Running head: MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 1

1 Manipulating Moral Dumbfounding: Inhibiting the Identification of Reasons for a Moral

2 Judgement

1 2 1 1 3 Cillian McHugh , Marek McGann , Eric R. Igou , & Elaine L Kinsella

1 4 University of Limerick

2 5 Mary Immaculate College ~ University of Limerick

6 Author Note

7 All procedures performed in studies involving human participants were approved by

8 institutional research ethics committee and conducted in accordance with the Code of

9 Professional Ethics of the Psychological Society of Ireland, and with the 1964 Helsinki

10 declaration and its later amendments or comparable ethical standards. Informed consent was

11 obtained from all individual participants included in the study. The authors declare that

12 there are no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or

13 publication of this article. All authors consented to the submission of this manuscript. This

14 work was part funded by Mary Immaculate College seed funding.

15 Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Cillian McHugh,

16 University of Limerick, Limerick, Ireland. E-mail: [email protected] MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 2

17 Abstract

18 Moral dumbfounding occurs when people defend a moral judgement even though they

19 cannot provide a reason in support of this judgement. It manifests as an admission of not

20 having reasons, or the use of unsupported declarations (“it’s just wrong”) or tautological

21 reasons (“because it’s incest”) as justifications for a judgment. We test a dual-processes

22 explanation of moral dumbfounding, where moral dumbfounding is an example of conflict

23 between a habitual response (making a judgement) and a response that results from

24 deliberation (providing a reason for the judgement). The dumbfounding paradigm involves

25 three possible responses: (a) providing reasons for a judgement (deliberative/controlled

26 process); (b) accepting the counter-arguments and rating the behaviour as “not wrong”

27 (habitual/automatic process); (c) a dumbfounded response (habitual/automatic process).

28 Cognitive load manipulations have been shown to inhibit deliberative responding. We

29 present 5 studies in which dumbfounded responding was investigated under cognitive load

30 manipulations. We hypothesised that rates of providing reasons would be reduced under

31 cognitive load. The identification of reasons was inhibited in Studies 1 and 3, but not in

32 Studies 2, 4 or 5. The results provide weak evidence for a dual-process explanation of moral

33 dumbfounding. We found some evidence that dumbfounded responding may be linked with

34 Need for Cognition.

35 Keywords: moral dumbfounding, dual-processes, reasons, intuitions, need for cognition

36 Word count: 11,025 MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 3

37 Manipulating Moral Dumbfounding: Inhibiting the Identification of Reasons for a Moral

38 Judgement

39 Moral dumbfounding occurs when people defend a moral judgement even though they

40 cannot provide a reason in support of this judgement (Haidt, 2001; Haidt, Björklund, &

41 Murphy, 2000; see also McHugh et al., 2017). It is seen as evidence for the intuitive nature of

42 moral judgements and has been cited as support for both intuitionist and dual-process

43 theories of moral judgement (e.g., Cameron, Payne, & Doris, 2013; Crockett, 2013; Cushman,

44 2013; Cushman, Young, & Greene, 2010; Greene, 2008; Haidt, 2001; Prinz, 2005). Despite

45 the influence of moral dumbfounding on the morality literature, the phenomenon is not well

46 understood. Until recently (e.g., Royzman, Kim, & Leeman, 2015; McHugh et al., 2017),

47 empirical evidence testing the phenomenon was limited to a single study with a final sample

48 of N = 30, unpublished in peer-reviewed form. The dumbfounding paradigm involves

49 presenting participants with a moral scenario, and asking them to judge the behaviour in the

50 scenario. Participants are then asked to provide reasons for their judgement. Typically the

51 scenarios in the dumbfounding paradigm depict “harmless taboos” (Haidt & Björklund, 2008,

52 p. 196). McHugh et al. (2017), building on the original work by Haidt et al. (2000),

53 identified two measurable responses that may be taken as indicators of moral dumbfounding.

54 Firstly, people may explicitly admit to not having reasons for their judgement. Secondly,

55 people may use unsupported declarations (“it’s just wrong”) or tautological reasons

56 (“because it’s incest”) as justifications for a judgement. The current research uses the

57 methods developed by McHugh et al. (2017) to test one potential explanation of moral

58 dumbfounding.

59 Moral Dumbfounding: A Dual-Process Perspective

60 Drawing on dual-process theories of moral judgement (e.g., Greene, 2008; Brand, 2016;

61 Cushman, 2013), the studies presented here aim to test the hypothesis that moral

62 dumbfounding can be explained as a result of a dual-process conflict (Bonner & Newell, 2010; MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 4

63 De Neys, 2012; De Neys & Glumicic, 2008; Evans, 2007). Conflicts occur when a

64 habitual/intuitive response is different from a response that results from deliberation.

65 Examples of such conflicts include, base rate neglect problems (Bonner & Newell, 2010; De

66 Neys, 2012; De Neys & Glumicic, 2008; Evans, 2007), the conjunction fallacy (De Neys, 2012;

67 Tversky & Kahneman, 1983), and the persistence of apparently “irrational” behaviours

68 (Evans, 2007), and compulsive behaviours (e.g. overeating, smoking, or gambling, Evans,

69 2008).

70 Another example of this kind of dual-process conflict is identified by Lerner and

71 Goldberg (1999), discussing a study by Rozin, Markwith, and McCauley (1994). In this

72 study, Rozin et al. (1994) found that people reported reduced willingness to contact various

73 items that they believed had prior contact with (i) an AIDS victim, (ii) someone who had

74 been in a car accident, or (iii) a murderer. This unwillingness persisted despite assurances

75 that these items are sanitary (Rozin et al., 1994). The original unpublished moral

76 dumbfounding study (Haidt et al., 2000) included a similar task; in addition to three moral

77 judgement tasks, Haidt et al. (2000) included two non-moral tasks. As part of one of the

78 non-moral tasks, the experimenter dipped a sterilised cockroach in a glass of juice.

79 Participants were then asked to drink from the glass. Much like the study by Rozin et al.

80 (1994), participants were unwilling to drink from the glass (Haidt et al., 2000).

81 Haidt et al. (2000) present this response as equivalent to dumbfounded responding in a

82 moral task; in both tasks participants reject a given action (either performing it in the case

83 of the drink, or accepting it in the case of the moral vignettes) despite the context removing

84 the typical reasons given for doing so. This parity suggests that the cognitive processes that

85 lead to this unwillingness to contact items seen as contaminated (identified as dual-process

86 conflict by Lerner & Goldberg, 1999) may similarly lead to moral dumbfounding. It is

87 possible that dumbfounded responding may also be explained as the result of dual-process

88 conflict, where the making of a moral judgement is a habitual/intuitive response, and MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 5

89 identifying reasons involves deliberation. According to this interpretation, conflict occurs

90 when deliberation fails to identify reasons for an intuitive judgement, and this results in a

91 dumbfounded response. We aim to test this explanation here.

92 Dual-Processes in the Dumbfounding Paradigm

93 Normal cases of conflict can be resolved either by (a) the over-riding of the habitual

94 response or (b) the ignoring of the inconsistent information from deliberation. Consider the

95 following problem (taken from De Neys, 2012, p. 29):

96 A psychologist wrote thumbnail descriptions of a sample of 1000 participants

97 consisting of 995 females and 5 males. The description below was chosen at

98 random from the 1,000 available descriptions.

99 Jo is 23 years old and is finishing a degree in engineering. On Friday nights, Jo

100 likes to go out cruising with friends while listening to loud music and drinking

101 beer. Which one of the following two statements is most likely?

102 (i) Jo is a man

103 (ii) Jo is a woman

104 Jo appears to present as stereotypically male, and so the intuitive/habitual response is

105 (i): Jo is a man. Deliberation (and attending to the make up of the sample) reveals that Jo

106 is 199 times more likely to be a woman (99.5%) than to be a man (0.5%). In this case there

107 is a clear conflict between the intuitive/habitual response and the deliberative response. This

108 conflict can resolved if a person accepts that their intuition was incorrect and adopts the

109 deliberative response. Alternatively a person may choose to ignore the inconsistent

110 information that resulted from deliberation and maintain their initial judgement.

