Richard Rorty's Liberalism : a Marxist Perspective

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Richard Rorty's Liberalism : a Marxist Perspective University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1997 Richard Rorty's liberalism : a Marxist perspective. Markar. Melkonian University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Melkonian, Markar., "Richard Rorty's liberalism : a Marxist perspective." (1997). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2299. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2299 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RICHARD RORTY'S LIBERALISM A MARXIST PERSPECTIVE A Dissertation Presented by MARKAR MELKON1AN Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY February 1997 Philosophy © Copyright by Markar Melkoman 1997 All Rights Reserved RICHARD RORTY’S LIBERALISM A MARXIST PERSPECTIVE A Dissertation Presented by MARKAR MELKONIAN Approved as to style and content by: 4 Thomas Wartenburg, Member /lyCX' Robert Paul Wolff, Mempe, John Robison, Department Head Department of Philosophy ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank the members of my committee, John Brentlinger, Ann Ferguson, Tom Wartenberg and Robert Paul Wolff for their help. 1 want to thank Kanchana Mahadevan for her encouragement, Richard Rorty for his assistance, and John Brentlinger again for his unusual forbearance, as well as advice that spared me much trouble. Finally, 1 want to thank Suzy Melkoman for her unusual patience. This dissertation is dedicated to Charles and Zabelle Melkoman, in loving memory of Monte. IV ABSTRACT RICHARD RORTY’S LIBERALISM A MARXIST PERSPECTIVE FEBRUARY 1997 MARKAR MELKON1AN, A.B., UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LOS ANGELES M.A., SAN FRANCISCO STATE UNIVERSITY M.A., UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Ph D., UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Directed by: Professor John Brentlinger A sympathetic reviewer has noted that the best a critic of Rorty can do is to compare his views invidiously to alternative views. Taking this advice to heart, I contrast Rorty' s social and political views to Dewey's, and then to an alternative account which I elaborate. My standards of comparison are two liberal ideals than according which, to Rorty, none others are higher. These are. ( 1 ) amelioration of suffering, and (2) leaving people alone to pursue their own visions of personal perfection. In Chapter One, I point out that there are significant differences between Rorty and his alleged progenitor, Dewey, notably when it comes to their respective conceptions of how to harmonize personal freedom with public responsibility. Unlike Dewey, Rorty advocates abandoning the attempt to fuse the public realm of altruism and the private realm of sublimity by means of one all-encompassing theory. In Chapter Two, 1 argue that the existing liberal democracies Rorty is concerned to defend bear little resemblance to his democratic utopia, in which "the quest for autonomy is impeded as little as possible by social institutions.” I introduce an alternative vocabulary, according to which political institutions, broadly conceived, traverse nearly the entire length and breadth of the private sphere in the north Atlantic democracies. In Chapter Three, 1 argue that existing liberal democracies fare little better with reference to Rorty's public ideal of ameliorating suffering than they did with reference to his private ideal of making room for self making. Then 1 suggest an alternative setup which I believe to be more promising for purposes of ameliorating suffering. In the final chapter, I argue that Rorty’s private role as ironist and his public role as self-described apologist for bourgeois liberal democracy are not so much incommensurable as they are incompatible. The better he fulfills one role, I argue, the more seriously he compromises the other. VI . TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS , v ABSTRACT . V Chapter INTRODUCTION 1 Framing the Conversation 4 Three Anti-Isms 10 Rorty’s“We’s” 24 1 DEPARTURES FROM DEWEY 35 Dewey and the Public/Private Split 38 Dewey on Liberty and Democracy 49 Rorty on Liberty and Democracy 60 2. THE ELUSIVE IDEAL OF FREEDOM 85 Depicting the Apolitical Private Sphere 88 State Power and the Private Sphere 97 Privatization and Socialism 113 Private Selfhood and Ideology 129 3. THE ILLUSIVE IDEAL OF DECENCY 143 Liberalism and Suffering 146 The Solemn Complement of Liberal Ideals 154 Going beyond Liberalism 168 4. OF LIGHT MINDS AND HEAVY HANDS 176 Rorty’s Politics 176 Rorty’ s Incompatible Roles 196 BIBLIOGRAPHY 214 vii . INTRODUCTION Until recently, the best known liberal thinkers from Locke to the present have imagined liberalism as standing on “the grounding in natural law, the appeal to the light of reason, the evocation of homo humanus Their opponents, from Robert 2 Filmer to the Frankfurters, have disputed this characterization. Critics both on the right and the left have endeavored to show that Reason does not dictate the practices and institutions associated with liberalism and human nature does not 2. legitimate them, the assumption being that this in itself constitutes a definitive indictment of liberalism. In recent years, however, some self-described liberals themselves have abandoned the familiar philosophical rationales for their tradition. While conceding that liberalism is no more rooted in universal reason or human nature than any other 1 ) Comay, p. 120. A wide variety of beliefs and authors have been associated in various