Aspasia and Socrates

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aspasia and Socrates AS ORIGENS DO PENSAMENTO OCIDENTAL THE ORIGINS OF WESTERN THOUGHT ARTIGO I ARTICLE Paideutikos eros: Aspasia as an ‘alter Socrates’ Francesca Pentassuglio i https://orcid.org/0000-0003-4034-9453 [email protected] i “Sapienza” Università di Roma – Roma – Italia PENTASSUGLIO, F. (2020). Paideutikos eros: Aspasia as an ‘alter Socrates’. Archai 30, e03015. Abstract: This paper focuses on the figure and the role of Aspasia in Aeschines’ eponymous dialogue, with special regard to the Milesian’s ‘paideutic’ activity and the double bond connecting it to Socrates’ teaching, namely the elenctic method and a particular application of Σωκρατικὸς ἔρως. The study aims to highlight some crucial traits of Aeschines’ Aspasia by examining three key texts, all numbered among the testimonies on the Aspasia: Cicero’s account in https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_30_15 [1] 2 Rev. Archai (ISSN: 1984-249X), n. 30, Brasília, 2020, e03015. De inventione 1.31.51-53 and two fundamental passages from Xenophon’s Memorabilia (2.3.36) and Oeconomicus (3.14). After analysing a set of ancient sources which repeatedly mention the close and personal association between Socrates and Aspasia (Plato, Maximus of Tyre, Plutarch, Theodoret of Cyrus), I will try to reconstruct the dialogical context of Xenophon’s testimonies and to combine them with Cicero’s account. My final aim is to clarify the role of Aspasia in Aeschines’ presentation of the Socratic theory of ἔρως. In pursuing this main objective, in the concluding section I will address two further issues: (1) Aspasia’s connection with the figure of Diotima, as depicted in the same ancient sources and (2) the relationship between Aspasias’ pedagogical use of ἔρως and that made by Socrates in the Alcibiades. Keywords: Aeschines’ Aspasia, Socrates, Socratic method, eros, paideia. Introduction Aeschines’ Aspasia was first defined as a “weblicher Sokrates” by Rudolf Hirzel (1895, vol. 1, p. 80), and since then the depiction of the Milesian as a “female Socrates” has been taken up by several scholars.1 Such a definition is basically drawn from Cicero’s account in De inventione 1.31.51-53, which reports a conversation between Aspasia, Xenophon and his wife. The aim of this study is to investigate the association between these two figures in depth, by paying special attention to their respective teaching activity, both in terms of the methodology adopted and of the content conveyed. In order to do so, in the first section I shall proceed to examine the main sources mentioning a personal association between Socrates and Aspasia, namely: Plato 1 The definition is adopted both by Kahn (1994, p. 101) and by Döring (2011, p. 31). PAIDEUTIKOS EROS: ASPASIA AS AN ‘ALTER SOCRATES’ 3 (Mx. 235e), Maximus of Tyre (Philosoph. 38.4), Plutarch (Per. 24.3) and Theodoret of Cyrus (Graec. aff. cur. 1.17). As we will see in a short while, some of these sources directly touch on the issue of the connection between the two figures of Aspasia and Diotima, to which I shall return in the final section. After having dealt with these portrayals of the Socrates-Aspasia relationship from a ‘biographical’ standpoint, I will outline some crucial traits of the figure and the teaching of Aspasia as portrayed in Aeschines’ eponymous dialogue. In this regard, less attention will be paid to testimonies on the Milesian’s role as an expert and a teacher of rhetoric. Important as they may be, both for the reconstruction of the content of the Aspasia and for their connections with Plato’s Menexenus, they don’t leave room for a direct comparison with the paideutic activity carried out by Socrates himself (at least as depicted by Aeschines in the Alcibiades).2 The analysis will thus be focused on two fundamental passages from Xenophon’s Memorabilia (2.3.36) and Oeconomicus (3.14): a preliminary