Moore's Paradox and Essential Indexicality

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Moore's Paradox and Essential Indexicality Moore’s Paradox and Essential Indexicality Woomin Park (Seoul National University) Draft (10-6-2019) 1. Introduction The aim of this paper is to argue that Moore’s paradox stands for Essential Indexicality because it occurs only when self-reference appears, and thus, for the case of Moore’s paradox, to contend that it is not possible to construct a case of the Frege counterpart that Herman Cappelen and Josh Dever assert as a counterexample to John Perry’s Essential Indexical. In their recent book, The Inessential Indexical: On the Philosophical Insignificance of Perspective and the First Person (Cappelen and Dever 2013), Cappelen and Dever show that there is opacity in the indexical in the case of behavior explanation, but exactly the same kind of opacity between the co- referring expressions also holds in the third person case. They argue that the opacity in the case of indexical does not necessarily hold the special status of the indexicality (or first-person) because of the more general latter opacity. According to them, Perry’s Essential Indexical, contrary to its name, does not address the nature of indexical but suggests that there is a failure of truth-preserving substitution between the indexical and their co-referring expressions in attitude-context. Because, in those cases, the difference between one sentence and the other is, after all, a difference in the cases of Frege’s puzzle. In the case where the Essential Indexical is considered to have emerged, they claim that it is possible to present a counterpart (Frege Counterpart) that is the same in all respects except that it occurs between two co-referring expressions, not between the indexical and its co-referring expressions. Cappelen and Dever write that they provide (and can provide) the Frege Counterpart to all possible Perry-style cases that Essential Indexicals are present, but I think there is a case they haven't dealt with yet. This is the case of Moore's Paradox, which many philosophers thought is the example of the first- person personality (e.g., Moran 1997). Moore’s paradox is widely regarded as a typical example of the peculiarity of the first-person, but curiously, they did not address Moore’s paradox in their discussions that deny the philosophical significance of the first-person view. Against their thesis, I will contend that the indexical (or first-person) still seems to have a special status, based on Moore’s Paradox. When self-reporting on belief attribution, it sounds strange to say “p” and then say, “I don’t believe p.” This paradoxical situation only occurs when one uses a sentence with the first-person indexical that reports his attribution of belief in p. With my analysis of Moore’s paradox presented in this paper, we will see Moore’s paradox only happens with self-reference and then the inability to remove the indexical or first-person perspectives. If Moore’s paradox does not occur without self-reference, the case of Moore’s paradox is a failure of substitution that occurs only when Moore’s Paradox and Essential Indexicality 1 the indexical is involved even if it is a failure of truth-preserving substitutions between co-referring expressions. I will argue, in the case of Moore’s paradoxical absurdity, there is no Frege Counterpart, such as a failure to replace between co-referring expressions where the same absurdity is a problem. In the end, I will conclude this suggests the peculiarity and irremovability of the first-person view. 2. Preliminaries: Perry’s Messy Shopper & the Problem of Essential Indexical Many philosophers believe that John Perry’s monumental article “The Problem of the Essential Indexical” (Perry 1979/2000) showed this: it convincingly argues that some beliefs, such as self- locating belief, that use indexical to refer themselves, have some conceptual element that is not explained only by its propositional content. Let us consider two men along Perry who have almost similar belief systems. The situation is this: They believed that “one of us is making a mess” and “anyone who makes a mess should stop making the mess.” In fact, one of them, John Perry, bought perforated sugar sacks, so he unwittingly puts it in a shopping cart and wanders around. Based on their observations, they believed that the shopper with holey sugar bags is making a mess. No one stopped at those beliefs alone. Looking around, they found out that “John Perry is making a mess.” Then one person stopped the cart. If the situation is the above, their belief systems would eventually be the same. However, what do you find out that if one person stopped making a mess, why would it be? Perhaps, the