contexts with the word liberal and its cognates. I will offer a few preliminary words of clarification forthwith and expand on them in Chapters One and Two. ) Refer to Filmer, pp. 251-308, and to Rorty's discussion of Horkheimer and Adorno in Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (henceforth CIS), pp. 56-7. All source references from Rorty's works are listed by title or abbreviated title and appear chronologically under the author’s entry in the bibliography below. All other references appear under the name of the author. political creed, they have nevertheless maintained their allegiance to liberal institutions and counseled others to do so, too. Richard Rorty may be counted among the latter category of liberal His particular defense of liberalism does not depend for its force on claims to be grounded in reason, or on epistemological guarantees or transcultural and ahistoncal notions of human nature. He tells us he wants to “retain Enlightenment liberalism while dropping Enlightenment 4 rationalism.” Thus, what he has to say in defense of liberalism is likely to be received with sympathy by an audience which, having read lots of books by, say, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault and the communitarians, has come to doubt still-prevalent enlightenment assumptions about human nature, community, historical progress and so on—assumptions which traditionally have been deployed to repel attacks against liberalism. Moreover, if it turns out that Rorty's case against Philosophy with a capital “P”~that is, roughly, his case against foundational ism, representationalism and essentialism discussed below in this mtroduction-is incompatible with alternative political and social views, then so much the worse for those alternative views. If, on the other hand, the discussion in the following pages succeeds in breaching Rorty’s defense of liberalism, then readers whom he has convinced to abandon more traditional defenses might well register this as a blow against liberalism per se. What is at stake in the present discussion, then, is the defensibility of liberalism when it is stripped of its familiar enlightenment rationales. 3.) Refer, for example, to Rorty, “Dewey between Hegel and Darwin,” p. 68, and to his paper, “Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism.” 4.) CIS, p. 57. 5 Rorty understands a liberal, in its occasional meaning borrowed from Judith Shklar, to be a person who thinks that ‘'cruelty is the worst thing we do.” He also uses liberal and its cognates to describe certain actual and imaginary' political set- ups. These include his preferred utopia, characterized by the public and private ideals introduced in Chapter One, as well as a number of existing institutions characteristic of what Rorty, following Roberto Unger, has dubbed the “rich North " f Atlantic ' democracies Rorty holds these institutions to be paradigmatically liberal. In the course ot this discussion, it will become increasingly clear that there are discrepancies between Judith Shklar's liberals and the institutions and practices ot the “rich North Atlantic democracies.” Before proceeding to examine Rorty’s defense of liberalism, a few words are in order to frame the discussion in relation to the larger body of his own writings on other topics. In the balance of this introduction, 1 will do several things: After saying a few more words in the first section about why it is worthwhile to take a serious look at Rorty’s social and political views, I will indicate gesturally in what 5. respect I agree with him and why. This will motivate the discussion in the chapters 6. that follow and help to narrow its scope. Remarks in the second section about his views on some chief concerns of analytic philosophy segue to related observations in the third and final
Recommended publications
  • Gifts Basket for Professor Grzegorz W. Kolodko
    „Ekonomista” 2019, nr 3 http://www.ekonomista.info.pl KONFERENCJE I SEMINARIA ANDRZEJ K. KOŹMIŃSKI* Gifts Basket for Professor Grzegorz W. Kolodko We are celebrating here two important anniversaries: Kozminski University’s 25th and Professor Grzegorz W. Kolodko’s 70th birthday. They are both young and hopeful. But Professor Kolodko seems younger. This is at least my impression when I try to follow his countless activities spanning around the globe. Birthdays are gifts’ time. Professor Kolodko has found by his bed two sizable baskets of gifts: one international and one Polish. In principle all the donors volunteered to bring their gifts personally. Unfortunately, some were hounded by bad luck with health prob- lems like Nuti, Galbraith Jr. or Phelps, others had to give priority to meetings with the highest authorities like Prof. Lin meeting President Xi exactly at this time, or to the call of duty like Saul Estrin who has a lecture at LSE. However, all the missing and missed contributors prepared videos, which will be shown and will be referred to in our debate. Because I do hope for a lively debate, you are all invited to. Today we are permitted to peep into the international baskets: special issue of Acta Oeconomica dedicated to Pro- fessor Kolodko and debate will be conducted in English. Tomorrow will be the Polish day referring to the sumptuous volume of 28 essays by top notch Polish economists, just of press by Polish Scientific publishers. To kick off our today’s debate, let me share with you some impressions I had when reading through this unique collection of scientific papers edited with care by promi- nent journal affiliated to the Hungarian Academy of Sciences.
