text]
  • What the Applicability of Mathematics Says About Its Philosophy
    What the applicability of mathematics says about its philosophy Phil Wilson Introduction We use mathematics to understand the world. This fact lies behind all of modern science and technology. Mathematics is the tool used by physicists, engineers, biologists, neuroscientists, chemists, astrophysicists and applied mathematicians to investigate, explain, and manipulate the world around us. The importance of mathematics to science cannot be overstated. It is the daily and ubiquitous tool of millions of scientists and engineers throughout the world and in all areas of science. The undeniable power of mathematics not only to predict but also to explain phenomena is what physics Nobel laureate Eugene Wigner dubbed the “unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences” (Wigner, 1960). Yet the success of mathematics in explaining the world belies a great mystery: why is that possible? Why are our abstract thought and our manipulation of symbols able to successfully explain the workings of distant stars, the patterns of stripes on a tiger, and the weirdest behaviour of the smallest units of matter? Why is applying mathematics to the real world even possible? This is a question in the philosophy of mathematics. The traditional approach to answering it is to first decide (hopefully on rational grounds) what to believe about the nature of mathematics and its objects of study, and then to explore what this philosophical standpoint says about the applicability of mathematics to the world. In this chapter, I take a different approach. I take as given the existence of applied mathematics. On this foundational axiom, I ask the question “what does the existence of applied mathematics say about the philosophy of mathematics?” In this way, we treat the existence of applied mathematics as a lens through which to examine competing claims about the nature of mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Fabrice Pataut Editor Truth, Objects, Infinity New Perspectives on the Philosophy of Paul Benacerraf Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science
    Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science 28 Fabrice Pataut Editor Truth, Objects, Infinity New Perspectives on the Philosophy of Paul Benacerraf Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science Volume 28 Series editors Shahid Rahman, University of Lille III, France John Symons, University of Texas at El Paso, USA Editorial Board Jean Paul van Bendegem, Free University of Brussels, Belgium Johan van Benthem, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands Jacques Dubucs, CNRS/Paris IV, France Anne Fagot-Largeault, Collège de France, France Göran Sundholm, Universiteit Leiden, The Netherlands Bas van Fraassen, Princeton University, USA Dov Gabbay, King’s College London, UK Jaakko Hintikka, Boston University, USA Karel Lambert, University of California, Irvine, USA Graham Priest, University of Melbourne, Australia Gabriel Sandu, University of Helsinki, Finland Heinrich Wansing, Ruhr-University Bochum, Germany Timothy Williamson, Oxford University, UK Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science aims to reconsider the question of the unity of science in light of recent developments in logic. At present, no single logical, semantical or methodological framework dominates the philosophy of science. However, the editors of this series believe that formal techniques like, for example, independence friendly logic, dialogical logics, multimodal logics, game theoretic semantics and linear logics, have the potential to cast new light on basic issues in the discussion of the unity of science. This series provides a venue where philosophers and logicians can apply specific technical insights to fundamental philosophical problems. While the series is open to a wide variety of perspectives, including the study and analysis of argumentation and the critical discussion of the relationship between logic and the philosophy of science, the aim is to provide an integrated picture of the scientific enterprise in all its diversity.
    [Show full text]
  • A COGNITIVE APPROACH to BENACERRAF's DILEMMA Thesis Format: Monograph Luke V. Jerzykiewicz Graduate Program in Philosophy a Th
    A COGNITIVE APPROACH TO BENACERRAF'S DILEMMA Thesis format: Monograph by Luke V. Jerzykiewicz Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada c Luke V. Jerzykiewicz 2009 Abstract One of the important challenges in the philosophy of mathematics is to account for the se- mantics of sentences that express mathematical propositions while simultaneously explaining our access to their contents. This is Benacerraf's Dilemma. In this dissertation, I argue that cognitive science furnishes new tools by means of which we can make progress on this problem. The foundation of the solution, I argue, must be an ontologically realist, albeit non-platonist, conception of mathematical reality. The semantic portion of the problem can be addressed by accepting a Chomskyan conception of natural languages and a matching internalist, mentalist and nativist view of semantics. A helpful perspective on the epistemic aspect of the puzzle can be gained by translating Kurt G¨odel'sneo-Kantian conception of the nature of mathematics and its objects into modern, cognitive terms. Keywords: mathematical cognition, philosophy of mathematics, realism, psycholo- gism, functional architecture, conceptualist semantics, cognition, mathematics, Benacerraf, Chomksy, G¨odel,Kant. iii Acknowledgements I have accrued a great many personal and professional debts over the years. Let me restrict myself here to acknowledging explicitly only those that bear directly on the writing of this monograph. Above all, let me express my heartfelt thanks to my thesis supervisor, Robert Stainton, whose firm guidance, patient instruction, unfailing support, and kind help over many years have seen me though this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Truth Paul Benacerraf the Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 70, No. 19, Seventieth Annual Meeting of the American Philoso
    Mathematical Truth Paul Benacerraf The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 70, No. 19, Seventieth Annual Meeting of the American Philosophical Association Eastern Division. (Nov. 8, 1973), pp. 661-679. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0022-362X%2819731108%2970%3A19%3C661%3AMT%3E2.0.CO%3B2-V The Journal of Philosophy is currently published by Journal of Philosophy, Inc.. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/jphil.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Wed Jan 9 12:17:32 2008 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME LXX, NO.