person who stopped would have stopped because he thought he was John Perry. Without it, he would not have reached the point where the messer had to stop and would still be making messes. Observations like this seem to make it difficult to regard belief-attribution as merely a simple binary relation between propositions and epistemic subjects, regardless of relations to any referential element. Consider two cases of a simple binary relation between propositions and subjects, de re relation and de dicto relation. In the case with de re relation between propositions and subjects, there is no distinction between the relation of the subject with “the shopper with holey sugar bags making a mess” and the relation of the subject with “John Perry is making a mess.” If so, how can we explain the case why the mess- stopping event occurred when he had the latter belief? At first, Perry did not consider “The shopper with holey sugar bags making a mess” as the proposition about himself. After believing that “John Perry is making a mess,” he regards “John Perry is making a mess” as the proposition about himself, and then he could conclude that "John Perry should stop." Moore’s Paradox and Essential Indexicality 2 Since John Perry stopped when he came to the latter belief, one could expect to explain this situation if the subject is related to the proposition in de dicto fashion where these beliefs can be distinguished naturally. However, if we are dealing with the case de dicto here, Perry believes in both beliefs at the same time but does not have the belief that I am making a mess. So, if Perry does not believe in “I’m a shopper with perforated sugar bags” or “I’m John Perry,” he cannot draw conclusions like “I should stop” from the first two beliefs. After all, de dicto relation is not a solution to this situation and must be appealed to the indexicality. In both approaches, we do not seem to be able to explain this situation without appealing to something like “what I regard as a proposition about myself” or “what I regard as content about myself.” In the end, the idea that this belief is de dicto or de re relation to the proposition does not seem to explain sufficiently the messy shopper case because it does not reflect the difference between the case with and without the indexicality. In addition, if John Perry says, “I made a mess,” he expresses that he believes in a Russellian proposition <John Perry, making a mess>. But the other believes that same Russellian proposition, expressed by the belief report “John Perry has made a mess.” Naturally, those who believe in the same proposition and make claims about it, but who are not John Perry, will hold it is false that “I make a mess.” The proposition corresponding to this man’s claim “I make a mess” is not about John Perry, but about himself and is therefore false. If so, the sentence “I make a mess” does not seem to identify some particular proposition. This shows that the belief report, such as “I believe I make a mess,” does not have enough information that it is a belief-report on some particular proposition. Obviously, the propositional content of the beliefs shared by the two men in our example seems to be the same, but there seems to be a difference in the way in which the subject is related to propositional content. According to Perry, one breakthrough in solving this problem is to provide an explanation for it. In other words, it explains that any belief in the same proposition can be in a different state of belief if it is believed in a different way. Anyone can believe the proposition, <John Perry, making a mess> but only John Perry can have a state of belief that states, “I made a mess.” When we have this type of belief in ourselves, we say that we have an indexical or de se belief. Because of that, he would have stopped making a mess. According to de re relation approach or the Russell propositional approach so far, we have the same belief in both cases when the indexical is replaced by a co-referring expression, just as when indexical has included in belief. However, when we have belief using the indexical, we have belief by means of some particular way, that is, an indexical way. If such indexicals are indispensable to describe some propositional attitude we have correctly, then the indexical used in that case can be called an Essential Indexical, and the phenomenon that emerges is called an Essential Indexicality. Moore’s Paradox and Essential Indexicality 3 3. Cappelen and Dever: No Essential Indexical or Indexicality Perry, discussed in Section 2, contended that in the Self-Locating Belief, belief acquired by using Indexicals that directs believer himself, there is a conceptual element that is not explained solely by its propositional content.
