It's a Contradiction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

It's a Contradiction It’s a Contradiction—No, it’s Not: A Case Study using Functional Relations Alan Ritter, Doug Downey, Stephen Soderland and Oren Etzioni Turing Center Department of Computer Science and Engineering University of Washington Box 352350 Seattle, WA 98195, USA {aritter,ddowney,soderlan,etzioni}@cs.washington.edu Abstract 1.1 Contradictions and World Knowledge Contradiction Detection (CD) in text is a Our paper is motivated in part by de Marneffe et al.’s difficult NLP task. We investigate CD work, but with some important differences. First, over functions (e.g., BornIn(Person)=Place), we introduce a simple logical foundation for the CD and present a domain-independent algorithm task, which suggests that extensive world knowl- that automatically discovers phrases denoting edge is essential for building a domain-independent functions with high precision. Previous work CD system. Second, we automatically generate a on CD has investigated hand-chosen sentence large corpus of apparent contradictions found in ar- pairs. In contrast, we automatically harvested bitrary Web text. We show that most of these appar- from the Web pairs of sentences that appear contradictory, but were surprised to find that ent contradictions are actually consistent statements most pairs are in fact consistent. For example, due to meronyms (Alan Turing was born in London “Mozart was born in Salzburg” does not con- and in England), synonyms (George Bush is mar- tradict “Mozart was born in Austria” despite ried to both Mrs. Bush and Laura Bush), hypernyms the functional nature of the phrase “was born (Mozart died of both renal failure and kidney dis- in”. We show that background knowledge ease), and reference ambiguity (one John Smith was about meronyms (e.g., Salzburg is in Austria), born in 1997 and a different John Smith in 1883). synonyms, functions, and more is essential for success in the CD task. Next, we show how background knowledge enables a CD system to discard seeming contradictions and focus on genuine ones. 1 Introduction and Motivation De Marneffe et al. introduced a typology of con- tradiction in text, but focused primarily on contra- Detecting contradictory statements is an important dictions that can be detected from linguistic evi- and challenging NLP task with a wide range of dence (e.g. negation, antonymy, and structural or potential applications including analysis of politi- lexical disagreements). We extend their analysis to cal discourse, of scientific literature, and more (de a class of contradictions that can only be detected Marneffe et al., 2008; Condoravdi et al., 2003; utilizing background knowledge. Consider for ex- Harabagiu et al., 2006). De Marneffe et al. present a ample the following sentences: model of CD that defines the task, analyzes different types of contradictions, and reports on a CD system. 1) “Mozart was born in Salzburg.” They report 23% precision and 19% recall at detect- 2) “Mozart was born in Vienna.” ing contradictions in the RTE-3 data set (Voorhees, 3) “Mozart visited Salzburg.” 2008). Although RTE-3 contains a wide variety of 4) “Mozart visited Vienna.” contradictions, it does not reflect the prevalence of Sentences 1 & 2 are contradictory, but 3 & 4 are seeming contradictions and the paucity of genuine not. Why is that? The distinction is not syntactic. contradictions, which we have found in our corpus. Rather, sentences 1 and 2 are contradictory because 11 Proceedings of the 2008 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, pages 11–20, Honolulu, October 2008. c 2008 Association for Computational Linguistics the relation expressed by the phrase “was born in” delegated to TEXTRUNNER or simply ignored. Nev- can be characterized here as a function from peo- ertheless, extracted tuples are a convenient approxi- ple’s names to their unique birthplaces. In contrast, mation of sentence content, which enables us to fo- “visited” does not denote a functional relation.1 cus on function detection and function-based CD. We cannot assume that a CD system knows, in Our contributions are the following: advance, all the functional relations that might ap- • We present a novel model of the Contradiction pear in a corpus. Thus, a central challenge for a Detection (CD) task, which offers a simple log- function-based CD system is to determine which re- ical foundation for the task and emphasizes the lations are functional based on a corpus. Intuitively, central role of background knowledge. we might expect that “functional phrases” such as “was born in” would typically map person names • We introduce and evaluate a new EM-style al- to unique place names, making function detection gorithm for detecting whether phrases denote easy. But, in fact, function detection is surprisingly functional relations and whether nouns (e.g., difficult because name ambiguity (e.g., John Smith), “dad”) are ambiguous, which enables a CD sys- common nouns (e.g., “dad” or “mom”), definite de- tem to identify functions in arbitrary domains. scriptions (e.g., “the president”), and other linguistic • We automatically generate a corpus of seem- phenomena can mask functions in text. For example, ing contradictions from Web text, and report the two sentences “John Smith was born in 1997.” on a set of experiments over this corpus, which and “John Smith was born in 1883.” can be viewed provide a baseline for future work on statistical as either evidence that “was born in” does not de- function identification and CD. 2 note a function or, alternatively, that “John Smith” is ambiguous. 