    [Show full text]
  • Geuss-On-Rorty.Pdf
    Richard Rorty at Princeton: Personal Recollections RAYMOND GEUSS When i arrived in Princeton during the 1970s my addiction to tea was already long-standing and very well entrenched, but I was so concerned about the quality of the water in town that I used to buy large containers of allegedly “pure” water at Davidson’s—the local supermarket, which seems now to have gone out of business. I didn’t, of course, have a car, and given the amount of tea I consumed, the trans- port of adequate supplies of water was a highly labor-inten- sive and inconvenient matter. Dick and Mary Rorty must have noticed me lugging canisters of water home, because, with characteristic generosity, they developed the habit of call- ing around at my rooms in 120 Prospect, often on Sunday mornings, offering to take me by car to fill my water bottles at a hugely primitive and highly suspicious-looking outdoor water tap on the side of a pumphouse which was operated by the Elizabethtown Water Company on a piece of waste land near the Institute Woods. This pumphouse with its copiously dripping tap was like something out of Tarkhovski’s film about Russia after a nuclear accident, Stalker, and the sur- rounding area was a place so sinister one half expected to be attacked by packs of dogs in the final stages of radiation sick- ness or by troops of feral children who had been left by their parents to fend for themselves while the parents went off to the library to finish their dissertations.
    [Show full text]
  • Post-Truth Politics and Richard Rorty's Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism
    Ash Center Occasional Papers Tony Saich, Series Editor Something Has Cracked: Post-Truth Politics and Richard Rorty’s Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism Joshua Forstenzer University of Sheffield (UK) July 2018 Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation Harvard Kennedy School Ash Center Occasional Papers Series Series Editor Tony Saich Deputy Editor Jessica Engelman The Roy and Lila Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation advances excellence and innovation in governance and public policy through research, education, and public discussion. By training the very best leaders, developing powerful new ideas, and disseminating innovative solutions and institutional reforms, the Center’s goal is to meet the profound challenges facing the world’s citizens. The Ford Foundation is a founding donor of the Center. Additional information about the Ash Center is available at ash.harvard.edu. This research paper is one in a series funded by the Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation at Harvard University’s John F. Kennedy School of Government. The views expressed in the Ash Center Occasional Papers Series are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect those of the John F. Kennedy School of Government or of Harvard University. The papers in this series are intended to elicit feedback and to encourage debate on important public policy challenges. This paper is copyrighted by the author(s). It cannot be reproduced or reused without permission. Ash Center Occasional Papers Tony Saich, Series Editor Something Has Cracked: Post-Truth Politics and Richard Rorty’s Postmodernist Bourgeois Liberalism Joshua Forstenzer University of Sheffield (UK) July 2018 Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation Harvard Kennedy School Letter from the Editor The Roy and Lila Ash Center for Democratic Governance and Innovation advances excellence and innovation in governance and public policy through research, education, and public discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey Author(S): Richard Rorty Source: the Review of Metaphysics , Dec., 1976, Vol
    Overcoming the Tradition: Heidegger and Dewey Author(s): Richard Rorty Source: The Review of Metaphysics , Dec., 1976, Vol. 30, No. 2 (Dec., 1976), pp. 280-305 Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.com/stable/20126921 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Metaphysics This content downloaded from 132.174.255.116 on Sat, 27 Jun 2020 15:25:17 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms OVERCOMING THE TRADITION: HEIDEGGER AND DEWEY RICHARD RORTY I X HILOSOPHERS who envy scientists think that philosophy should deal only with problems formulated in neutral terms?terms satis factory to all those who argue for competing solutions. Without common problems and without argument, it would seem, we have no professional discipline, nor even a method for disciplining our own thoughts. Without discipline, we presumably have mysticism, or poetry, or inspiration?at any rate, something which permits an escape from our intellectual responsibilities. Heidegger is frequently
    [Show full text]