examination of such passages may enrich our understanding of Cicero’s testimony. In this section of the paper, I will attempt to draw some conclusions about the method, content, and aim of Aspasia’s ‘paideutic intervention’, so as to proceed – in the concluding section – to compare it with the depiction of Socratic παιδεία Aeschines provides in the Alcibiades, and thus to investigate the double bond connecting Aspasias’ and Socrates’ teaching: the elenctic method and the (different) recourse to a παιδευτικὸς ἔρως. 2 We know of testimonies on Socrates’ activity (and even teaching) in the field of rhetoric: Diogenes Laertius (quoting Favorinus’ Miscellaneous History) says that “Socrates and his pupil Aeschines were the first to teach rhetoric” (2.20). In the same passage, Diogenes refers to some information we find in Xenophon (Mem. 1.2.31), according to which the Thirty forbade Socrates “to teach the art of words” (τέχνας διδάσκειν λόγων). 4 Rev. Archai (ISSN: 1984-249X), n. 30, Brasília, 2020, e03015. Aspasia and Socrates The ancient testimony on Socrates’ relationship with Aspasia which scholars are most familiar with is perhaps that by Plato in the Menexenus (235e), where Socrates himself declares Aspasia to be his “instructor” (διδάσκαλος) and “by no means weak in the art of rhetoric” (οὐ πάνυ φαύλη περὶ ῥητορικῆς; transl. by Lamb, 1925). Plato’s passage clearly makes reference to Aspasia’s expertise in the τέχνη ῥητορική. As is well-known, in the following lines he then mentions the case of Pericles, one of the “many fine orators” she has turned out. Both aspects find confirmation in the scholium to the dialogue3 according to which Aspasia not only made Pericles into an effective political orator,4 but succeeded in the same task with the sheep-merchant Lysicles. It may be argued5 that Lysicles’ political career (see Th. 3.19.1) offers even stronger evidence of Aspasia’s expertise as a teacher of rhetoric: while Pericles’ political success might be said to depend on his natural gifts and previous education, Aspasia’s influence on Lysicles – a man of humble origins and of no talent – would be undeniable. If we move beyond the testimonies dealing with Aspasias’ expertise in rhetoric, we find that the list of ancient sources mentioning a close and personal association between Socrates and Aspasia is much longer. According to Maximus of Tyre (Philosoph. 38.4 = VI A 66 SSR = 101 P.), not only did Socrates regularly visit Aspasia himself, but he also exhorted others to send her their sons: 3 Schol. in Pl. Mx. 235e: τὸν Λυσικλέα ῥήτορα δεινότατον κατεσκευάσατο, καθάπερ καὶ Περικλέα δημηγορεῖν παρεσκεύασεν. It is particularly telling that Aeschines’ Aspasia is mentioned among the sources of this information (VI A 66 SSR = 100 P.). The double numbering of the testimonies on Aeschines refers to the collections Socratis and Socraticorum Reliquiae (Giannantoni, 1990 = SSR) and Eschine di Sfetto. Tutte le testimonianze (Pentassuglio, 2017 = P.). 4 Cf. Philostr. Ep. 73 (VI A 65 SSR = 98 P.). As far as the relationship with Pericles is concerned, a fundamental testimony is provided by Plutarch, who inserts a long excursus on Aspasia (24.1 ff.) within the bios of Pericles. 5 This hypothesis has been put forward by Kahn (1994, p. 98-99; 1996, p. 25-26). PAIDEUTIKOS EROS: ASPASIA AS AN ‘ALTER SOCRATES’ 5 We often hear you insisting, Socrates, that you honour knowledge more than anything else, as you recommend the young each to a different teacher. After all, you encourage Callias to send his son to Milesian Aspasia’s, a man to an establishment run by a woman (εἰς γυναικὸς ἄνδρα); and you yourself, at your advanced age, go to her as a pupil. Nor is she enough for you: you assemble together expertise in love (τὰ ἐρωτικά) from Diotima, in music (τὰ μουσικά) from Connus, in poetry (τὰ ποιητικά) from Evenus, in farming (τὰ γεωργικά) from Ischomachus, and in geometry (τὰ γεωμετρικά) from Theodorus (transl. by Trapp, 1997). The passage hints at a well-known Socratic principle on education, stating that the most effective learning method is to associate with someone who is an expert in a specific field of knowledge (the idea can be found in Pl. La. 180 ff., in Ly. 209c ff. and particularly in X. Oec. 2.19; 3.16; 4.13 ff.).6 Now, within the list of ‘experts’ provided by Maximus of Tyre the name of Aspasia stands out,7 whose teachings Socrates recommended to Callias for his son Hipponicus. The passage is probably to be read in parallel with Atheneus’ testimony (5.220a-b = VI A 61 SSR = 92 P.), which seems to refer to the same context: Callias, as a rich man, is determined to provide his son with a good education and seeks advice from Socrates, who suggests he turn to Aspasia. Socrates’ familiarity with Aspasia is also mentioned by Plutarch, who in his Vita Periclis reports that “Socrates sometimes came to see her with his disciples (μετὰ τῶν γνωρίμων ἐφοίτα), and his intimate friends brought their wives to her to listen to her discourse” (24.3; transl. by Perrin, 1916, modified). Theodoret of Cyrus (Graec. aff. 6 Cf. Pl. Smp. 206b; 207c. See also Pl. Ap. 21c and 22b-c on the polemics against illusory knowledge; Ap. 24d; Cri. 44c-d; 46e; 47a; 48a on the criticism about the δόξα τῶν πολλῶν; Alc. 1 110e and La. 184e-185a on the opposition between δόξα and ἀλήθεια. 7 The reference can be connected to a passage from Lucian’s De saltatione (25), where it is said that Socrates “could stoop to learn wisdom from the mouth of an hetaira, Aspasia” (παρ’ ἑταίρας γυναικὸς οὐκ ἀπηξίου σπουδαῖόν τι ἀκούειν, τῆς Ἀσπασίας). 6 Rev. Archai (ISSN: 1984-249X), n. 30, Brasília, 2020, e03015. cur. 1.17) confirms the same: Socrates, the best of philosopher, did not consider it shameful to learn something helpful also from women (οὐδὲ παρὰ γυναικῶν μαθεῖν τι χρήσιμον ὑπέλαβε φιλοσοφίας ἀνάξιον); so he wasn’t ashamed of choosing Diotima as his teacher, and besides this he continued to associate with Aspasia (παρὰ τὴν Ἀσπασίαν διετέλει θαμίζων ).8 What we can infer from this set of sources is (1) that Socrates held Aspasia’s teachings in the highest regard9 and (2) that some authors connect the two figures of Aspasia and Diotima as Socrates’ ‘teachers’.
Recommended publications
  • The Trial and Death of Socrates : Being the Euthyphron, Apology, Crito, and Phaedo of Plato
    LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SAN DIEGO /?. (Boffcen THE TRIAL & DEATH OF SOCRATES *O 5' dve^Tcurroj /3toj ov /Siwrds cu>0p(j!nrip ' An unexamined life is not worth living.' (PLATO, Apol. 38 A. ) THE TRIAL AND DEATH OF SOCRATES BEING THE EUTHYPHRON, APOLOGY, CRITO, AND PH^EDO OF PLATO TRANSLATED INTO ENGLISH BY F. J. CHURCH, M.A. LONDON MACMILLAN AND CO. AND NEW YORK 1895 [ All rights reserved.] First Edition printed 1880 Second Edition, Golden Treasury Series, 1886 Reprinted 1887, 1888, 1890, 1891, 1892, March and September 1895 PREFACE. THIS book, which is intended principally for the large and increasing class of readers who wish to learn something of the masterpieces of Greek literature, and who cannot easily read them in Greek, was originally published by Messrs. Macmillan in a different form. Since its first appearance it has been revised and corrected throughout, and largely re- written. The chief part of the Introduction is new. It is not intended to be a general essay on Socrates, but only an attempt to explain and illustrate such points in his life and teaching as are referred to in these dialogues, which, taken by themselves, con- tain Plato's description of his great master's life, and work, and death. The books which were most useful to me in writing it are Professor Zeller's Socrates and the Socratic Schools, and the edition of the VI PREFACE. Apology by the late Rev. James Riddell, published after his death by the delegates of the Clarendon Press. His account of Socrates is singularly striking.