2 A Logical Foundation for CD On what basis can a CD system conclude that two 1.2 A CD System Based on Functions statements T and H are contradictory? Logically, We report on the AUCONTRAIRE CD system, which contradiction holds when T |= ¬H. As de Marneffe addresses each of the above challenges. First, AU- et al. point out, this occurs when T and H contain CONTRAIRE identifies “functional phrases” statis- antonyms, negation, or other lexical elements that tically (Section 3). Second, AUCONTRAIRE uses suggest that T and H are directly contradictory. But these phrases to automatically create a large cor- other types of contradictions can only be detected pus of apparent contradictions (Section 4.2). Fi- with the help of a body of background knowledge nally, AUCONTRAIRE sifts through this corpus to K: In these cases, T and H alone are mutually con- find genuine contradictions using knowledge about sistent. That is, synonymy, meronymy, argument types, and ambi- guity (Section 4.3). T |=\ ¬H ∧ H |=\ ¬T Instead of analyzing sentences directly, AUCON- T H TRAIRE relies on the TEXTRUNNER Open Informa- A contradiction between and arises only in tion Extraction system (Banko et al., 2007; Banko the context of K. That is: and Etzioni, 2008) to map each sentence to one or more tuples that represent the entities in the sen- ((K ∧ T ) |= ¬H) ∨ ((K ∧ H) |= ¬T ) tences and the relationships between them (e.g., was born in(Mozart,Salzburg)). Using extracted tu- Consider the example of Mozart’s birthplace in ples greatly simplifies the CD task, because nu- the introduction. To detect a contradiction, a CD merous syntactic problems (e.g., anaphora, rela- system must know that A) “Mozart” refers to the tive clauses) and semantic challenges (e.g., quantifi- same entity in both sentences, that B) “was born in” cation, counterfactuals, temporal qualification) are denotes a functional relation, and that C) Vienna and Salzburg are inconsistent locations. 1Although we focus on function-based CD in our case study, we believe that our observations apply to other types of CD as 2The corpus is available at http://www.cs. well. washington.edu/research/aucontraire/ 12 Of course, world knowledge, and reasoning about tional relation appear non-functional. Example B text, are often uncertain, which leads us to associate depicts a distribution of y values that appears less probabilities with a CD system’s conclusions. Nev- functional due to the fact that “John Adams” refers ertheless, the knowledge base K is essential for CD. to multiple, distinct real-world individuals with that We now turn to a probabilistic model that helps name. Finally, example C exhibits evidence for a us simultaneously estimate the functionality of re- non-functional relation. lations (B in the above example) and ambiguity of A. was born in(Mozart, PLACE): argument values (A above). Section 4 describes the Salzburg(66), Germany(3), Vienna(1) remaining components of AUCONTRAIRE. B. was born in(John Adams, PLACE): 3 Detecting Functionality and Ambiguity Braintree(12), Quincy(10), Worcester(8) This section introduces a formal model for comput- C. lived in(Mozart, PLACE): ing the probability that a phrase denotes a function Vienna(20), Prague(13), Salzburg(5) based on a set of extracted tuples. An extracted tuple takes the form R(x, y) where (roughly) x is the sub- Figure 1: Functional relations such as example A have a ject of a sentence, y is the object, and R is a phrase different distribution of y values than non-functional rela- denoting the relationship between them. If the re- tions such as C. However, an ambiguous x argument as in lation denoted by R is functional, then typically the B, can make a functional relation appear non-functional. object y is a function of the subject x. Thus, our dis- cussion focuses on this possibility, though the anal- 3.1 Formal Model of Functions in Text ysis is easily extended to the symmetric case. Logically, a relation R is functional in a vari- To decide whether R is functional in x for all x, able x if it maps it to a unique variable y: we first consider how to detect whether R is lo- ∀x, y1, y2 R(x, y1) ∧ R(x, y2) ⇒ y1 = y2. Thus, cally functional for a particular value of x.