  • György Pápay: Pragmatism and the Ordinary: the Rorty-Putnam Debate
    PRAGMATISM AND THE ORDINARY: The Rorty-Putnam Debate from a Different Angle 1 György Pápay E-mail: [email protected] In his essay „Philosophy and Ordinary Experience” Stanley Rosen claims that when philosophers become increasingly interested in the question of the Ordinary— ordinary language or ordinary experience—it always indicates a crisis of philosophy. Both the phenomenological and the analytical school of modern philosophy included important thinkers who supposed that philosophical activity as such had reached a theoretical dead end, and therefore urged a return to the Ordinary. This enterprise itself can be carried out in a more or less theoretical way. The more theoretical approach is represented by Husserl or Heidegger. The less or sometimes even antitheoretical way of returning to the Ordinary is exemplified by Oxonian philosophers such as Ryle and Austin, and the later Wittgenstein. As Rosen adds, „Perhaps it would be fair to classify pragmatist like James and Dewey in this camp.” 2 Although the latter suggestion is not indisputable, I think Rosen has a point. If we put the scientistic vein aside that is common in some works of Peirce, Dewey and Sidney Hook, classical pragmatism with its firm critique of metaphysical dualisms and its emphasis on the practical character of human concerns could be seen as a philosophical movement that takes side with everyday life rather than pure theory. However, my aim is not to consider whether this classification of James and Dewey proves to be useful. I would rather focus on two influental contemporary pragmatists, Richard Rorty and Hilary Putnam, and especially on their relation to the question of the Ordinary.
    [Show full text]
  • The Liberal Imagination: Essays on Literature and Society Free
    FREE THE LIBERAL IMAGINATION: ESSAYS ON LITERATURE AND SOCIETY PDF Lionel Trilling,Louis Menand | 336 pages | 23 Oct 2008 | The New York Review of Books, Inc | 9781590172834 | English | New York, United States The Liberal Imagination - Wikipedia The Liberal Imagination: Essays on Literature and Society Liberal Imagination: Essays on Literature and Society is a collection of sixteen essays by American literary critic Lionel Trillingpublished by Viking in The book was edited by Pascal Covici, who had worked with Trilling when he edited and introduced Viking's Portable Matthew Arnold in The essays, then, represent Trilling's written work and critical thoughts of the s. In the essays, Trilling explores the theme of what he calls "liberalism" by looking closely at the relationship between literature, culture, mind, and the imagination. He offers passionate critiques against literary ideas of reality as material and physical, such as those he ascribes to V. ParringtonTheodore Dreiserand the writers of the Kinsey Reports. He supports writers who engage in "moral realism" through an engaged imagination and a "power of love," which he sees expressed in works by Henry JamesMark TwainTacitusF. Scott Fitzgeraldand William Wordsworth —and in the ideas of human nature in the works of Sigmund Freud. Blackmore, Norman Podhoretzand Delmore Schwartzrepresent the importance of this book to the "Intellectuals. Trilling argues that because his contemporary America is predominantly tending to an intellectually liberal tradition, the lack of a robust conservative intellectual tradition causes the lack of a cultural dialectic, making liberal ideas also weak. Trilling confronts the influence of literary critic V. Trilling argues that Parrington believed in a reality that is "immutable; it is wholly external, it is irreducible," and that Parrington believed the job of a literary writer to be the transmission of this reality by loyal reproduction.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIVERSITY of CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Romantic Liberalism
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE Romantic Liberalism DISSERTATION submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in English by Brent Lewis Russo Dissertation Committee: Professor Jerome Christensen, Chair Professor Andrea Henderson Associate Professor Irene Tucker 2014 Chapter 1 © 2013 Trustees of Boston University All other materials © 2014 Brent Lewis Russo TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS iii CURRICULUM VITAE iv ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION v INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER 1: Charles Lamb’s Beloved Liberalism: Eccentricity in the Familiar Essays 9 CHAPTER 2: Liberalism as Plenitude: The Symbolic Leigh Hunt 33 CHAPTER 3: Samuel Taylor Coleridge’s Illiberalism and the Early Reform Movement 58 CHAPTER 4: William Hazlitt’s Fatalism 84 ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I