111 In the dumbfounding paradigm, conflict cannot be as easily resolved using these MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 6

112 strategies. Firstly, regarding an attempt to over-ride the intuitive/habitual moral judgement,

113 there is considerable evidence suggesting that people are unwilling to over-ride habitual

114 responses, or revise their intuitive judgements, on certain issues, and this is particularly true

115 for moral issues (Abelson, 1988; Kruglanski & Webster, 1996; Kruglanski, Webster, & Klem,

116 1993; McGregor, 2006a, 2006b; McGregor, Zanna, Holmes, & Spencer, 2001). This

117 robustness of the habitual/intuitive response means that resolving conflict requires either the

118 identification of reasons that are consistent with the initial judgement, or ignoring the

119 inconsistent information. If further reasons cannot be identified, and inconsistencies cannot

120 be resolved (e.g., because of direct questioning) a person may maintain their judgement

121 while also acknowledging that they cannot provide supporting reasons for it (i.e., presenting

122 as dumbfounded).

123 Two types of dumbfounded responses were identified by McHugh et al. (2017): (a)

124 unsupported declarations and (b) admissions of not having reasons. The salience of

125 inconsistent information is much greater when a person admits to not having reasons than

126 when they simply provide an unsupported declaration. As such, an unsupported declaration

127 is likely a much more attractive response than admitting to not having reasons for a

128 judgement. Indeed, McHugh et al. (2017) provide some suggestive evidence for this: when

129 dumbfounding was measured as the selecting of an unsupported declaration, rates of

130 dumbfounding were much higher than in other studies. In the absence of explicit reminders

131 that deliberation did not provide reasons to support their judgement, participants appeared

132 to readily dismiss inconsistencies between their initial judgement and the outcome of

133 deliberation.

134 Intuitive and Deliberative Responding

135 In traditional dual-process conflict studies there are generally two responses: a correct

136 response and an incorrect response; and two types of responses: logical (deliberative) and

137 intuitive (habitual). This binary correct/incorrect, logical/intuitive classification means that MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 7

138 the dependent variables in these studies can be operationalised relatively easily, a response is

139 either correct or incorrect. The correct response always maps onto the logical (deliberative)

140 and various manipulations can frame the intuitive response as either correct or incorrect.

141 In contrast, there is no clear correct or incorrect answer in moral judgement tasks. In

142 addition to this, the study of moral dumbfounding (in the common case of an initial

143 judgement that the target behaviour is wrong) involves at least three different responses (1)

144 the providing of reasons (reason); (2) accepting the counter-arguments and rating the

145 behaviour as “not wrong” (nothing wrong); or (3) a dumbfounded response (dumbfounding).

146 The positioning of these responses options in terms of habitual or deliberative responses may

147 vary from person to person or from situation to situation.

148 The nature of the dumbfounding paradigm, which involves explicit arguments against

149 the most common judgements, requires that participants engage in some deliberation. This

150 means that all responses are likely the result of some level of deliberation in order to support

151 (or attempt to support) an initial intuition. A simplistic view of the possible responses

152 identified above would identify (1) reason as the successful alignment of deliberation and

153 intuition. (2) Nothing wrong is the over-riding of intuition by deliberation, while (3)

154 dumbfounding is the failure of deliberation to rationalise an intuition. This view however

155 presumes that there is only one intuition at play, and participants’ deliberations are an

156 attempt to provide reasons for this single intuition.

157 At least one other intuition that may become salient as part of the dumbfounding

158 paradigm has been identified. Participants may have intuitions relating to the nature of

159 moral knowledge, for example that moral judgements should be justifiable by reasons. During

160 the course of the study, this intuition (or alternative intuitions) may become salient. The

161 emergence of this intuition appears consistent with what has been observed in studies of

162 moral dumbfounding, whereby people appear to be motivated to identify reasons for their

163 judgement (McHugh et al., 2017; Royzman et al., 2015). This means that people experience MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 8

164 more than a conflict between habitual and deliberative responding, they may also experience

165 competing intuitions. The emergence of these competing intuitions may be attributed to

166 deliberation, however, it is also possible that their emergence occurs as a result of the nature

167 of the dumbfounding paradigm independently of level of deliberation; participants are asked

168 to provide reasons for their judgements. The need for judgements to be justifiable by reasons

169 may be made salient by simply asking participants to provide justifications for their

170 judgements.

171 Three possible types of responses in the dumbfounding paradigm are listed above, (1)

172 reason; (2) nothing wrong; and (3) dumbfounding. In addition, two classes of (3)

173 dumbfounding have been identified: admissions of not having reasons, and unsupported

174 declaration (e.g., “It’s just wrong!” or “Incest is wrong.”). To reflect this, response (3)

175 dumbfounding may be described as (3a) admission and (3b) unsupported declaration . The

176 discussion below attempts to describe each of the responses 1-3 in terms of the varying roles

177 of deliberation and intuition, where at least two relevant (competing) intuitions have been

178 identified.

179 It is likely that (1) a reason response is the most desirable, it involves successfully

180 resolving the conflicting intuitions and providing reasons for a judgement. However, a reason

181 response also requires that deliberation is “successful”, that is, deliberation results in

182 successfully identifying a reason for a judgement. In the dumbfounding paradigm this is

183 made particularly difficult because commonly identified reasons for judgements are refuted

184 during the course of the study. This means that successfully identifying a reason requires

185 identifying a reason beyond the refuted reasons, or identifying shortcomings in the

186 refutations.

187 It is also likely that (3b) unsupported declaration requires the least deliberation.

188 Defending a judgement with a restatement of the judgement can be done without

189 deliberation. Furthermore, in restating a judgement and affirming a position, the salience of MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 9

190 inconsistent intuitions may be reduced. This response may be likened to the “seizing and

191 freezing” behaviours described by Kruglanski and Webster (1996).

192 This leaves (2) nothing wrong and (3a) admission. It is probable that changing a

193 judgement requires more deliberation than admitting to not having a reason for it; in

194 changing a judgement a person would likely deliberate the strength of the counter-arguments.

195 It has also been shown that both types of dumbfounded response are more similar to each

1 196 other than to either (1) a reason response or (2) nothing wrong. It is likely that the

197 observed similarity between both dumbfounded responses would extend to levels of

198 deliberation. As such, dumbfounded responding is hypothesised to involve the least amount

199 of deliberation, and providing reasons requires the most amount of deliberation, with

200 changing judgement involving more deliberation than dumbfounded responding, but not as

201 much deliberation as successfully providing reasons.

202 Competing Intuitions. The only response that can be positioned as habitual or

203 deliberative with any confidence is (1) a reason response, which is certainly deliberative, as it

204 illustrates successful deliberation such that two competing intuitions may be aligned. The

205 relative roles of intuition and deliberation in each of the other responses are less clear. There

206 are at least two competing intuitions that may give rise to the remaining responses: (i) that

207 the behaviour is wrong, and (ii) that moral judgements should be grounded in reasons.

208 Furthermore, (3b) unsupported declaration is a clear endorsing of the first intuition (i)

209 that the behaviour is wrong over the second intuition (ii) that moral judgements should be

210 grounded in reasons. Arriving at this response is possible without deliberation. If a person

211 does not see a need for judgements to be justified by reasons, they are unlikely to engage in

212 a deliberative search for reasons.

213 The remaining responses (2) nothing wrong and (3a) admission, may be viewed as

1 This is based on the analysis of non-verbal behaviours such as laughing, smiling, silence; see McHugh et al. (2017) MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 10

214 instances of selecting one of the competing intuitions following deliberation. Providing

215 response (2) nothing wrong, may also be viewed as selecting one of the competing intuitions

216 based on, and informed by deliberation, acknowledging the value of this deliberation process.

217 For this reason it is possible that response (2) nothing wrong, may, in some cases, involve

218 slightly more deliberation than (3a) an admission. The relative level of deliberation involved

219 in (2) nothing wrong and (3a) admission, may vary depending on the individual. Some

220 people may readily change their judgement based on new information, while others may not

221 see the need to justify their judgement by reasons.