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 5: Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic
    Chapter 5: Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic § 5.1 Valid inference steps Conjunction elimination Sometimes called simplification. From a conjunction, infer any of the conjuncts. • From P ∧ Q, infer P (or infer Q). Conjunction introduction Sometimes called conjunction. From a pair of sentences, infer their conjunction. • From P and Q, infer P ∧ Q. § 5.2 Proof by cases This is another valid inference step (it will form the rule of disjunction elimination in our formal deductive system and in Fitch), but it is also a powerful proof strategy. In a proof by cases, one begins with a disjunction (as a premise, or as an intermediate conclusion already proved). One then shows that a certain consequence may be deduced from each of the disjuncts taken separately. One concludes that that same sentence is a consequence of the entire disjunction. • From P ∨ Q, and from the fact that S follows from P and S also follows from Q, infer S. The general proof strategy looks like this: if you have a disjunction, then you know that at least one of the disjuncts is true—you just don’t know which one. So you consider the individual “cases” (i.e., disjuncts), one at a time. You assume the first disjunct, and then derive your conclusion from it. You repeat this process for each disjunct. So it doesn’t matter which disjunct is true—you get the same conclusion in any case. Hence you may infer that it follows from the entire disjunction. In practice, this method of proof requires the use of “subproofs”—we will take these up in the next chapter when we look at formal proofs.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics Versus Science
    To appear in Journal for General Philosophy of Science (2004) In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics versus Science F.A. Muller Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Mathematics Utrecht University, P.O. Box 80.000 3508 TA Utrecht, The Netherlands E-mail: [email protected] August 2003 Summary Over the past years, in books and journals (this journal included), N. Maxwell launched a ferocious attack on B.C. van Fraassen's view of science called Con- structive Empiricism (CE). This attack has been totally ignored. Must we con- clude from this silence that no defence is possible against the attack and that a fortiori Maxwell has buried CE once and for all, or is the attack too obviously flawed as not to merit exposure? We believe that neither is the case and hope that a careful dissection of Maxwell's reasoning will make this clear. This dis- section includes an analysis of Maxwell's `aberrance-argument' (omnipresent in his many writings) for the contentious claim that science implicitly and per- manently accepts a substantial, metaphysical thesis about the universe. This claim generally has been ignored too, for more than a quarter of a century. Our con- clusions will be that, first, Maxwell's attacks on CE can be beaten off; secondly, his `aberrance-arguments' do not establish what Maxwell believes they estab- lish; but, thirdly, we can draw a number of valuable lessons from these attacks about the nature of science and of the libertarian nature of CE. Table of Contents on other side −! Contents 1 Exordium: What is Maxwell's Argument? 1 2 Does Science Implicitly Accept Metaphysics? 3 2.1 Aberrant Theories .
    [Show full text]
  • Deduction (I) Tautologies, Contradictions And
    D (I) T, & L L October , Tautologies, contradictions and contingencies Consider the truth table of the following formula: p (p ∨ p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula depends on the way a truth value is assigned to p: the whole formula is true if p is true and false if p is false. Contrast the truth table of (p ∨ p) in () with the truth table of (p ∨ ¬p) below: p ¬p (p ∨ ¬p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula does not depend on the way a truth value is assigned to p. The formula is always true because of the meaning of the connectives. Finally, consider the truth table table of (p ∧ ¬p): p ¬p (p ∧ ¬p) () This time the formula is always false no matter what truth value p has. Tautology A statement is called a tautology if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contradiction A statement is called a contradiction if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contingency A statement is called a contingency or contingent if the final column in its truth table contains both ’s and ’s. Let’s consider some examples from the book. Can you figure out which of the following sentences are tautologies, which are contradictions and which contingencies? Hint: the answer is the same for all the formulas with a single row. () a. (p ∨ ¬p), (p → p), (p → (q → p)), ¬(p ∧ ¬p) b.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem Of