    [Show full text]
  • Alexander the Great and Hephaestion
    2019-3337-AJHIS-HIS 1 Alexander the Great and Hephaestion: 2 Censorship and Bisexual Erasure in Post-Macedonian 3 Society 4 5 6 Same-sex relations were common in ancient Greece and having both male and female 7 physical relationships was a cultural norm. However, Alexander the Great is almost 8 always portrayed in modern depictions as heterosexual, and the disappearance of his 9 life-partner Hephaestion is all but complete in ancient literature. Five full primary 10 source biographies of Alexander have survived from antiquity, making it possible to 11 observe the way scholars, popular writers and filmmakers from the Victorian era 12 forward have interpreted this evidence. This research borrows an approach from 13 gender studies, using the phenomenon of bisexual erasure to contribute a new 14 understanding for missing information regarding the relationship between Alexander 15 and his life-partner Hephaestion. In Greek and Macedonian society, pederasty was the 16 norm, and boys and men did not have relations with others of the same age because 17 there was almost always a financial and power difference. Hephaestion was taller and 18 more handsome than Alexander, so it might have appeared that he held the power in 19 their relationship. The hypothesis put forward here suggests that writers have erased 20 the sexual partnership between Alexander and Hephaestion because their relationship 21 did not fit the norm of acceptable pederasty as practiced in Greek and Macedonian 22 culture or was no longer socially acceptable in the Roman contexts of the ancient 23 historians. Ancient biographers may have conducted censorship to conceal any 24 implication of femininity or submissiveness in this relationship.
    [Show full text]
  • Who Freed Athens? J
    Ancient Greek Democracy: Readings and Sources Edited by Eric W. Robinson Copyright © 2004 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd The Beginnings of the Athenian Democracv: Who Freed Athens? J Introduction Though the very earliest democracies lildy took shape elsewhere in Greece, Athens embraced it relatively early and would ultimately become the most famous and powerful democracy the ancient world ever hew. Democracy is usually thought to have taken hold among the Athenians with the constitutional reforms of Cleisthenes, ca. 508/7 BC. The tyrant Peisistratus and later his sons had ruled Athens for decades before they were overthrown; Cleisthenes, rallying the people to his cause, made sweeping changes. These included the creation of a representative council (bode)chosen from among the citizens, new public organizations that more closely tied citizens throughout Attica to the Athenian state, and the populist ostracism law that enabled citizens to exile danger- ous or undesirable politicians by vote. Beginning with these measures, and for the next two centuries or so with only the briefest of interruptions, democracy held sway at Athens. Such is the most common interpretation. But there is, in fact, much room for disagree- ment about when and how democracy came to Athens. Ancient authors sometimes refer to Solon, a lawgiver and mediator of the early sixth century, as the founder of the Athenian constitution. It was also a popular belief among the Athenians that two famous “tyrant-slayers,” Harmodius and Aristogeiton, inaugurated Athenian freedom by assas- sinating one of the sons of Peisistratus a few years before Cleisthenes’ reforms - though ancient writers take pains to point out that only the military intervention of Sparta truly ended the tyranny.
    [Show full text]
  • The Poverty of Socratic Questioning: Asking and Answering in the Meno
    University of Cincinnati University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications Faculty Articles and Other Publications College of Law Faculty Scholarship 1994 The oP verty of Socratic Questioning: Asking and Answering In The eM no Thomas D. Eisele University of Cincinnati College of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.uc.edu/fac_pubs Part of the Legal Education Commons Recommended Citation Eisele, Thomas D., "The oP verty of Socratic Questioning: Asking and Answering In The eM no" (1994). Faculty Articles and Other Publications. Paper 36. http://scholarship.law.uc.edu/fac_pubs/36 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Law Faculty Scholarship at University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Articles and Other Publications by an authorized administrator of University of Cincinnati College of Law Scholarship and Publications. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE POVERTY OF SOCRATIC QUESTIONING: ASKING AND ANSWERING IN THE MEND Thomas D. Eisele* I understand [philosophy 1 as a willingness to think not about some­ thing other than what ordinary human beings think about, but rather to learn to think undistractedly about things that ordinary human beings cannot help thinking about, or anyway cannot help having occur to them, sometimes in fantasy, sometimes asa flash across a landscape; such things, for example, as whether we can know the world as it is in itself, or whether others really know the nature of one's own experiences, or whether good and bad are relative, or whether we might not now be dreaming that we are awake, or whether modern tyrannies and weapons and spaces and speeds and art are continuous with the past of the human race or discontinuous, and hence whether the learning of the human race is not irrelevant to the problems it has brought before itself.