222 In view of the above discussion, the responses may be (tentatively) ranked in order of

223 the relative role of deliberation. Beginning with the highest level of deliberation and ending

224 with the lowest, the responses may be ranked as follows: (i) providing reasons (successful

225 deliberation), (ii) accepting the counter-arguments and rating the behaviour as “not wrong”

226 (failed deliberation/deliberation over-riding an initial intuition), (iii) an admission of not

227 having reasons (failed deliberation/rejection of value of deliberation) and, (iv) an

228 unsupported declaration (failed deliberation/rejection of value of deliberation/deliberation

229 absent). As noted previously, providing reasons is the only response for which claims

230 regarding the relative role of deliberation and intuition can be made with any degree of

231 certainty.

232 Influences on Moral Dumbfounding

233 One prediction of explaining dumbfounding as conflict in dual-processes is that under

234 specific manipulations, responses in the moral dumbfounding paradigm should vary in

235 predictable ways. In addition to external manipulation, a second prediction of this conflict in

236 dual-processes explanation is that responses in the moral dumbfounding paradigm may

237 display variability that can be linked to specific individual difference variables. The studies

238 described here aim to investigate both of these possibilities. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 11

239 Influencing Moral Dumbfounding through Experimental Manipulation

240 Cognitive load has been shown to inhibit deliberative responding (e.g., De Neys, 2006;

241 Evans & Curtis-Holmes, 2005; Evans & Stanovich, 2013; Schmidt, 2016). Above, we

242 identified providing reasons as involving more deliberation than alternative responses in the

243 dumbfounding paradigm. This implies that cognitive load should inhibit the identification of

244 reasons for a judgement, leading to an increase in dumbfounded responding or an increase in

245 accepting the counter-arguments and revising the judgement made.

246 According to Greene et al. (2008), cognitive load reduces the likelihood of utilitarian

247 judgements but not deontological judgements. The judgements in dumbfounding paradigms

248 are typically deontological; the moral violations described in the scenarios in studies of moral

249 dumbfounding are violations of widely accepted deontic propositions. Changing a judgement

250 in the dumbfounding paradigm means rejecting a deontological judgement in favour of a

251 judgement informed by a utilitarian position (the counter-arguments highlight the lack of

252 harm in the scenarios). Drawing on Greene et al. (2008), who showed that utilitarian

253 judgements are negatively influenced by cognitive load, it is expected that cognitive load

254 should led to more dumbfounded responding, rather than changing of judgements. This

255 prediction is also purported to be supported by Haidt et al. (2000). In the opening note of

256 the original Haidt et al. (2000) report, they report that they conducted a second study in

257 which they manipulated cognitive load. They report that they found that cognitive load led

258 to increased levels of dumbfounding but did not influence judgements made. Beyond a brief

259 mention in the opening note, this cognitive load and moral dumbfounding study is not

260 reported in full in Haidt et al. (2000) or elsewhere.

261 An investigation of the dumbfounding under cognitive load can test two predictions of

262 dual-process models of moral judgement. Firstly, it is hypothesised that deliberative

263 responding generally will be inhibited by cognitive load, leading to less identification of

264 reasons for judgements. This inhibition may result in higher rates of selecting “there is MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 12

265 nothing wrong” or higher rates of dumbfounded responding (or both). However, adopting

266 the work by Greene et al. (2008) suggests that the inhibition of deliberation should result in

267 higher rates of dumbfounded responding only.

268 Again, there are three possible responses in the dumbfounding paradigm: (1) providing

269 reasons; (2) a change in judgement; and (3) a dumbfounded response. Providing reasons has

270 been identified as requiring more deliberation than the other responses, and as such the

271 introduction of a cognitive load manipulation should reduce the providing of reasons in

272 favour of one of the other responses. It is not clear whether participants would be more

273 likely to revise their judgement or provide a dumbfounded response.

274 Individual Differences in Moral Dumbfounding

275 As noted above, it is likely that responses in the dumbfounding paradigm will vary

276 depending on individual differences. One individual difference variable linked to dual-process

277 approaches to cognition, therefore may be related to susceptibility to dumbfounding is Need

278 for Cognition (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Forsterlee & Ho, 1999; Petty, Cacioppo, & Kao,

279 1984; Petty, Feinstein, Blair, & Jarvis, 1996). The Need for Cognition Scale (NFC) is a

280 measure of an individual’s tendency “to engage in and enjoy effortful analytic activity”

281 (Forsterlee & Ho, 1999, p. 471; see also Cacioppo & Petty, 1982). In other words, it measures

282 a tendency to engage in deliberation (Evans & Stanovich, 2013). It is also related to a

283 person’s need to understand and make sense of the world (Forsterlee & Ho, 1999). It is

284 hypothesised that people who score highly on the NFC will be more likely to provide reasons

285 for their judgement. Related to this, people who score low on the NFC are likely to fail to

286 identify reasons for their judgement. That NFC is related to a need to understand and make

287 sense of the world suggests that of the people who fail to identify reasons for their

288 judgement, the people who revise their judgement will likely score higher on the NFC than

289 people who provide a dumbfounded response. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 13

290 The Current Studies

291 The studies described here aim to investigate test three predictions of a conflict in

292 dual-process explanation of moral dumbfounding. To test the first two predictions we

293 experimentally manipulated cognitive load. Our primary prediction is that a cognitive load

294 manipulation will inhibit people’s ability to provide reasons for their judgement, leading to

295 greater habitual responses (either nothing wrong or dumbfounding or both). A second

296 prediction, informed by Greene et al. (2008), that a cognitive load manipulation will inhibit

297 people’s ability to provide reasons for their judgement, leading to greater dumbfounding

298 specifically will also be tested. The third prediction that will be tested is that a person’s

299 tendency to provide reasons will be related to their score on the Need for Cognition scale

300 (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et al., 1984). We hypothesise that as NFC increases people

301 will be less likely to present as dumbfounded. We conducted five studies to assess these

2,3 302 predictions. In all five studies, we report all measures, manipulations and exclusions.

303 Study 1 - College Sample

304 The aim of Study 1 was to investigate if a cognitive load manipulation influenced

305 participants’ ability to justify their judgement. We also measured Need for Cognition

2 A priori power analysis indicated that, for the primary research question (the influence of cognitive load on dumbfounded responding), in order to detect a large effect size (V = .35) with 80% power, a sample of N = 79 participants was required; in order to detect a medium effect size (V = .21) with 80% power a sample of N = 218 participants was required; in order to detect a small effect size (V = .07) with 80% power a sample of N = 1966 was required. This means that the studies described here are likely underpowered. To account for this we conclude with a combined analysis of all studies which includes mini meta-analyses.

3 A priori power analysis indicated that, for the secondary research question (the relationship between dumbfounded responding and Need for Cognition), in order to detect a large effect size (OR = 9) with 80% power, a sample of N = 11 participants was required; in order to detect a medium effect size (OR = 3.45) with 80% power a sample of N = 32 participants was required; in order to detect a small effect size (OR = 1.49) with 80% power a sample of N = 309 was required. Again, the studies described here are likely underpowered and we conclude with a combined analysis of all studies. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 14

306 (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et al., 1984) as a potential moderator variable.

307 Study 1: Method

308 Participants and design. Study 1 was a between subjects design. The dependent

309 variable was rates of providing reasons/dumbfounding (measured using to the critical slide

310 with 3 response options: 1: providing reasons; 2: there is nothing wrong; 3: dumbfounded

311 response - admission). The independent variable was cognitive load with two levels: present

312 and absent. Cognitive load was manipulated by presenting participants with an eight digit

313 number letter string to be memorised. Need for Cognition (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et

314 al., 1984) was included as a potential correlate and moderator variable.

315 A total sample of 66 participants (55 female, 11 male; M age = 22.42, min = 18, max =

316 57, SD = 6.86) took part. Participants in this sample were undergraduate students,

317 postgraduate students, and alumni from Mary Immaculate College (MIC), and University of

318 Limerick (UL). Participation was voluntary and participants were not reimbursed for their

319 participation.