    Leibniz’s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem of »Impossible Objects« Wolfgang Lenzen (Osnabrück) Abstract The core idea of the ontological proof is to show that the concept of existence is somehow contained in the concept of God, and that therefore God’s existence can be logically derived – without any further assumptions about the external world – from the very idea, or definition, of God. Now, G.W. Leibniz has argued repeatedly that the traditional versions of the ontological proof are not fully conclusive, because they rest on the tacit assumption that the concept of God is possible, i.e. free from contradiction. A complete proof will rather have to consist of two parts. First, a proof of premise (1) God is possible. Second, a demonstration of the “remarkable proposition” (2) If God is possible, then God exists. The present contribution investigates an interesting paper in which Leibniz tries to prove proposition (2). It will be argued that the underlying idea of God as a necessary being has to be interpreted with the help of a distinguished predicate letter ‘E’ (denoting the concept of existence) as follows: (3) g =df ιxE(x). Principle (2) which Leibniz considered as “the best fruit of the entire logic” can then be formalized as follows: (4) ◊E(ιxE(x)) → E(ιxE(x)). At first sight, Leibniz’s proof appears to be formally correct; but a closer examination reveals an ambiguity in his use of the modal notions. According to (4), the possibility of the necessary being has to be understood in the sense of something which possibly exists.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastive Empiricism
    Elliott Sober Contrastive Empiricism I Despite what Hegel may have said, syntheses have not been very successful in philosophical theorizing. Typically, what happens when you combine a thesis and an antithesis is that you get a mishmash, or maybe just a contradiction. For example, in the philosophy of mathematics, formalism says that mathematical truths are true in virtue of the way we manipulate symbols. Mathematical Platonism, on the other hand, holds that mathematical statements are made true by abstract objects that exist outside of space and time. What would a synthesis of these positions look like? Marks on paper are one thing, Platonic forms an­ other. Compromise may be a good idea in politics, but it looks like a bad one in philosophy. With some trepidation, I propose in this paper to go against this sound advice. Realism and empiricism have always been contradictory tendencies in the philos­ ophy of science. The view I will sketch is a synthesis, which I call Contrastive Empiricism. Realism and empiricism are incompatible, so a synthesis that merely conjoined them would be a contradiction. Rather, I propose to isolate important elements in each and show that they combine harmoniously. I will leave behind what I regard as confusions and excesses. The result, I hope, will be neither con­ tradiction nor mishmash. II Empiricism is fundamentally a thesis about experience. It has two parts. First, there is the idea that experience is necessary. Second, there is the thesis that ex­ perience suffices. Necessary and sufficient for what? Usually this blank is filled in with something like: knowledge of the world outside the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Proofs
    CHAPTER 1 Logic, Proofs 1.1. Propositions A proposition is a declarative sentence that is either true or false (but not both). For instance, the following are propositions: “Paris is in France” (true), “London is in Denmark” (false), “2 < 4” (true), “4 = 7 (false)”. However the following are not propositions: “what is your name?” (this is a question), “do your homework” (this is a command), “this sentence is false” (neither true nor false), “x is an even number” (it depends on what x represents), “Socrates” (it is not even a sentence). The truth or falsehood of a proposition is called its truth value. 1.1.1. Connectives, Truth Tables. Connectives are used for making compound propositions. The main ones are the following (p and q represent given propositions): Name Represented Meaning Negation p “not p” Conjunction p¬ q “p and q” Disjunction p ∧ q “p or q (or both)” Exclusive Or p ∨ q “either p or q, but not both” Implication p ⊕ q “if p then q” Biconditional p → q “p if and only if q” ↔ The truth value of a compound proposition depends only on the value of its components. Writing F for “false” and T for “true”, we can summarize the meaning of the connectives in the following way: 6 1.1. PROPOSITIONS 7 p q p p q p q p q p q p q T T ¬F T∧ T∨ ⊕F →T ↔T T F F F T T F F F T T F T T T F F F T F F F T T Note that represents a non-exclusive or, i.e., p q is true when any of p, q is true∨ and also when both are true.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A
    Logic, Sets, and Proofs David A. Cox and Catherine C. McGeoch Amherst College 1 Logic Logical Statements. A logical statement is a mathematical statement that is either true or false. Here we denote logical statements with capital letters A; B. Logical statements be combined to form new logical statements as follows: Name Notation Conjunction A and B Disjunction A or B Negation not A :A Implication A implies B if A, then B A ) B Equivalence A if and only if B A , B Here are some examples of conjunction, disjunction and negation: x > 1 and x < 3: This is true when x is in the open interval (1; 3). x > 1 or x < 3: This is true for all real numbers x. :(x > 1): This is the same as x ≤ 1. Here are two logical statements that are true: x > 4 ) x > 2. x2 = 1 , (x = 1 or x = −1). Note that \x = 1 or x = −1" is usually written x = ±1. Converses, Contrapositives, and Tautologies. We begin with converses and contrapositives: • The converse of \A implies B" is \B implies A". • The contrapositive of \A implies B" is \:B implies :A" Thus the statement \x > 4 ) x > 2" has: • Converse: x > 2 ) x > 4. • Contrapositive: x ≤ 2 ) x ≤ 4. 1 Some logical statements are guaranteed to always be true. These are tautologies. Here are two tautologies that involve converses and contrapositives: • (A if and only if B) , ((A implies B) and (B implies A)). In other words, A and B are equivalent exactly when both A ) B and its converse are true.