Recommended publications
  • Curriculum Vitae John R. Perry Email: [email protected] Born: 16 January 1943 in Lincoln, Nebraska Address: 545 Hilbar Lane
    Curriculum Vitae John R. Perry Email: [email protected] Born: 16 January 1943 in Lincoln, Nebraska Address: 545 Hilbar Lane, Palo Alto, CA 94303 Websites: http://www.john.jperry.net http://www-csli.stanford.edu/groups/center-explanation-consciousness http://www.structuredprocrastination.com/ http://www.philosophytalk.org/ Education 1968 Ph.D., Philosophy, Cornell University 1964 B.A., Philosophy, Doane College Appointments Spring, 2015 Visiting Professor, University of California, Berkeley 2014-- Professor Emeritus, University of California, Riverside 2009 --2014 Distinguished Professor (50%), University of California, Riverside. 2009-- Professor Emeritus, Stanford (recalled halftime through 2010-11) 2000-2001 Chair, Department of Philosophy 1993–99 Director, Center for the Study of Language and Information 1990–1991 Chair, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University 1985– 2008 Henry Waldgrave Stuart Professor of Philosophy, Stanford University 1985–1986 Director, Center for the Study of Language and Information 1977– 2008 Full Professor, Philosophy, Stanford University 1976–1982 Chair, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University 1974–1977 Associate Professor, Philosophy, Stanford University 1972–1974 Associate Professor, Philosophy, University of California, Los Angeles 1971–1972 Visiting Assistant Professor, Philosophy, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor 1968–1972 Assistant Professor, Philosophy, University of California, Los Angeles Fellowships, Honors, Recent Lectures 2014 Romanell Lecturer, American Philosophical Association
    [Show full text]
  • In the “The Problem of the Essential Indexical” John Perry Presents The
    1 Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), 191-200. Penultimate Draft DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre In this paper I examine an argument that has been made by Patrick Grim for the claim that de se knowledge is incompatible with the existence of an omniscient being. I claim that the success of the argument depends upon whether it is possible for someone else to know what I know in knowing (F), where (F) is a claim involving de se knowledge. I discuss one reply to this argument, proposed by Edward Wierenga, that appeals to first-person propositions and argue that this response is unsuccessful. I then consider David Lewis‟s theory of de se attitudes involving the self-ascription of properties. I claim that, according to this theory, there are two senses in which someone else can know what I know in knowing (F). I then argue that the second sense allows for the compatibility of de se knowledge with the existence of an omniscient being. Consider the following case:1 I am at a pool party and around the pool are several burning torches. At some point, I smell the distinct smell of burning hair and I come to know that someone‟s hair is on fire. I then see a reflection in the water of an individual whose hair is on fire and I come to know of this individual that his hair is on fire. Next I realize that everyone is pointing and shouting at me. I suddenly realize: (F) My hair is on fire! 1 2 When I come to realize (F), my behavior changes drastically; I jump into the pool in order to extinguish the flames.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 1000, Spring 2017
    INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHY 1000, SPRING 2017 SECTION 001 MWF, 10:00, VAC 1B90 INSTRUCTOR Jonathan Spelman [email protected] https://www.chalkup.co/course/585dcc64281f930800a658cb/trending COURSE DESCRIPTION This course introduces students to some of the central questions in philosophy and identifies some potential answers to them. For example, we consider epistemological questions such as whether we can trust our senses and, more generally, whether we can know anything. We consider metaphysical questions such as whether God exists and whether we could survive the death of our bodies. Finally, we consider normative questions such as whether we have a moral obligation to donate money to famine relief and whether it is morally wrong to buy and eat factory-farmed meat, pollute the environment, and/or play violent video games. Along the way, this course helps students develop the philosophical skills they need to answer these questions. In particular, it helps students to construct and evaluate arguments, devise thought experiments and counterexamples, and develop intellectual courage, empathy, and humility. OFFICE HOURS I will hold office hours on Mondays from 11:00a-12:45p and Wednesdays from 2:00p-3:45p in Hellems 15. I am also available by appointment. REQUIRED TEXTS • Course Pack • John Perry, A Dialogue on Personal Identity and Immortality. Hackett, 1978. • René Descartes, Discourse on Method and Meditation on First Philosophy, translated by Donald A. Cress, 4th ed., Hackett, 1999. TECHNOLOGY POLICY Studies show that students who write their notes retain more information than those who type their notes (see, for example, http://www.npr.org/2016/04/17/474525392/attention-students-put- your-laptops-away).
    [Show full text]
  • Identity and Self-Knowledge
    Philos Theor Pract Biol (2017) 9:5 special issue Identity and Self-Knowledge John Perry∗ Self, person, and identity are among the concepts most central to the way humans think about themselves and others. It is often natural in biology to use such concepts; it seems sensible to say, for example, that the job of the immune system is to attack the non-self, but sometimes it attacks the self. But does it make sense to borrow these concepts? Don’t they only pertain to persons, beings with sophisticated minds, and perhaps even souls? I argue that if we focus on the every-day concepts of self and identity, and set aside loftier concepts found in religion, philosophy, and psychology that are applicable, at most, to humans, we can see that self and identity can be sensibly applied widely in biology. Keywords self • self-knowledge • identity • person • personal identity • unity-relation • process philosophy Part of a special issue, Ontologies of Living Beings, guest-edited by A. M. Ferner and Thomas Pradeu Editorial introduction: John Perry works primarily in logic, metaphysics and the philos- ophy of mind—and this essay is a contribution to a sub-field in the latter: self-knowledge. How do we have, and how do we understand, knowledge of ourselves and of our own men- tal states? While initially this might seem quite far removed from the focus of this special issue, there are two important reasons for including his piece here. Firstly, the essay sets out and examines different uses of the term ‘self ’ and ‘identity’ (alongside the related notion of ‘genidentity’).