would like to thank Charles Rzepka and the Trustees of Boston University for permission to include Chapter One of my dissertation, which was originally published in Studies in Romanticism (Fall 2013). Financial support was provided by the University of California, Irvine Department of English, School of Humanities, and Graduate Division. iii CURRICULUM VITAE Brent Lewis Russo 2005 B.A. in English Pepperdine University 2007 M.A. in English University of California, Irvine 2014 Ph.D. in English with Graduate Emphasis in Critical Theory University of California, Irvine PUBLICATIONS “Charles Lamb’s Beloved Liberalism: Eccentricity in the Familiar Essays.” Studies in Romanticism. Fall 2013. iv ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Romantic Liberalism By Brent Lewis Russo Doctor of Philosophy in English University of California, Irvine, 2014 Professor Jerome Christensen, Chair This dissertation examines the Romantic beginnings of nineteenth-century British liberalism. It argues that Romantic authors both helped to shape and attempted to resist liberalism while its politics were still inchoate.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Rorty's Irony Seriously
    Humanities 2013, 2, 292–312; doi:10.3390/h2020292 OPEN ACCESS humanities ISSN 2076-0787 www.mdpi.com/journal/humanities Article Taking Rorty’s Irony Seriously Andrew Inkpin School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, University of Melbourne, Victoria 3010, Australia; E-Mail: [email protected] Received: 4 May 2013; in revised form: 26 May 2013 / Accepted: 6 June 2013 / Published: 12 June 2013 Abstract: Richard Rorty’s Contingency, Irony and Solidarity (CIS) is an ambitious and provocative, but for many readers a deeply flawed work. This paper argues that many of its apparent flaws can be understood as integral to Rorty’s attempt to write a work of private, post-theoretical irony. The paper’s first section outlines the substantive theoretical claims about language, selfhood and community which Rorty proposes as an antiessentialist alternative to ‘metaphysics’. The second identifies three difficulties—residual dualism, conceptual problems with the public-private distinction, and the work’s self-referential consistency—which constitute serious, but obvious problems for those substantive claims. The third section argues that Rorty’s metaphilosophical discussion of ‘ironist theory’ suggests CIS should be read as a personal work of irony which eschews theoretical ambitions, showing how this is consistent with and provides a motive for accepting the presence of conspicuous difficulties. The final section considers how the work’s metaphilosophical views interact with its substantive theoretical claims. The work’s irony is interpreted as resulting from the tension between these, so as to coexist rather than conflict with Rorty’s enduring commitments to liberalism and pragmatism. Keywords: Rorty; irony; metaphilosophy; pragmatism; continental philosophy 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Lionel Trilling's Existential State
    Lionel Trilling’s Existential State Michael Szalay Death is like justice is supposed to be. Ralph Ellison, Three Days Before the Shooting IN 1952, LIONEL TRILLING ANNOUNCED THAT “intellect has associated itself with power, per- haps as never before in history, and is now conceded to be in itself a kind of power.” He was de- scribing what would be his own associations: his personal papers are littered with missives from the stars of postwar politics. Senator James L. Buckley admires his contribution to American let- ters. Jacob J. Javits does the same. Daniel Patrick Moynihan praises him as “the nation’s leading literary critic.” First Lady Jacqueline Kennedy writes from the White House, thanking him for the collection of D. H. Lawrence stories and hoping to see him again soon. Three years later, President Lyndon Johnson sends a telegram asking Trilling to represent him at the funeral of T. S. Eliot. Politicians liked having Trilling around. He confirmed their noble sense of mission as often as they praised him.1 Trilling’s accommodating relation to power alienated many of his peers, like Irving Howe and C. Wright Mills, and later provoked condemnations from historians like Christopher Lasch and MICHAEL SZALAY teaches American literature and culture at UC, Irvine, and is the author of New Deal Modernism and The Hip Figure, forthcoming from Stanford University Press. He is co-editor of Stanford’s “Post*45” Book Series. 1 Trilling thought that the political establishment embraced intellectuals because it was “uneasy with itself” and eager “to apologize for its existence by a show of taste and sensitivity.” Trilling, “The Situation of the American Intellectual at the Present Time,” in The Moral Obligation to Be Intelligent, ed.