    [Show full text]
  • Atomistic Empiricism Or Holistic Empiricism?*
    ATOMISTIC EMPIRICISM OR HOLISTIC EMPIRICISM?∗ I. Atomistic Empiricism Traditional empiricism was atomistic: it assumed that scientific knowledge may be tested through direct comparison of the “atoms” of knowledge, i.e. particular sentences, with the “atoms” of experience, that is separate results of observation and experiments, or through the confrontation of small units (if only sensible) of knowledge with small units (“elementary” units) of experience. “Atomistic” tendencies in empiricism can be best observed in positivism. Especially the so-called doctrine of logical atomism in which the notions of atomic sentence and molecular sentence come to the fore, proclaimed mainly by Russell and Wittgenstein, represents decisively the viewpoint of atomistic empiricism. One of the fundamental dogmas of neopositivism is the thesis on the possibility of empirical confirmation or refutation of every statement, taken separately, by means of particular elements of experience.1 In principle, the thesis is also shared by a critic of some of other dogmas of logical empiricism – K.R. Popper. II. The Concept of Holistic Empiricism It appears that the systemic character of knowledge makes it impossible to juxtapose separate theoretical statements with experimental data; what is more, theoretical hypotheses (laws) are not only and cannot be on the whole separately tested but mostly are not (and cannot be) separated ∗ Translation of “Empiryzm atomistyczny czy empiryzm holistyczny?” Studia Filozoficzne, 12, 1975, 149-160. 1 W. Mejbaum writes that empiricism of neopositivists is based on a conviction about the divisibility of experimental material into particular building blocks: impressions in the subjectivist version, and facts in the objectivist version. We subordinate sentences to those events, and a set of those sentences may be considered to be a starting point of a programme of logical reconstruction of knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Indemonstrability of the Principle of Contradiction
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 6-23-2003 On the Indemonstrability of the Principle of Contradiction Elisabeta Sarca University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons Scholar Commons Citation Sarca, Elisabeta, "On the Indemonstrability of the Principle of Contradiction" (2003). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/1465 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. On the Indemonstrability of the Principle of Contradiction by Elisabeta Sarca A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: John P. Anton, Ph.D. Kwasi Wiredu, Ph.D. Willis Truitt, Ph.D. Eric Winsberg, Ph.D. Date of Approval: June 23, 2003 Keywords: logic, metaphysics, aristotle, mill, russell-whitehead © Copyright 2003, Elisabeta Sarca Acknowledgements I would like to express my gratitude to Dr. John Anton for his invaluable advice and guidance throughout the preparation of this thesis and to Dr. Kwasi Wiredu, Dr. Willis Truitt and Dr. Eric Winsberg for their help and encouragement and for their participation in the defense of my thesis. I want to take this opportunity to thank the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate School for granting me the University Fellowship for graduate studies at University of South Florida.