    [Show full text]
  • 1 a REFUTATION of QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael
    1 To appear in M. O’Rourke and C. Washington (eds.), Situating Semantics: Essays on the Philosophy of John Perry (MIT Press) A REFUTATION OF QUALIA-PHYSICALISM Michael McKinsey Wayne State University Recent defenders of reductive physicalism such as Brian Loar (1990, 1997) and John Perry (2001) have adopted an intriguing new strategy:i (1) accept as so much common sense (nearly) everything that property-dualists want to say about sensory qualia, including the central claims that sensory qualia determine ‘what it’s like’ to have a given sense experience, and that persons are directly aware of these qualia in the having of such experiences; (2) contend that while these common sense facts about qualia may show that our ways of thinking and speaking about qualia are conceptually different from our ways of thinking and speaking about physical properties of the brain, these facts do not show that sensory qualia themselves (as opposed to our ways of thinking and speaking about them) are distinct from physical properties of the brain; (3) use this contention to turn aside the few existing arguments against reductive physicalism by such property dualists as Kripke (1972), Nagel (1974), Jackson (1982), and Chalmers (1996); and finally (4) insist that sensory qualia are in fact just identical with physical properties of the brain, so that consequently, the facts about the sensory qualities of conscious experience are nothing over and above physical facts about the brain. I will call the view that incorporates this strategy ‘qualia-physicalism’, or ‘Q-physicalism’ for short. In this paper I will argue that Q-physicalism is false.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moral Self Summer 2011
    The Moral Self Summer 2011 Description This course will examine the nature of moral status. First, we will ask what it takes to have moral status. Do you have to be alive? Sentient? Autonomous? Second, we will ask whether groups can have moral status. For example, do nations, species, ecosystems, etc. have moral rights and/or duties? Third, we will ask whether parts of individuals can have moral status. For example, if a person has multiple personality disorder (or multiple personalities in a non-pathological sense), do their personalities have moral duties to each other? And do we have moral duties to our past or future selves more generally? Finally, we will ask when in life moral status begins and ends. Do we have moral duties to embryos and corpses? What about past and future generations? General Information • Time: M/W 6:00-9:00 • Place: TISC LC1 • Instructor: Jeff Sebo • Email: jeff[email protected] • Office: 285 Mercer, #902 • Office hours: by appointment • Course website: jeffsebo.net/teaching/ 1 Readings The required books for this course are: • David DeGrazia, Human Identity and Bioethics • Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons • John Perry, A Dialogue on Personal Identity and Immortality You can find the required books at Bluestockings (172 Allen Street between Stanton and Rivington) as well as online. All readings not from the required book will be posted on blackboard. Grading Your grades will be determined as follows: • Papers (70%): You can write either two 10-page papers (35% each) or one 20-page paper (70%) on the topic of your choice.
    [Show full text]
  • Personal Identity and Immortality
    Personal Identity and Immortality I. Some Background (A) The Self The questions “Who am I?” “What am I?” and “Will I survive my bodily death?” are fundamental questions in human existence. Not surprisingly, however, they don’t admit of obvious or simple answers. As you will recall, Descartes argued that he was essentially a thinking thing or a mind (“sum res cogitans”) and that the mind could exist apart from the body. (That is, it is conceptually possible for the mind to exist apart from the body, and, therefore, presumably we have some philosophical wiggle-room for an afterlife.) As I have said, Descartes’s view led him to an ontology that many have considered unattractive. But there also be something odd in the idea that we can look inside ourselves and determine what or who we are. Consider the flaky saying, “I need (to go to California) to find myself.” What could possibly count as the thing to be found? What is one looking for? David Hume offered a brilliant critique of the idea that one kind find one’s self through introspection. “When I turn my reflection on myself, I never can perceive this self without some one or more perceptions; nor can I ever perceive any thing but the perceptions. It is the composition of these, therefore, which forms the self.” (Treatise, Appendix) In other words, we have no direct knowledge of or experience of the self; we only have knowledge of particular sensations, memories, and so on. We must suppose that there is something that underlies or bundles together these sensations, and that is the self.