    [Show full text]
  • De Theognide Megarensi. Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara. a Bilingual Edition
    FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE De Theognide Megarensi Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara – A Bilingual Edition – Translated by R. M. Kerr THE NIETZSCHE CHANNEL Friedrich Nietzsche De Theognide Megarensi Nietzsche on Theognis of Megara A bilingual edition Translated by R. M. Kerr ☙ editio electronica ❧ _________________________________________ THE N E T ! " # H E # H A N N E $ % MM&' Copyright © Proprietas interpretatoris Roberti Martini Kerrii anno 2015 Omnia proprietatis iura reservantur et vindicantur. Imitatio prohibita sine auctoris permissione. Non licet pecuniam expetere pro aliquo, quod partem horum verborum continet; liber pro omnibus semper gratuitus erat et manet. Sic rerum summa novatur semper, et inter se mortales mutua vivunt. augescunt aliae gentes, aliae invuntur, inque brevi spatio mutantur saecla animantum et quasi cursores vitai lampada tradiunt. - Lucretius - - de Rerum Natura, II 5-! - PR"#$CE %e &or' presente( here is a trans)ation o* #rie(rich Nietzsche-s aledi!tionsarbeit ./schoo) e0it-thesis12 *or the "andesschule #$orta in 3chu)p*orta .3axony-$nhalt) presente( on 3epte4ber th 15678 It has hitherto )arge)y gone unnotice(, especial)y in anglophone Nietzsche stu(- ies8 $t the ti4e though, the &or' he)pe( to estab)ish the reputation o* the then twenty year o)( Nietzsche and consi(erab)y *aci)itate( his )ater acade4ic career8 9y a)) accounts, it &as a consi(erab)e achie:e4ent, especial)y consi(ering &hen it &as &ri;en: it entai)e( an e0pert 'no&)e(ge, not =ust o* c)assical-phi)o)ogical )iterature, but also o* co(ico)ogy8 %e recent =u(ge4ent by >"+3"+ .2017<!!2< “It is a piece that, ha( Nietzsche ne:er &ri;en another &or(, &ou)( ha:e assure( his p)ace, albeit @uite a s4a)) one, in the history o* Ger4an phi)o)ogyB su4s the 4atter up quite e)o@uently8 +ietzsche )ater continue( his %eognis stu(ies, the sub=ect o* his Crst scho)ar)y artic)e, as a stu(ent at Leip,ig, in 156 D to so4e e0tent a su44ary o* the present &or' D a critical re:ie& in 156!, as &e)) as @uotes in se:eral )e;ers *ro4 1567 on.
    [Show full text]
  • The Roles of Solon in Plato's Dialogues
    The Roles of Solon in Plato’s Dialogues Dissertation Presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Samuel Ortencio Flores, M.A. Graduate Program in Greek and Latin The Ohio State University 2013 Dissertation Committee: Bruce Heiden, Advisor Anthony Kaldellis Richard Fletcher Greg Anderson Copyrighy by Samuel Ortencio Flores 2013 Abstract This dissertation is a study of Plato’s use and adaptation of an earlier model and tradition of wisdom based on the thought and legacy of the sixth-century archon, legislator, and poet Solon. Solon is cited and/or quoted thirty-four times in Plato’s dialogues, and alluded to many more times. My study shows that these references and allusions have deeper meaning when contextualized within the reception of Solon in the classical period. For Plato, Solon is a rhetorically powerful figure in advancing the relatively new practice of philosophy in Athens. While Solon himself did not adequately establish justice in the city, his legacy provided a model upon which Platonic philosophy could improve. Chapter One surveys the passing references to Solon in the dialogues as an introduction to my chapters on the dialogues in which Solon is a very prominent figure, Timaeus- Critias, Republic, and Laws. Chapter Two examines Critias’ use of his ancestor Solon to establish his own philosophic credentials. Chapter Three suggests that Socrates re- appropriates the aims and themes of Solon’s political poetry for Socratic philosophy. Chapter Four suggests that Solon provides a legislative model which Plato reconstructs in the Laws for the philosopher to supplant the role of legislator in Greek thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT PLATO Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-54600-3 - Plato: Gorgias, Menexenus, Protagoras Edited by Malcolm Schofield Frontmatter More information CAMBRIDGE TEXTS IN THE HISTORY OF POLITICAL THOUGHT Series editors R AYMOND GEUSS Professor in Philosophy, University of Cambridge Q UENTIN SKINNER Professor of the Humanities, Queen Mary, University of London Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought is now firmly estab- lished as the major student textbook series in political theory. It aims to make available to students all the most important texts in the