320 Procedure and materials. Data were collected using an online questionnaire.

321 Data collection took place in a designated computer laboratory in MIC. The experimenter

322 remained in the laboratory for the duration of the study. Participants were first presented

323 with an information sheet and consent form. The main study proceeded when participants

324 had signed the consent form.

325 Participants in the experimental condition were presented with an eight digit

326 number/letter string and asked to memorise the sequence. After 30 seconds, the experiment

327 progressed to the next slide. Participants had the option to click “ok” and progress to the

328 next slide after 15 seconds.

329 Participants were then presented with the “Julie and Mark” (Incest) vignette (Haidt et

330 al., 2000). Participants rated on a 7-point Likert scale how right or wrong the behaviour of MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 15

331 Julie and Mark was (where, 1 = Morally wrong; 4 = neutral; 7 = Morally right), and were

332 given an opportunity to provide reasons for their judgement. Following this, participants

333 were presented with a series of counter-arguments, which refuted commonly used

334 justifications for rating the behaviour as “wrong”.

335 Dumbfounding was measured using the critical slide (McHugh et al., 2017). This

336 contained a statement defending the behaviour and a question as to how the behaviour could

337 be wrong (“Julie and Mark’s behaviour did not harm anyone, how can there be anything

338 wrong with what they did?”). There were three possible answer options: (a) “There is

339 nothing wrong”; (b) an admission of not having reasons (“It’s wrong but I can’t think of a

340 reason”); and finally a judgement with accompanying justification (c) “It’s wrong and I can

341 provide a valid reason”. The order of these response options was randomised. Participants

342 who selected (c) were prompted to type a reason. The selecting of option (b), the admission

343 of not having reasons, was taken to be a dumbfounded response. Following the critical slide,

344 participants in the experimental condition were required to reproduce the eight digit

345 number-letter string sequence presented previously. Following this a post-discussion

346 questionnaire in which participants rated their response to the scenario across various

347 dimensions (Haidt et al., 2000).

348 Need for Cognition was measured using the short form of the Need for Cognition scale

349 (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et al., 1984). This is an 18 item scale containing questions

350 relating to motivation to engage in thinking (e.g., “I would prefer complex to simple

351 problems”). Responses were recorded on a -4 to +4 Likert-type scale, where -4 = very strong

352 disagreement and +4 = very strong agreement.

353 Study 1: Results

354 Forty six participants (69.70%) rated the behaviour of Julie and Mark as wrong initially.

355 The mean initial rating of the behaviour was, M = 2.38, SD = 1.87. There was no difference MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 16

356 in initial judgement depending on cognitive load, t(63.90) = 1.26, p = .214; d = 0.31.

100%

75% 63.6%

Condition 50% 45.5% Cognitive load Control 36.4%

25% 21.2% 18.2% 15.2%

Percentage of participants selecting each response 0% 15 5 6 7 12 21

Nothing Wrong Dumbfounded Reasons Response to Critical Slide

Figure 1 . Study 1: Responses to critical slide and for the experimental group (N = 33) and the control group (N = 33)

357 Participants who selected the admission of not having reasons on the critical slide were

358 identified as dumbfounded. Thirteen participants (19.70%) selected “It’s wrong but I can’t

359 think of a reason”. Thirty three participants (50%) selected “It’s wrong and I can provide a

360 valid reason”; and twenty participants (30.30%) selected “There is nothing wrong”.

361 Cognitive load manipulation check. Analysis of the responses to the cognitive

362 load manipulation revealed that nine participants (27.27%) successfully remembered the

363 sequence of numbers and letters in full. Responses to the manipulation check question

364 revealed that five participants (15.15%) found the memory task easy. Of these, four

365 participants both found the task easy and got the answer right. All participants correctly

366 remembered at least two digits, indicating at least some level of engagement with the MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 17

Table 1 Study 1 – Observed counts, expected counts, and standardised residuals for each response to the critical slide depending on cognitive load

Cognitive Load Control

Observed count Nothing Wrong 15 5 Dumbfounded 6 7 Reasons 12 21 Expected count Nothing Wrong 10 10 Dumbfounded 6.5 6.5 Reasons 16.5 16.5 Standardised residuals Nothing Wrong 2.68* -2.68* Dumbfounded -0.31 0.31 Reasons -2.22* 2.22*

Note. * = sig. at p < .05; ** = sig. at p < .001

367 cognitive load manipulation.

368 We tested for differences between the cognitive load group and the control group for

369 Initial Judgement and Initial Confidence. An independent samples t-test revealed no

370 significant difference in initial rating in the cognitive load group, (M = 2.67, SD = 1.90),

371 and the control group, (M = 2.55, SD = 1.92), t(63.90) = 1.26 , p = 0.21; d = 0.31. An

372 independent samples t-test revealed no significant difference in initial confidence in the

373 cognitive load group, (M = 5.42, SD = 1.30), and the control group, (M = 5.09, SD = 1.83),

374 t(57.80) = 0.85 , p = 0.40; d = 0.21. In view of this, we assume that both groups engaged

375 equally with the task.

376 Cognitive load and dumbfounded responding. A chi-squared test for

377 independence revealed a significant association between experimental condition and response MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 18

2 378 to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 66) = 7.53, p = .023, V = 0.34, the observed power was 0.69.

379 Under cognitive load fewer participants (12; 63.64%) provided reasons than in the control

380 condition (21; 36.36%). Similarly, under cognitive load more participants (15; 45.45%)

381 selected “There is nothing wrong” than in the control group (5; 15.15%). The responses to

382 the critical slide for the experimental group (N = 33) and the control group (N = 33) are

383 displayed in Figure 1. The observed counts, expected counts and standardised residuals are

384 displayed in Table 1.

385 Need for Cognition. A multinomial logistic regression revealed no significant

2 386 association between Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 66) =

4 387 4.86, p = .088, the observed power was 0.49.

388 Study 1: Discussion

389 The aim of the Study 1 was to investigate if dumbfounded responding was influenced

390 by cognitive load. Specifically, adopting a dual-systems model of moral judgement, it was

391 hypothesised that cognitive load would lead to reduced levels of deliberative responding, and

392 that a reduction in rates of successfully identifying reasons for judgements would be

393 observed. This may lead to (a) increased levels of dumbfounding, or (b) increased selecting

394 of the “nothing wrong” response. As predicted we found lower rates of providing reasons in

395 the cognitive load group than in the control group. This led to higher rates of selecting

396 “there is nothing wrong” in the cognitive load group.

397 As discussed above, we hypothesised that moral dumbfounding occurs when people fail

398 to resolve a conflict between an initial intuition and an intuition that emerges following

399 deliberation. Under cognitive load a higher proportion of participants failed to provide

400 reasons for their judgements, and a higher proportion of participants selected the “There’s

4 As noted previously the studies presented here are likely underpowered. We conclude with a combined analysis. The relative probabilities of selecting each response depending on Need for Cognition for each study are presented in Appendix D. See Figure 11 for Study 1. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 19

401 nothing wrong” response. There was no difference in rates of dumbfounding between the

402 cognitive load group and the control group. It appears that when faced with an inability to

403 justify a judgement with reasons, it is preferable to revise the judgement than to

404 acknowledge the inconsistencies in the form of a dumbfounded response.

405 Study 2 - Online Replication

406 Study 1 demonstrated interesting variability in responses to the critical slide depending

407 on cognitive load. The aim of Study 2 was to assess the replicability of the results of Study 1,

408 using an online sample. In Study 1, the experimenter was in the room with the participants.

409 This made it more difficult for participants to cheat on the memory task. This is not possible

410 with an online sample. An alternative cognitive load manipulation was taken from De Neys

411 and Schaeken (De Neys & Schaeken, 2007), whereby a dot pattern is briefly presented to

412 participants, and participants are required to reproduce the dot pattern at a later stage.

413 Study 2: Method

414 Participants and design. Study 2 was a between subjects design. The dependent

415 variable was response to the critical slide. The independent variable was cognitive load with

416 two levels: high and low. Need for Cognition (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et al., 1984)

417 was included as a potential correlate and moderator variable.