    [Show full text]
  • Von Neumann's Methodology of Science
    GIAMBATTISTA FORMICA Von Neumann’s Methodology of Science. From Incompleteness Theorems to Later Foundational Reflections Abstract. In spite of the many efforts made to clarify von Neumann’s methodology of science, one crucial point seems to have been disregarded in recent literature: his closeness to Hilbert’s spirit. In this paper I shall claim that the scientific methodology adopted by von Neumann in his later foundational reflections originates in the attempt to revaluate Hilbert’s axiomatics in the light of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems. Indeed, axiomatics continues to be pursued by the Hungarian mathematician in the spirit of Hilbert’s school. I shall argue this point by examining four basic ideas embraced by von Neumann in his foundational considerations: a) the conservative attitude to assume in mathematics; b) the role that mathematics and the axiomatic approach have to play in all that is science; c) the notion of success as an alternative methodological criterion to follow in scientific research; d) the empirical and, at the same time, abstract nature of mathematical thought. Once these four basic ideas have been accepted, Hilbert’s spirit in von Neumann’s methodology of science will become clear*. Describing the methodology of a prominent mathematician can be an over-ambitious task, especially if the mathematician in question has made crucial contributions to almost the whole of mathematical science. John von Neumann’s case study falls within this category. Nonetheless, we can still provide a clear picture of von Neumann’s methodology of science. Recent literature has clarified its key feature – i.e. the opportunistic approach to axiomatics – and has laid out its main principles.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantic and Mathematical Foundations for Intuitionism
    SEMANTIC AND MATHEMATICAL FOUNDATIONS FOR INTUITIONISM Michael Randall Koss Submitted to the faculty of the University Graduate School in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy Indiana University June 2013 Accepted by the Graduate Faculty, Indiana University, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Doctoral Committee |||||||||||||| David Charles McCarty, Ph.D. |||||||||||||| Gary Ebbs, Ph.D. |||||||||||||| Amit Hagar, Ph.D. |||||||||||||| Neil Tennant, Ph.D. February 27th, 2013 ii Copyright c 2013 Michael Randall Koss iii To my parents iv Acknowledgements I would like to express my gratitude to Professors David McCarty, Gary Ebbs, Amit Hagar, and Neil Tennant, who together comprised my research committee, for their guidance and advice during this project. I owe special thanks to Professor McCarty for his invaluable encouragement and help improving my work and developing as a writer, teacher, and philosopher. I am also especially grateful to Professor Ebbs for coordinating a weekly discussion group that allowed me to receive helpful feedback on this work and to the other members of that group: Susan Blake, Matt Carlson, Marija Jankovic, Andrew McAninch, and Blakely Phillips. The community of philosophers and logicians at Indiana University was an indis- pensable source of support and encouragement. In addition to those mentioned above, I want to thank especially David Fisher, Derek Jones, Professor Kari Theurer, and Professor Paul Spade. The Indiana University Logic Program, the Indiana Philosoph- ical Association, and the Department of Philosophy at Indiana University-Purdue University, Fort Wayne provided opportunities for me to present work that appears in a revised form here.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Benacerraf 2007 Book.Pdf
    Princeton University Honors Faculty Members Receiving Emeritusd Status June 2007 The biographical sketches were written by colleagues in the departments of those honored. Contentsd Paul Benacerraf Page 5 Nancy Bermeo Page 8 Herman Sergeevich Ermolaev Page 13 Sam Glucksberg Page 17 Maitland Jones Jr. Page 20 Daniel Kahneman Page 23 Ulrich Camillus Knoepflmacher Page 26 Suzanne Crelly Nash Page 30 Andrew Henry Plaks Page 32 Thomas George Spiro Page 34 Howard Francis Taylor Page 37 Scott Duncan Tremaine Page 40 John Ralph Willis Page 42 John Wilmerding Page 44 Paul Benacerrafd Paul Benacerraf was born in Paris on March 26, 1931, to a Moroccan father and an Algerian mother. Paul’s earliest years were spent in Paris, until 1939 when the family moved first to Caracas, and then, when Paul was nine, to New York. Paul is proud that he still retains French citizenship. Two years lat- er, when he was 11, Paul’s parents returned to Caracas, and he entered the Peddie School in Hightstown, New Jersey, as a boarding student. In the fall of 1948, Paul entered Princeton University as a freshman, where he has remained ever since. Paul was not initially an eager student. Indeed, he told the Princeton Weekly Bulletin in November 1998 that in his junior year “the dean and I agreed that both Princeton and I would profit from a brief separation.” But he returned to Princeton after a year’s leave, and decided to major in philosophy. That proved to be a very wise decision. The following year, classes with professors John Kemeny in the philosophy of science and Robert Scoon in the philosophy of religion made a deep impression on him.