history of western political thought, from ancient Greece to the early twentieth century. All the familiar classic texts will be included, but the series seeks at the same time to enlarge the conventional canon by incorporating an extensive range of less well-known works, many of them never before available in a modern English edition. Wherever possible, texts are published in complete and unabridged form, and translations are specially commissioned for the series. Each vol- ume contains a critical introduction together with chronologies, biographical sketches, a guide to further reading and any necessary glossaries and text- ual apparatus. When completed the series will aim to offer an outline
    [Show full text]
  • Genesis 2–3 and Alcibiades's Speech in Plato's Symposium: a Cultural
    Page 1 of 6 Original Research Genesis 2–3 and Alcibiades’s speech in Plato’s Symposium: A cultural critical reading Author: The purpose of this article is to discuss some basic problems and methodological steps 1,2 Evangelia G. Dafni concerning the encounter between Hebrews and Greeks in the Classical period and its impact Affiliations: on the Hellenistic era. The relationship between the Old Testament and Ancient Greek 1Department of Ecclesiastical literature will be examined on the basis of Genesis 2–3 and Alcibiades’s speech in Plato’s and Social Theology, Faculty Symposium (212c–223d). The following considerations and models of interpretation can arise of Theology, Aristotle from the analysis of Alcibiades’s speech compared to M- and LXX-Genesis 2–3: (1) Ancient University of Thessaloniki, Greece Greek writers were familiar with Old Testament oral or written traditions through improvised translations. They prepared the way for the LXX and, in their compositions, were in dispute 2Department of Old with them although they do not make specific references to the Hebrews and their literature; Testament Studies, Faculty (2) Hebrew authors knew the works of Ancient Greek authors and used Greek philosophical of Theology, University of Pretoria, South Africa terminology which they creatively adapted to Semitic models; (3) Both models are possible. One should not rush to any decisions but examine each case individually, in the original Note: language. Professor Evangelia Dafni is a Research Associate of Professor Dirk Human in the Department of Old Testament Introduction Studies at the Faculty of Genesis 2–3 is of central importance for the anthropology of the Old Testament: It describes in Theology, University of Pretoria.
    [Show full text]
  • Marathon 2,500 Years Edited by Christopher Carey & Michael Edwards
    MARATHON 2,500 YEARS EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS BULLETIN OF THE INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SUPPLEMENT 124 DIRECTOR & GENERAL EDITOR: JOHN NORTH DIRECTOR OF PUBLICATIONS: RICHARD SIMPSON MARATHON – 2,500 YEARS PROCEEDINGS OF THE MARATHON CONFERENCE 2010 EDITED BY CHRISTOPHER CAREY & MICHAEL EDWARDS INSTITUTE OF CLASSICAL STUDIES SCHOOL OF ADVANCED STUDY UNIVERSITY OF LONDON 2013 The cover image shows Persian warriors at Ishtar Gate, from before the fourth century BC. Pergamon Museum/Vorderasiatisches Museum, Berlin. Photo Mohammed Shamma (2003). Used under CC‐BY terms. All rights reserved. This PDF edition published in 2019 First published in print in 2013 This book is published under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- NoDerivatives (CC-BY-NC-ND 4.0) license. More information regarding CC licenses is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Available to download free at http://www.humanities-digital-library.org ISBN: 978-1-905670-81-9 (2019 PDF edition) DOI: 10.14296/1019.9781905670819 ISBN: 978-1-905670-52-9 (2013 paperback edition) ©2013 Institute of Classical Studies, University of London The right of contributors to be identified as the authors of the work published here has been asserted by them in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. Designed and typeset at the Institute of Classical Studies TABLE OF CONTENTS Introductory note 1 P. J. Rhodes The battle of Marathon and modern scholarship 3 Christopher Pelling Herodotus’ Marathon 23 Peter Krentz Marathon and the development of the exclusive hoplite phalanx 35 Andrej Petrovic The battle of Marathon in pre-Herodotean sources: on Marathon verse-inscriptions (IG I3 503/504; Seg Lvi 430) 45 V.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: the Parent Analogy in Plato's Menexenus