418 A total sample of 100 participants (56 female, 44 male; M age = 38.38, min = 19, max =

419 72, SD = 12.41) took part. Participants in this sample were recruited using Amazon’s MTurk

420 (Amazon Web Services Inc., 2016). Participants were paid $0.50 for their participation.

421 Participants were recruited from English speaking countries or from countries where

422 residents generally have a high level of English (e.g., The Netherlands, Denmark, Sweden).

423 Procedure and materials. Data were collected using an online questionnaire.

424 Materials were largely the same as in Study 1, with a change to the cognitive load

425 manipulation. Cognitive load was manipulated using a dot-pattern memory task (De Neys & MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 20

426 Schaeken, 2007).

427 Participants were presented with a 3 x 3 grid containing a dot pattern. This image

428 disappeared after one second. Participants then answered a question relating to the moral

429 judgement task. Following this, participants were asked to reproduce the dot-pattern. All

430 participants took part in the memory task, and cognitive load was manipulated by varying

431 the complexity of the patterns presented (De Neys & Schaeken, 2007). The control group

432 were presented with simple patterns, containing three dots in a line, while the experimental

433 group were presented with more complex dot patterns containing 4 dots, see Figure 2.

a b

Figure 2 . Sample dot patterns - more simple for the control group (a) and higher complexity for the experimental condition (b)

434 Study 2 proceeded in much the same way as Study 1. There were four target questions

435 during which participants were engaged in the memory task. A different pattern was

436 presented before each of the following: the initial judgement, the initial opportunity to

437 provide reasons, the critical slide, and the revised judgement. After each of these questions

438 participants were required to reproduce the pattern. As in Study 1, dumbfounding was

439 measured using the critical slide.

440 Study 2: Results

441 Seventy seven participants (77%) rated the behaviour of Julie and Mark as wrong

442 initially. The mean initial rating of the behaviour was, M = 2.13, SD = 1.54. There was no MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 21

443 difference in initial judgement depending on cognitive load, t(97.77) = 0.96, p = .339; d =

444 0.19.

445 Participants who selected the admission of not having reasons on the critical slide were

446 identified as dumbfounded. Twenty six participants (26%) selected “It’s wrong but I can’t

447 think of a reason”. Fifty participants (50%) selected “It’s wrong and I can provide a valid

448 reason”; and twenty four participants (24%) selected “There is nothing wrong”.

449 Cognitive load and dumbfounded responding. A chi-squared test for

450 independence revealed no association between experimental condition and response to the

2 451 critical slide, χ (2, N = 100) = 0.74, p = .690, V = 0.09, the observed power was 0.11. The

452 responses to the critical slide for the experimental group (N = 51) and the control group (N

453 = 49) are displayed in Figure 3.

454 Engagement with the Memory Task. It is possible that the difference in results

455 observed between Study 1 and Study 2 is due to the alternative manipulation of cognitive

456 load employed. In Study 1, the control group did not engage in any task, however, adopting

457 De Neys and Shaeken’s procedure (De Neys & Schaeken, 2007), participants in the control

458 group of Study 2 engaged in a memory task. It is possible that simply engaging in a memory

459 task led to differences in responses, and that level of difficulty (the manipulation that was

460 employed) was irrelevant. Indeed, the responding to the critical slide in the control group in

461 Study 2 is more similar to the responding in the experimental group in 1 than to the control

462 group in Study 1.

463 Rates of successful reproduction of the dot patterns in Study 2 were much lower than

464 reported by De Neys and Shaeken (De Neys & Schaeken, 2007). It appears that participants

465 in Study 2 did not engage with the memory task in the same way as participants in De Neys

466 and Shaeken’s studies (De Neys & Schaeken, 2007). We hypothesised that the effectiveness

467 of the cognitive load manipulation may be moderated by the degree to which people engage

468 with the manipulation. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 22

100%

75%

Condition 49.0% 51.0% 50% Cognitive load

Control

29.4% 26.5% 25% 21.6% 22.4%

Percentage of participants selecting each response 0% 11 13 15 11 25 25

Nothing Wrong Dumbfounded Reasons Response to Critical Slide

Figure 3 . Study 2: Responses to critical slide for the experimental group (N = 51) and the control group (N = 49)

469 The memory task involved correctly placing dots in a 3 x 3 grid. For the scoring of this

470 task, each of the nine places in the grid could be marked/not marked correctly or incorrectly,

471 making 9 the total possible number of correct responses. If a person misplaced one dot in

472 the pattern this would count for 2 incorrect places in the grid: the mark in the incorrect

473 place, and the absence of a mark in the place it should have been. A participant who

474 received a score of 7, could reasonably be taken to have engaged with the task, and simply

475 made a slip. As such, this was taken as the cut-off point for identifying engagement. This

476 resulted in 56 participants being identified as engaging with the memory task, and 44 being

477 identified as not engaging with the task.

478 Responses to critical slide for participants who engaged with the memory task and MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 23

100%

75%

61.4% Condition

50% Engaged

41.1% Not Engaged 35.7%

25.0% 25% 23.2% 13.6%

Percentage of participants selecting each response 0% 13 11 20 6 23 27

Nothing Wrong Dumbfounded Reasons Response to Critical Slide

Figure 4 . Study 2: Responses to critical slide depending on engagement (N = 56) or non-engagement (N = 44) with the memory task

479 participants who did not engage with the memory task were analysed separately (see

480 Figure 4). A chi-squared test for independence revealed an association between engagement

2 481 in the memory task and response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 100) = 6.68, p = .035, V =

482 0.26, the observed power was 0.11. The responses to the critical slide for the experimental

483 group (N = 51) and the control group (N = 49) are displayed in Figure 4. The observed

484 counts, expected counts and standardised residuals are displayed in Table 2.

485 Need for Cognition. A multinomial logistic regression revealed no significant

2 486 association between Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 100) =

5 487 2.19, p = .334, the observed power was 0.24.

5 See Appendix D Figure 12 for relative probabilities of selecting each response depending on Need for Cognition. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 24

Table 2 Study 2 – Observed counts, expected counts, and standardised residuals for each response to the critical slide depending on cognitive load

Engaged Not Engaged

Observed count Nothing Wrong 13 11 Dumbfounded 20 6 Reasons 23 27 Expected count Nothing Wrong 13.44 10.56 Dumbfounded 14.56 11.44 Reasons 28 22 Standardised residuals Nothing Wrong -0.21 0.21 Dumbfounded 2.5* -2.5* Reasons -2.01* 2.01*

Note. * = sig. at p < .05; ** = sig. at p < .001

488 Study 2: Discussion

489 The aim of Study 2 was to replicate Study 1. As a replication it failed. However,

490 interesting variability was observed when engagement with the memory task was accounted

491 for. As predicted, under cognitive load (engagement with the memory task) rates of

492 providing reasons were reduced. In contrast to Study 1, the reduced rates of providing

493 reasons led to higher rates of dumbfounded responding (rather than increased rates of

494 selecting “There is nothing wrong”).

495 Two problems with the cognitive load manipulation were identified. Firstly, the control

496 did not serve as an appropriate control. Secondly, (and unsurprisingly) the manipulation is

497 only effective if participants engage with the memory task. A follow-up study addresses each

498 of these, using no task as the control for the cognitive load manipulation (e.g., Drolet & MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 25

499 Frances Luce, 2004), and assessing the responses to the memory task to ensure participants

500 adequately engaged with the load manipulation.

501 Study 3 - Revised Online Replication

502 In Study 2 the role of engagement with the memory task emerged as an important

503 moderator of the effectiveness of the cognitive load manipulation. Study 3 was conducted in

504 order to test if cognitive load affects participants’ ability to identify reasons for their

505 judgements, when accounting for engagement with the memory task.

506 Study 3: Methods

507 Participants and Design. Study 3 was a between subjects design. The dependent

508 variable was response to the critical slide. The independent variable was cognitive load with

509 two levels: present and absent. Need for Cognition (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et al.,

510 1984) was included as a potential correlate and moderator variable.