    [Show full text]
  • Phenomenal Ways of Thinking*
    teorema Vol. XXVII/3, 2008, pp. 149-166 ISSN: 0210 - 1602 Phenomenal Ways of Thinking* Luca Malatesti RESUMEN Los argumentos a favor de la tesis de que las experiencias conscientes tienen propiedades no-físicas o qualia incluyen ciertas situaciones concebibles. El argumento del conocimiento de Frank Jackson toma en consideración a la hipotética científica Mary, quien a pesar de tener conocimiento científico completo de la visión del color, supuestamente carece de conocimiento de los qualia. Los argumentos mo- dales de Saul Kripke y David Chalmers incluyen zombis, criaturas concebibles que son físicamente idénticas a nosotros, pero carecen de qualia. Algunos fisicistas han respondido a estos argumentos mediante la réplica de los conceptos fenoménicos. Aunque sin tratar de socavar esta réplica en general, voy a argumentar que algunas versiones recientes de la misma, las propuestas por John Perry y David Papineau, no son satisfactorias. ABSTRACT Certain conceivable situations figure as premises in arguments for the conclu- sion that conscious experiences have non-physical properties or qualia. Frank Jack- son’s Knowledge Argument considers the hypothetical scientist Mary, who despite having complete scientific knowledge of colour vision, supposedly lacks knowledge of qualia. Both Saul Kripke’s and David Chalmers’ modal arguments involve zom- bies, conceivable creatures physically identical to us who lack qualia. Several physi- calists have replied to all these objections by endorsing the phenomenal concept reply. Without trying to undermine this reply in general, I argue that recent versions of it proposed by John Perry and David Papineau are unsatisfactory. I INTRODUCTION Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument aims to prove that scientific knowledge leaves out something about conscious experiences and, thus, that conscious experiences cannot have only physical properties.1 Saul Kripke (1971) and David Chalmers (1996) reach the same conclusion by means of modal arguments concerning the conceivability of creatures physically iden- tical to us who lack consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Pragmatics: an Inquiry Into Reference and Communication Kepa Korta and John Perry Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-76497-1 - Critical Pragmatics: An Inquiry into Reference and Communication Kepa Korta and John Perry Frontmatter More information Critical Pragmatics Critical Pragmatics develops three ideas: language is a way of doing things with words; meanings of phrases and contents of utterances derive ultimately from human intentions; and language combines with other factors to allow humans to achieve communicative goals. In this book, Kepa Korta and John Perry explain why critical pragmatics provides a coherent picture of how parts of language study fit together within the broader picture of human thought and action. They focus on issues about singular reference, that is, talk about particular things, places, or people, which have played a central role in the philosophy of language for more than a century. They argue that attention to the ‘reflexive’ or ‘utterance-bound’ contents of utterances shed new light on these old problems. Their important study proposes a new approach to pragmatics and should be of wide interest to philosophers of language and linguists. kepa korta is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of the Basque Country. He is the co-author (with John Perry) of articles in Mind and Language, Synthèse, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, and The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. john perry is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside and Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at Stanford Uni- versity. He is the author of The Problem of the Essential Indexical (1993; 2000), Reference and Reflexivity (2001), Knowledge, Possibility and Con- sciousness (2001), and Identity, Personal Identity and the Self (2002), and co-author (with Jon Barwise) of Situations and Attitudes (1983).