    [Show full text]
  • James Kenneth Galbraith [email protected] Curriculum Vitae
    James Kenneth Galbraith [email protected] Curriculum Vitae Current Position: Lloyd M. Bentsen, Jr. Chair in Government/ Business Relations, Lyndon B. Johnson School of Public Affairs, and Professor of Government, The University of Texas at Austin. Experience: Chair, LBJ School Budget Council, 2002-2004. Director, Ph.D. program in Public Policy, 1995-1997; Professor, LBJ School of Public Affairs, 1990-2002, Associate Professor, 1986 - 1990; Visiting Associate 1985-86. Visiting Scholar, The Brookings Institution, 1985. Executive Director, Joint Economic Committee, Congress of the United States, 1981 - 1982; Deputy Director, 1983 - 1984. Economist, Committee on Banking, Finance and Urban Affairs, United States House of Representatives, 1975-76 and 1977-80. Lecturer, Department of Economics, University of Maryland, 1979-1980. Teaching Subjects: Inequality and Development; International Economics; Technical Change and Financial Crisis; Economics for Policy; History of Economic Thought. Research Fields: Inequality; Economic policy. Degrees: Почетного доктора наук, Plekhanov Russian University of Economics, 2017 Docteur Honoris Causa, Université Pierre Mendes-France, October 2010 Ph.D., Yale University, May 1981 M. Phil., Yale University, May 1978 M.A., Yale University, December 1977 A.B., Magna Cum Laude, Harvard University, June 1974. Academy: Socio Straniero dell’Accademia dei Lincei - Classe di Scienze Morali, Storiche e Filologiche (Categoria VII - Scienze Sociali e Politiche). Elected 2010. Awards: GPAC Faculty Awards: Best Taught Class, 2020. GPAC Faculty Awards: Best Course to Challenge Your Assumptions, 2020. GPAC Faculty Awards: Best Transition Online, 2020. Veblen-Commons Award, Association for Evolutionary Economics, 2020. Почетного профессора, Urals State University of Economics, 2018. Trustee, Economists for Peace and Security, Elected 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Hayley Levin ’
    Spotlight: Hayley Levin ’16 Hayley Levin ’16 was recently named Grinnell College Athlete of the Week, as well as the Midwest Conference Women’s Swimming and Diving Performer of the Week. She holds the fastest time in the Midwest Conference this season for the 100 fly and 200 IM, is ranked second in the 400 IM, 100 breast and 200 breast and has the third-fastest time in the 200 free and 200 fly. She also swims on several highly ranked relays. Photo by Saw Min Maw Why did you choose Grinnell College? I chose Grinnell because I got recruited for swimming, which was the first eye-opener I had to Grinnell. Also, the academics are amazing and I believe a liberal arts education is important to have. Another really cool thing that drew me to Grinnell was that I could create my own schedule and I wasn’t limited to certain topics. When did you begin swimming? I started swimming when I was nine through summer league. I actually did a bunch of other sports like ice-skating, gymnastics, softball and soccer. Eventually my mom said I needed to pick one and I just really loved being in the water. I just felt really good when I was in the water, so I stayed. What was a highlight of the team training trip to Florida this year? The Connecticut College meet, which was outside and we were able to race fast people. On a non-swimming note, we had a beach day, which was a day off. We got to hang out with the entire team the whole day and bury ourselves in sand and play elbow tag in the ocean.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Reflections on the Construct of Emancipatory Accounting: Shifting Meaning and the Possibilities of a New Pragmatism
    This is a repository copy of Some reflections on the construct of emancipatory accounting: Shifting meaning and the possibilities of a new pragmatism. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/111823/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Gallhofer, S. and Haslam, J. (2017) Some reflections on the construct of emancipatory accounting: Shifting meaning and the possibilities of a new pragmatism. Critical Perspectives on Accounting. ISSN 1045-2354 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cpa.2017.01.004 Article available under the terms of the CC-BY-NC-ND licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/) Reuse This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) licence. This licence only allows you to download this work and share it with others as long as you credit the authors, but you can’t change the article in any way or use it commercially. More information and the full terms of the licence here: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ SOME REFLECTIONS ON THE CONSTRUCT OF EMANCIPATORY ACCOUNTING: SHIFTING MEANING AND THE POSSIBILITIES OF A NEW PRAGMATISM Sonja Gallhofer (University of Glasgow)* Adam Smith Business School University of Glasgow University Avenue Glasgow. G12 8QQ Scotland, UK Jim Haslam (University of Sheffield) Sheffield University Management School University of Sheffield Crookesmoor Building Conduit Road Sheffield.
    [Show full text]