511 Following the elimination of 34 participants who scored less than 7 on the memory task

512 we were left with a final sample of 129 participants (74 female, 55 male; M age = 40.26, min

513 = 20, max = 72, SD = 13.04). Participants in this sample were recruited through MTurk

514 (under the same conditions as Study 2).

515 Procedure and Materials. Study 3 was the same as Study 2 with two changes.

516 The control group did not take part in a memory task, and to avoid task fatigue, in the dot

517 patterns presented to the experimental group, the dot patterns presented alternated between

518 the easy 3-dot patterns and the complex 4-dot patterns.

519 A score of 7 or higher on the memory task that accompanied the critical slide was

520 selected as the measure of engagement with the memory task. Only participants who

521 engaged with the task were eligible for analysis. Other than the two changes described above,

522 Study 3 was the same as Study 2. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 26

523 Study 3: Results

100%

75% 67.2%

52.9% Condition 50% Cognitive load

Control

24.6% 25.0% 25% 22.1%

8.2%

Percentage of participants selecting each response 0% 15 15 17 5 36 41

Nothing Wrong Dumbfounded Reasons Response to Critical Slide

Figure 5 . Study 3: Responses to critical slide for the cognitive load group (N = 68) and the control group (N = 61)

524 Ninety five participants (73.64%) rated the behaviour of Julie and Mark as wrong

525 initially. The mean initial rating of the behaviour was, M = 2.27, SD = 1.75. There was no

526 difference in initial judgement depending on cognitive load, t(122.69) = 0.15, p = .877; d =

527 0.03.

528 Participants who selected the admission of not having reasons on the critical slide were

529 identified as dumbfounded. Twenty two participants (17.05%) selected “It’s wrong but I

530 can’t think of a reason”. Seventy seven participants (59.69%) selected “It’s wrong and I can

531 provide a valid reason”; and thirty participants (23.26%) selected “There is nothing wrong”. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 27

Table 3 Study 3 – Observed counts, expected counts, and standardised residuals for each response to the critical slide depending on cognitive load

Cognitive Load Control

Observed count Nothing Wrong 15 15 Dumbfounded 17 5 Reasons 36 41 Expected count Nothing Wrong 15.81 14.19 Dumbfounded 11.6 10.4 Reasons 40.59 36.41 Standardised residuals Nothing Wrong -0.34 0.34 Dumbfounded 2.53* -2.53* Reasons -1.65 1.65

Note. * = sig. at p < .05; ** = sig. at p < .001

532 Cognitive load and dumbfounded responding. A chi-squared test for

533 independence revealed a significant association between experimental condition and response

2 534 to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 129) = 6.51, p = .039, V = 0.22, the observed power was

535 0.62. The responses to the critical slide for the experimental group (N = 68) and the control

536 group (N = 61) are displayed in Figure 5. The observed counts, expected counts and

537 standardised residuals are displayed in Table 3.

538 Need for Cognition. A multinomial logistic regression revealed no significant

2 539 association between Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 129) =

540 6.43, p = .040, the observed power was 0.62. Need for Cognition explained between 4.64%

541 (Cox and Snell R square) and 7.70% (Nadelkerke R squared) of the variance in responses to

542 the critical slide. As Need for Cognition increased, participants were significantly more likely

543 to provide reasons than to present as dumbfounded, Wald = 6.08, p = .014, odds ratio = MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 28

6 544 1.46, 95% CI [1.08, 1.97].

545 Study 3: Discussion

546 Study 3 partially demonstrated the predicted relationship between engagement with a

547 cognitive load task and response to the critical slide. Rates of dumbfounded responding were

548 significantly higher under cognitive load. Surprisingly, rates of providing reasons were not

549 significantly reduced under cognitive load. Study 3 did not include an objective

550 manipulation check. As such, we conducted a follow up study that included an objective

551 manipulation check.

552 Study 3 also provided some evidence that responses to the critical slide may be linked

553 with Need for Cognition. As predicted, participants who scored higher in Need for Cognition

554 were more likely to provide reasons than present as dumbfounded.

555 Study 4 - Online Replication with Manipulation Check

556 Study 3 found a significant relationship between cognitive load and response to the

557 critical slide and a significant relationship between Need for Cognition and response to the

558 critical slide. The aim of Study 4 was to replicate these findings. In addition Study 4

559 included a manipulation check to assess the effectiveness of the cognitive load manipulation

560 employed.

561 Study 4: Method

562 Participants and Design. Study 4 was a between subjects design. The dependent

563 variable was response to the critical slide. The independent variable was cognitive load with

564 two levels: present and absent. Need for Cognition (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et al.,

565 1984) was included as a potential correlate and moderator variable.

6 See Appendix D Figure 13 for relative probabilities of selecting each response depending on Need for Cognition. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 29

566 Following the elimination of 29 participants who scored less than 7 on the memory task

567 we were left with a final sample of 127 participants (84 female, 43 male; M age = 41.19, min

568 = 21, max = 74, SD = 13.91). Participants in this sample were recruited through MTurk

569 (under the same conditions as Studies 2 and 3).

570 Procedure and Materials. Study 4 was the same as Study 3 with one change, the

571 inclusion of a manipulation check. A prose paragraph was included after participants made

572 their revised judgements. Participants were then asked three comprehension questions

573 relating to the prose paragraph. It was expected that participants in the control group would

574 perform better at this task than participants under cognitive load (Just & Carpenter, 1992).

575 Study 4: Results

100%

75% 65.1%

54.7% Condition

50% Cognitive load

Control

29.7%

25% 19.0% 15.6% 15.9%

Percentage of participants selecting each response 0% 19 12 10 10 35 41

Nothing Wrong Dumbfounded Reasons Response to Critical Slide

Figure 6 . Study 4: Responses to critical slide for the cognitive load group (N = 64) and the control group (N = 61) MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 30

576 Ninety eight participants (77.17%) rated the behaviour of Julie and Mark as wrong

577 initially. The mean initial rating of the behaviour was, M = 2.09, SD = 1.62. There was no

578 difference in initial judgement depending on cognitive load, t(124.70) = 0.54, p = .589; d =

579 0.10.

580 Participants who selected the admission of not having reasons on the critical slide were

581 identified as dumbfounded. Twenty participants (15.75%) selected “It’s wrong but I can’t

582 think of a reason”. Seventy six participants (59.84%) selected “It’s wrong and I can provide a

583 valid reason”; and thirty one participants (24.41%) selected “There is nothing wrong”.

584 The responses to the manipulation check questions were investigated. There was no

585 difference in the number of correct answers to these questions between the cognitive load

586 group and the control group t(123.91) = 0.57, p = .569; d = 0.10. There was also no

587 difference in time taken to read the vignette between the groups t(63.40) = 1.62, p = .111; d

588 = 0.28.

589 Cognitive load and dumbfounded responding. A chi-squared test for

590 independence revealed no significant association between experimental condition and

2 591 response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 127) = 2.05, p = .359, V = 0.13, the observed power

592 was 0.23. The responses to the critical slide for the experimental group (N = 64) and the

593 control group (N = 63) are displayed in Figure 6. The observed counts, expected counts and

594 standardised residuals are displayed in Table 4.

595 Need for Cognition. A multinomial logistic regression revealed no statistically

2 596 significant association between Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide, χ (2, N

7 597 = 127) = 1.5, p = .472, the observed power was 0.18.

7 See Appendix D Figure 14 for relative probabilities of selecting each response depending on Need for Cognition. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 31

Table 4 Study 4 – Observed counts, expected counts, and standardised residuals for each response to the critical slide depending on cognitive load

Cognitive Load Control

Observed count Nothing Wrong 19.00 12.00 Dumbfounded 10.00 10.00 Reasons 35.00 41.00 Expected count Nothing Wrong 15.62 15.38 Dumbfounded 10.08 9.92 Reasons 38.30 37.70 Standardised residuals Nothing Wrong 1.40 -1.40 Dumbfounded -0.04 0.04 Reasons -1.19 1.19

Note. * = sig. at p < .05; ** = sig. at p < .001

598 Study 4: Discussion

599 The significant relationship between cognitive load and response to the critical slide

600 observed in previous studies was not observed in Study 4. However, the pattern of responses

601 resembled the predicted relationship and resembled the pattern of responses observed in

602 previous studies. In addition, the manipulation check did not reveal any differences between

603 the control group and the experimental group, suggesting that the cognitive load

604 manipulation was ineffective in Study 4. Studies 2, 3, and 4 were conducted using online

605 samples recruited using Amazon’s MTurk (where experimental manipulations can be

606 challenging e.g., Crump, McDonnell, & Gureckis, 2013; Goodman, Cryder, & Cheema, 2013).