    [Show full text]
  • John Perry, KNOWLEDGE, POSSIBILITY, and CONSCIOUSNESS
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 22 Issue 1 Article 10 1-1-2005 John Perry, KNOWLEDGE, POSSIBILITY, AND CONSCIOUSNESS David M. Jehle Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Jehle, David M. (2005) "John Perry, KNOWLEDGE, POSSIBILITY, AND CONSCIOUSNESS," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 22 : Iss. 1 , Article 10. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200522140 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol22/iss1/10 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. BOOK REVIEWS 107 Knowledge, Possibility, and Consciousness, by John Perry. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 2001. Pp. xvi + 212. $29.95 (hardback), $15.00 (paper). DAVID M. JEHLE, Cornell University Physicalism is the view that actuality is exhausted by physical reality. It's the reigning orthodoxy in contemporary philosophy of mind. But it faces a formidable problem: the problem of the experience gap. We all undergo various phenomenal experiences-those experiences that have a feel, a what-it-is-like aspect to them. If physicalism is true, phenomenal experi­ ences are brain states or constituted by brain states. That strikes many as false. The reason, says John Perry: "the gap between what it is like and what brain states are like is simply too large" (14). There have been three prominent developments and variations on the experience gap argument: the zombie argument, the knowledge argu­ ment, and the modal argument.
    [Show full text]
  • Time, Fission, and Personal Identity
    Time, Fission, and Personal Identity John Perry Stanford University Abstract I argue that the account I gave of Derek Parfit’s dividing self-case in “Can the Self Divide?” does not depend on a dubious four-dimensionalist metaphysics as claimed by Eric Olson (2006). I explain my metaphysics of time, and then re-de- scribe my solution in “Can the Self Divide?” comparing it to treatments of the di- viding selves by Parfit and Lewis. Identity, Unity relation, Four-dimensionalism, Thoughts, Circumstances, Events, Person-stages. 1. Introduction Derek Parfit was a wonderful philosopher and an exemplary human being. The only opportunity I had to interact with him personally for any length of time was at a symposium at the University of North Carolina in the early 1970’s. Parfit, David Lewis, and I gave talks on personal identity, focused on the problems Parfit had raised in his watershed 1971 paper, “Personal Identity”.1 It was a thrill to meet and talk with Parfit, and I regret that our paths did not cross more often. David Lewis was already a good friend by then. I can’t remember a symposium I enjoyed more, or from which I learned so much. Parfit’s key examples were cases of fissioning or dividing selves. One person becomes two, both of whom have first-person memories and meet other criteria for being the same person as the original. But they can’t both be the original per- son, since are not each other. They go their different ways with no special access to each others’ minds.
    [Show full text]
  • U039 SEMANTICS, POSSIBLE-WORLDS John Perry
    U039 SEMANTICS, POSSIBLE-WORLDS John Perry Department of Philosophy Stanford University Stanford, CA 94305 [email protected] NOTES: 1. Logical symbols throughout. 2. Not sure how one is supposed to to point to required background (see note just after B-section). 3. This piece, along with SITUATION SEMANTICS, has been separated out from U039, SEMANTICS, MODEL-THEORETIC (6K words). Separated entries was the original idea, so I assume it will be ok to revert to that. Word count: approximately 3800 not including references. 1 U039 SEMANTICS, POSSIBLE-WORLDS John Perry Possible worlds semantics (PWS) is a family of methods that have been used to analyze a wide variety of intensional phe- nomena, including modality, conditionals, tense and temporal adverbs, obligation, and reports of informational and cognitive content. PWS spurred the development of philosophical logic and led to new applications of logic in computer science and ar- tificial intelligence. It revolutionized the study of the semantics of natural languages. PWS has inspired analyses of many con- cepts of philosophical importance, and the concept of a possible world has been at the heart of important philosophical systems. (See also POSSIBLE WORLDS, PHILOSOPHICAL ISSUES IN MODAL LOGIC, INTENSIONALITY, INTENSIONAL LOGIC, MODEL THEORY.) This entry assumes some familiarity with symbolic logic (see SYMBOLIC LOGIC). 1. Intensions Demeaned 2. Modal Logic 3. Other Applications 4. Temporal Logic 5. Conditional Logic 6. Quantified Modal Logic 7. Index Theory and Intensional Logic 2 8. Montague Semantics 9. Intensions Triumphant 10. All the Intensions We Need? 1 Intensions Demeaned Traditionally, the intension of a predicate was distinguished from its ex- tension; the former is a property, the latter is a set.
    [Show full text]