    Dialogue http://journals.cambridge.org/DIA Additional services for Dialogue: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: The Parent Analogy in Plato's Menexenus Sandrine Berges Dialogue / Volume 46 / Issue 02 / March 2007, pp 211 - 230 DOI: 10.1017/S0012217300001724, Published online: 27 April 2009 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S0012217300001724 How to cite this article: Sandrine Berges (2007). Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: The Parent Analogy in Plato's Menexenus. Dialogue, 46, pp 211-230 doi:10.1017/S0012217300001724 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/DIA, IP address: 139.179.91.52 on 03 Dec 2015 Articles Virtue Ethics, Politics, and the Function of Laws: The Parent Analogy in Plato’s Menexenus SANDRINE BERGES Bilkent University ABSTRACT: Can virtue ethics say anything worthwhile about laws? What would a virtue-ethical account of good laws look like? I argue that a plausible answer to that question can be found in Plato’s parent analogies in the Crito and the Menexenus. I go on to show that the Menexenus gives us a philosophical argument to the effect that laws are just only if they enable citizens to flourish. I then argue that the result- ing virtue-ethical account of just laws is not viciously paternalistic. Finally, I refute the objection that the virtue-ethical account I am proposing is not distinct from a consequentialist account. RÉSUMÉ : Peut-on construire une théorie de la loi à partir de l’éthique de la vertu? Qu’est ce qu’une bonne loi?Je dis que l’on trouvera une réponse à la question dans l’analogie entre les lois et les parents présentée par Platon dans le Criton et le Ménéxène.
    [Show full text]
  • Citations in Classics and Ancient History
    Citations in Classics and Ancient History The most common style in use in the field of Classical Studies is the author-date style, also known as Chicago 2, but MLA is also quite common and perfectly acceptable. Quick guides for each of MLA and Chicago 2 are readily available as PDF downloads. The Chicago Manual of Style Online offers a guide on their web-page: http://www.chicagomanualofstyle.org/tools_citationguide.html The Modern Language Association (MLA) does not, but many educational institutions post an MLA guide for free access. While a specific citation style should be followed carefully, none take into account the specific practices of Classical Studies. They are all (Chicago, MLA and others) perfectly suitable for citing most resources, but should not be followed for citing ancient Greek and Latin primary source material, including primary sources in translation. Citing Primary Sources: Every ancient text has its own unique system for locating content by numbers. For example, Homer's Iliad is divided into 24 Books (what we might now call chapters) and the lines of each Book are numbered from line 1. Herodotus' Histories is divided into nine Books and each of these Books is divided into Chapters and each chapter into line numbers. The purpose of such a system is that the Iliad, or any primary source, can be cited in any language and from any publication and always refer to the same passage. That is why we do not cite Herodotus page 66. Page 66 in what publication, in what edition? Very early in your textbook, Apodexis Historia, a passage from Herodotus is reproduced.
    [Show full text]
  • The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 1946 The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates David J. Bowman Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Bowman, David J., "The Historicity of Plato's Apology of Socrates" (1946). Master's Theses. 61. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/61 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1946 David J. Bowman !HE HISTORICITY OP PLATO'S APOLOGY OF SOCRATES BY DA.VID J. BOWJWf~ S.J• .l. !BESIS SUBMITTED Ilf PARTIAL FULFILIJIE.NT OF THB: R}gQUIRE'IIENTS POR THE DEGREE OF IIA.STER OF ARTS Ill LOYOLA UlfiVERSITY JULY 1946 -VI'fA. David J. Bowman; S.J•• was born in Oak Park, Ill1no1a, on Ma7 20, 1919. Atter b!a eleaentar7 education at Ascension School# in Oak Park, he attended LoJola AcademJ ot Chicago, graduat1DS .from. there in June, 1937. On September 1, 1937# he entered the Sacred Heart Novitiate ot the SocietJ ot Jesus at Milford~ Ohio. Por the tour Jear• he spent there, he was aoademicallJ connected with Xavier Univeraitr, Cincinnati, Ohio. In August ot 1941 he tranaterred to West Baden College o.f Lorol& Universit7, Obicago, and received the degree ot Bachelor o.f Arts with a major in Greek in Deo.aber, 1941.
    [Show full text]