607 It is possible that, in addition to the manipulation being less effective than hoped, the online

608 sample did not engage with the study as effectively as the participants in Study 1. We MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 32

609 conducted a final study to assess if the effect found in Study 1 could be replicated.

610 Study 5 - College Sample revisited

611 Given the inconclusive results across studies 1-4, Study 5 was to an attempt at a direct

612 replication of Study 1, using a larger sample.

613 Study 5: Method

614 Participants and design. Study 5 was a between subjects design. The dependent

615 variable was response to the critical slide. The independent variable was cognitive load with

616 two levels: present and absent. Need for Cognition (Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Petty et al.,

617 1984) was included as a potential correlate and moderator variable.

618 A total sample of 204 participants (144 female, 59 male; M age = 20.56, min = 18, max

619 = 48, SD = 3.86) took part. Participants in this sample were undergraduate students,

620 postgraduate students, and alumni from Mary Immaculate College (MIC), and University of

621 Limerick (UL). Participation was voluntary and participants were not reimbursed for their

622 participation.

623 Procedure and materials. Data were collected using an online questionnaire.

624 Data collection took place in a designated computer laboratory in MIC. The experimenter

625 remained in the laboratory for the duration of the study. Participants were first presented

626 with an information sheet and consent form.

627 There were two sections of the online survey: the moral judgement task, and the Need

628 for Cognition scale. The order of presentation of these was randomised. At the beginning of

629 the moral judgement task, participants in the experimental condition were presented with an

630 eight digit number/letter string and asked to memorise the sequence. After 30 seconds, the

631 experiment progressed to the next slide. Participants had the option to click “ok” and

632 progress to the next slide after 15 seconds. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 33

633 Participants were then presented with the “Julie and Mark” (Incest) vignette (Haidt et

634 al., 2000). Participants rated how right or wrong the behaviour of Julie and Mark was, and

635 were given an opportunity to provide reasons for their judgement. Following this,

636 participants were presented with a series of counter-arguments, which refuted commonly

637 used justifications for rating the behaviour as “wrong”. Dumbfounding was measured using

638 the critical slide. Following the revised judgement participants were required to reproduce

639 the number/letter string.

640 Study 5: Results

641 A total of 165 participants (80.88%) rated the behaviour of Julie and Mark as wrong

642 initially. The mean initial rating of the behaviour was, M = 2.01, SD = 1.82. There was no

643 difference in initial judgement depending on cognitive load, t(191.10) = 1.04, p = .302; d =

644 0.15.

645 Participants who selected the admission of not having reasons on the critical slide were

646 identified as dumbfounded. Forty five participants (22.06%) selected “It’s wrong but I can’t

647 think of a reason”. one hundred Nineteen participants (58.33%) selected “It’s wrong and I

648 can provide a valid reason”; and forty participants (19.61%) selected “There is nothing

649 wrong”.

650 Cognitive load manipulation check. Initial check of responses to the memory

651 task revealed that 42 participants (42.86%) successfully remembered the sequence of

652 numbers and letters. Responses to the manipulation check question revealed that 22

653 participants (22.45%) found the memory task easy. Of these, 20 participants both found the

654 task easy and got the answer right. All participants correctly remembered at least two digits

655 suggesting engagement with the manipulation.

656 The cognitive load manipulation took place before the presenting of the vignette

657 describing the behaviour to be judged. This allowed for the possibility that participants MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 34

100%

75% 64.2%

52.0% Condition 50% Cognitive load

Control

25.5% 25% 22.4% 17.0% 18.9%

Percentage of participants selecting each response 0% 22 18 25 20 51 68

Nothing Wrong Dumbfounded Reasons Response to Critical Slide

Figure 7 . Study 5: Responses to critical slide and for the experimental group (N = 98) and the control group (N = 106)

658 under cognitive load may not have engaged fully with the vignette when compared to the

659 control group. An independent samples t-test revealed no significant difference in initial

660 rating in the cognitive load group, (M = 2.15, SD = 1.97), and the control group, (M =

661 2.05, SD = 1.66), t(191.10) = 1.04 , p = 0.30; d = 0.15. An independent samples t-test

662 revealed no significant difference in initial confidence in the cognitive load group, (M = 5.51,

663 SD = 1.55), and the control group, (M = 5.83, SD = 1.49), t(199.05) = -1.50 , p = 0.14; d

664 = 0.21. In view of this, it was concluded that both groups engaged equally with the task.

665 Cognitive load and dumbfounded responding. A chi-squared test for

666 independence revealed no significant association between experimental condition and

2 667 response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 204) = 3.08, p = .215, V = 0.12, the observed power

668 was 0.33. The predicted relationship between cognitive load and dumbfounded responding MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 35

Table 5 Study 5 – Observed counts, expected counts, and standardised residuals for each response to the critical slide depending on cognitive load

Cognitive Load Control

Observed count Nothing Wrong 22.00 18.00 Dumbfounded 25.00 20.00 Reasons 51.00 68.00 Expected count Nothing Wrong 19.22 20.78 Dumbfounded 21.62 23.38 Reasons 57.17 61.83 Standardised residuals Nothing Wrong 0.98 -0.98 Dumbfounded 1.14 -1.14 Reasons -1.75 1.75

Note. * = sig. at p < .05; ** = sig. at p < .001

669 was not observed in Study 5. The responses to the critical slide for the experimental group

670 (N = 98) and the control group (N = 106) are displayed in Figure 7. The observed counts,

671 expected counts and standardised residuals are displayed in Table 5.

672 Need for Cognition. A multinomial logistic regression revealed no significant

2 673 association between Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 204) =

674 5.83, p = .054, The observed power was 0.57. Need for Cognition explained between 2.73%

675 (Cox and Snell R square) and 4.19% (Nadelkerke R squared) of the variance in responses to

676 the critical slide. As Need for Cognition increased, participants seemed to be more likely to

677 provide reasons than to present as dumbfounded, Wald = 5.48, p = .019, odds ratio = 1.54,

678 95% CI [1.07, 2.21]. (As Need for Cognition increased, participants were also possibly more

679 likely to select there is nothing wrong than present as dumbfounded Wald = 2.47, p = .116, MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 36

8 680 odds ratio = 1.42, 95% CI [0.92, 2.21].)

681 Study 5: Discussion

682 Study 5 failed to demonstrate the predicted relationship between cognitive load and

683 response to the critical slide. This provides some evidence to suggest that the failure of

684 Study 4 to demonstrate this effect is likely not due to the use of an online sample. As with

685 Study 4, the pattern of responses in Study 5 resembled the predicted relationship. The

686 overall relationship between Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide was

687 non-significant, however there were trends in the predicted direction. As noted previously,

688 the studies reported here lack the statistical power to detect anything other than a large

689 effect. As such, in the next section we aggregate the data from all the studies and conduct a

690 combined analysis. We also conduct mini-meta-analyses for the primary research question.

691 Combined Results

692 The total raw responses (without accounting for engagement with the memory task)

693 for each option on the critical slide depending on experimental condition for each study and

694 all studies combined are shown in Table 6. Taking the combined raw data for each condition

695 across all 5 studies, without accounting for engagement with the memory task, a significant

2 696 association between cognitive load and responses to the critical slide was found, χ (2, N =

697 660) = 9.79, p = .007, V = 0.12, the observed power was 0.81.