    [Show full text]
  • Outline Winter 2005
    The University of Calgary Department of Philosophy Philosophy 567.03/667.16 PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS Winter 2005 — Richard Zach Course Outline Instructor: Richard Zach Office: 1254 Social Sciences Office Hours: Tu 3:30-4:30 (tentatively) Phone: 220–3170 email: [email protected] Lectures: W 3–6 SS 105 Course Description The philosophy of mathematics deals with, as its name suggests, philosophical issues that are raised by mathematics. Perhaps the most important difference between mathematics and the other sciences is that mathematics deals with entirely abstract concepts (such as number, set, function). Mathematicians do not conduct experiments to confirm their hypotheses, they find proofs. One important issue then, for instance, is clarifying the role of proofs in mathematics, and with it, the nature of mathematical knowledge. Another issue is the question of the status of mathematical objects—do they inhabit some Platonic realm of mathematical objects, are they constructions of the mind, or are there perhaps, strictly speaking, no mathematical objects, are they fictitious? In the course of discussing these issues, we will first focus on three important schools of thought: logicism, intuitionism, and formalism. These schools are associated with, respectively, Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell, Immanuel Kant and L. E. J. Brouwer, and with David Hilbert. In the second half of the course, we will study some of the more recent developments in the philosophy of mathematics (after 1950). This includes the debate about the metaphysics of mathematical objects, in particular, whether there are any (realism) or not (nominalism), and the status of mathematical truths; structuralism in mathematics; mathematical explanation; and empiricist and naturalist ap- proaches to mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Abstraction*
    THE METAPHYSICS AND EPISTEMOLOGY OF ABSTRACTION* CRISPIN WRIGHT University of St. Andrews & New York University 1 Paul Benacerraf famously wondered1 how any satisfactory account of mathematical knowledge could combine a face-value semantic construal of classical mathematical theories, such as arithmetic, analysis and set-the- ory – one which takes seriously the apparent singular terms and quantifiers in the standard formulations – with a sensibly naturalistic conception of our knowledge-acquisitive capacities as essentially operative within and subject to the domain of causal law. The problem, very simply, is that the entities apparently called for by the face-value construal – finite cardinals, reals and sets – do not, seemingly, participate in the causal swim. A re- finement of the problem, due to Field, challenges us to explain what reason there is to suppose that our basic beliefs about such entities, encoded in standard axioms, could possibly be formed reliably by means solely of what are presumably naturalistic belief-forming mechanisms. These prob- lems have cast a long shadow over recent thought about the epistemology of mathematics. Although ultimately Fregean in inspiration, Abstractionism – often termed ‘neo-Fregeanism’ – was developed with the goal of responding to them firmly in view. The response is organised under the aegis of a kind of linguistic – better, propositional – ‘turn’ which I suggest it is helpful to see as part of the content of Frege’s Context Principle. The turn is this. It is not that, before we can understand how knowledge is possible of statements re- ferring to or quantifying over the abstract objects of mathematics, we need to understand how such objects can be given to us as objects of acquaint- ance or how some other belief-forming mechanisms might be sensitive to them and their characteristics.
    [Show full text]