    [Show full text]
  • Principles of Contradiction, Sufficient Reason, and Identity Of
    Chapter 3 The Principles of Contradiction, Sufficient Reason, and Identity of Indiscernibles1 Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Leibniz was a philosopher of principles: the principles of Contradiction, of Sufficient Reason, of Identity of Indiscernibles, of Plenitude, of the Best, and of Continuity are among the most famous Leibnizian principles.2 In this article I shall focus on the first three principles; I shall discuss various formulations of the principles (sect. 1), what it means for these theses to have the status of principles or axioms in Leibniz’s philosophy (sect. 2), the fundamental character of the Principles of Contradiction and Sufficient Reason (sect. 3), some attempts to demonstrate the Principles of Contradiction and Sufficient Reason (sect. 4), and one attempt to demonstrate the Principle of Identity of Indiscernibles (sect. 5). The main results of the chapter are summarized in a short conclusion (sect. 6). 1. Formulations of the Principles of Contradiction, Sufficient Reason, and Identity of Indiscernibles. Leibniz gives several different formulations of the Principle of Contradiction, among them the following ones: 1 I am grateful to Maria Rosa Antognazza, Paul Lodge, and Brandon Look for comments on a previous version of this paper. 2 According to Ortega y Gasset Leibniz is both the philosopher who used the greatest number of maximally general principles and the philosopher who introduced the greatest number of new principles (1979: 12). 2 PC1: For any two contradictory propositions p and q, one is true and the other is false (GP VI 413).3 PC2: For any proposition p, p is either true or false (A 6 4 670/MP 93; GP VII 299/L225; GP VII 420/LC 96; A 6 6 362/NE 362).4 PC3: For any proposition p, p is not both true and false (GP VII 299/L 225; GP VII 355/LC 15).
    [Show full text]
  • The History of Logic
    c Peter King & Stewart Shapiro, The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (OUP 1995), 496–500. THE HISTORY OF LOGIC Aristotle was the first thinker to devise a logical system. He drew upon the emphasis on universal definition found in Socrates, the use of reductio ad absurdum in Zeno of Elea, claims about propositional structure and nega- tion in Parmenides and Plato, and the body of argumentative techniques found in legal reasoning and geometrical proof. Yet the theory presented in Aristotle’s five treatises known as the Organon—the Categories, the De interpretatione, the Prior Analytics, the Posterior Analytics, and the Sophistical Refutations—goes far beyond any of these. Aristotle holds that a proposition is a complex involving two terms, a subject and a predicate, each of which is represented grammatically with a noun. The logical form of a proposition is determined by its quantity (uni- versal or particular) and by its quality (affirmative or negative). Aristotle investigates the relation between two propositions containing the same terms in his theories of opposition and conversion. The former describes relations of contradictoriness and contrariety, the latter equipollences and entailments. The analysis of logical form, opposition, and conversion are combined in syllogistic, Aristotle’s greatest invention in logic. A syllogism consists of three propositions. The first two, the premisses, share exactly one term, and they logically entail the third proposition, the conclusion, which contains the two non-shared terms of the premisses. The term common to the two premisses may occur as subject in one and predicate in the other (called the ‘first figure’), predicate in both (‘second figure’), or subject in both (‘third figure’).
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Twofold Critique of Empiricism
    Hegel’s Twofold Critique of Empiricism: Cognition, Ontology and the Question of Universality Sebastian Stein Ruprecht-Karls Universität Heidelberg ABSTRACT: Hegel’s seemingly contradictory assessment of empiricism can be rendered consistent if one distinguishes between two ways in which he interprets it: Firstly, as a theory of cognition and secondly, as a theory of ontological truth. While Hegel argues that the former undermines itself due to its inability to establish the universal and necessary validity of its own perspective, he praises the latter for defending the irreducibility of particularity. Still, from Hegel’s own stance, a successful notion of ontological truth must accommodate what empiricism lacks: A dynamic notion of universality that forms a negative unity with particularity, in which both moments are acknowledged but neither is prioritised. Hegel calls this unity ‘the concept’ and deduces his own notion of cognition from it, thus equipping it with the universal and necessary status that he finds empiricism’s notion of cognition unable to account for. KEYWORDS: Hegel, Empiricism, Hume, Spinoza, Rationalism, Cognition, Universality, Particularity, Concept. 1. Introduction The relationship between Hegel’s idealism and empiricism continues to engage researchers.1 While some contrast Hegel from Kant by arguing that the former has a notion of Article received on 30/10/2015 and accepted for publication on 24/12/2015. This paper could not have been written without the enriching exchanges I have had on the topics under discussion with friends, colleagues and students. In particular, I would like to thank (in alphabetical order): Resgar Beraderi, Thom Brooks, Frank Carle, Frank Chouraqui, Tobias Dangel, Daniel Dragicevic, Katerinal Deligiorgi, Markus Gabriel, Michael Greene, Jens Halfwassen, Susanne Herrmann-Sinai, Michael Inwood, Anton Friedrich Koch, Christian Martin, David Merrill, Sebastian Ostritsch, Robert Pippin, Felix Stein, Klaus Vieweg, Roberto Vinco, Joshua Wretzel, Lucia Ziglioli, the participants of Prof.
    [Show full text]