698 The total responses for each option on the critical slide for each study depending on

699 experimental condition, taking engagement with the memory task into account, are displayed

700 in Table 7. The combined results for Studies 1-5 are displayed in Figures 8 and 9. Given

701 this larger combined sample, two measures of engagement with the memory task were

702 assessed: (a) a score of 7 or higher (as in previous analyses) and (b) a score of 8 or higher.

8 See Appendix D Figure 15 for relative probabilities of selecting each response depending on Need for Cognition. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 37

Table 6 Responses to critical slide for all cognitive load studies (raw)

Cognitive Load Control

Study Response N percent N percent

Study 1* Nothing wrong 15 45% 5 15%

Dumbfounded 6 18% 7 21%

Reasons 12 36% 21 64%

Study 2 Nothing wrong 11 22% 13 27%

Dumbfounded 15 29% 11 22%

Reasons 25 49% 25 51%

Study 3* Nothing wrong 21 21% 15 25%

Dumbfounded 27 26% 5 8%

Reasons 54 53% 41 67%

Study 4 Nothing wrong 19 30% 12 19%

Dumbfounded 10 16% 10 16%

Reasons 35 55% 41 65%

Study 5 Nothing wrong 22 22% 18 17%

Dumbfounded 25 26% 20 19%

Reasons 51 52% 68 64%

All Studies* Nothing wrong 88 25% 63 20%

Dumbfounded 83 24% 53 17%

Reasons 177 51% 196 63%

Note. *significant variation at p < .05; **significant variation at p < .001 MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 38

Table 7 Responses to critical slide for all cognitive load studies (controlling for engagement)

Cognitive Load Control

Study Response N percent N percent

Study 1* Nothing wrong 15 45% 5 15%

Dumbfounded 6 18% 7 21%

Reasons 12 36% 21 64%

Study 2 (engaged a)* Nothing wrong 13 23% 11 25%

Dumbfounded 20 36% 6 14%

Reasons 23 41% 27 61%

Study 3 (engaged a)** Nothing wrong 15 22% 15 25%

Dumbfounded 17 25% 5 8%

Reasons 36 53% 41 67%

Study 4 (engaged a) Nothing wrong 19 30% 12 19%

Dumbfounded 10 16% 10 16%

Reasons 35 55% 41 65%

Study 5 Nothing wrong 22 22% 18 17%

Dumbfounded 25 26% 20 19%

Reasons 51 52% 68 64%

All studies (engaged a)** Nothing wrong 84 26% 61 20%

Dumbfounded 78 24% 48 16%

Reasons 157 49% 198 64%

All studies (engaged b)** Nothing wrong 84 27% 61 20%

Dumbfounded 77 25% 48 16%

Reasons 149 48% 198 64%

Note. *significant variation at p < .05; **significant variation at p < .001 MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 39

Table 8 Studies 1-5 – Observed counts, expected counts, and standardised residuals for each response to the critical slide depending on cognitive load

Cognitive Load Control

Observed count Nothing Wrong 84 61 Dumbfounded 78 48 Reasons 157 198 Expected count Nothing Wrong 73.89 71.11 Dumbfounded 64.21 61.79 Reasons 180.9 174.1 Standardised residuals Nothing Wrong 1.92 -1.92 Dumbfounded 2.75* -2.75* Reasons -3.86** 3.86**

Note. * = sig. at p < .05; ** = sig. at p < .001

703 When engagement with the memory task was accounted for using (a) the primary measure of

704 engagement (N = 626, 319 experimental, 307 control), a significant association between

2 705 cognitive load and responses to the critical slide was found, χ (2, N = 626) = 15.30, p <

706 .001, V = 0.16, the observed power was 0.95. The observed counts, expected counts, and

707 standardised residuals are displayed in Table 8.

708 When the stricter measure of engagement was employed (N = 617, 310 experimental,

709 307 control), a significant association between cognitive load and response to the critical

710 slide was found, (N = 617, 310 experimental, 307 control), a significant association between

2 711 cognitive load and responses to the critical slide was found, χ (2, N = 617) = 17.28, p <

712 .001, V = 0.17, the observed power was 0.97. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 40

713 Furthermore, a mini meta-analysis was conducted and found that cognitive load

2 714 significantly influenced responding across all studies χ (10) = 26.88, p = .003 (Fisher’s

715 method); or when weighting for sample size, z = 2.874, p = .002 (Stouffer’s Z-score method). MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 41

100%

75% 64.5%

Condition 49.2% 50% Cognitive load

Control

26.3% 24.5% 25% 19.9% 15.6%

Percentage of participants selecting each response 0% 84 61 78 48 157 198

Nothing Wrong Dumbfounded Reasons Response to Critical Slide

Figure 8 . Studies 1-5: Responses to critical slide for the cognitive load groups (N = 309) and the control groups (N = 317) controlling for engagement (a) at > 6 correct MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 42

100%

75%

67.2% 65.1% 63.6% 64.2% 61.4%

54.7% condition 52.9% 52.0% 50% Load/Engaged

41.1% Control 36.4%

25% % of participants providing reasons for their judgements

0% 12 21 23 27 36 41 35 41 51 68

Study 1 Study 2 a Study 3 a Study 4 a Study 5 N=66 N=100 N=129 N=127 N=204 Study

Figure 9 . Rates of declaring reasons and cognitive load across each study MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 43

716 Need for Cognition

717 A multinomial logistic regression revealed a statistically significant association between

2 718 Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide, χ (2, N = 654) = 12.15, p = .002, The

719 observed power was 0.89. Need for Cognition explained between 2.52% (Cox and Snell R

720 square) and 3.94% (Nadelkerke R squared) of the variance in responses to the critical slide.

721 As Need for Cognition increased, participants were significantly more likely to provide

722 reasons than to present as dumbfounded, Wald = 11.01, p < .001, odds ratio = 1.27, 95% CI

723 [1.10, 1.46]. As Need for Cognition increased, participants were also significantly more likely

724 to select there is nothing wrong than present as dumbfounded Wald = 7.86, p = .005, odds

725 ratio = 1.27, 95% CI [1.07, 1.50]. The relative probabilities of selecting each response to the

726 critical slide depending on Need for Cognition are displayed in Figure 10.

1.00

0.75

Response to Critical Slide

Dumbfounded 0.50 Nothing Wrong

Reasons Predicted Probability

0.25

0.00

−4 −2 0 2 4 Need for Cognition

Figure 10 . Studies 1-5: Probability of selecting each response to the critical slide depending on Need for Cognition MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 44

727 General Discussion

728 We conducted five studies to test a conflict in dual-processes explanation of moral

729 dumbfounding. We hypothesised that moral dumbfounding emerges as a result of conflict

730 between a habitual/intuitive response and deliberation. We found some evidence in support

731 of this explanation of moral dumbfounding. This evidence was not as strong as expected.

732 This may be due to limitations in the methods employed, or it may be evidence that the

733 explanation tested here does not capture the full complexity of the phenomenon.

734 Interpreting the Results

735 The relative roles of intuition and deliberation in producing each of the possible

736 responses in the dumbfounding paradigm were identified, and these responses were ranked

737 according to level of deliberation involved in each. The responses are as follows: (1) reason;

738 (2) nothing wrong; and (3) dumbfounding. We hypothesised that, (1) a reason response

739 involves the most deliberation. The relative roles of intuition and deliberation in the

740 remaining responses were less clear, particularly because of the possibility of that competing

741 intuitions may emerge. If deliberation fails to identify justifications for an initial intuition, a

742 person may find that they must choose between two competing intuitions (initial judgement;

743 that moral judgements should be justifiable). Despite this limitation, a clear candidate for

744 relying on deliberation the most was identified: (1) reason.

745 Cognitive load and Providing Reasons. Having identified a response that

746 clearly relied on deliberation more than the other responses, an experimental manipulation

747 that is known to influence deliberative responding was selected for study: cognitive load (De

748 Neys, 2006; Evans & Curtis-Holmes, 2005; Evans & Stanovich, 2013; Schmidt, 2016). In

749 addition to this, an individual difference variable that has to been linked to a tendency to

750 engage in deliberation was identified and selected for investigation (Need for Cognition,

751 Cacioppo & Petty, 1982; Evans & Stanovich, 2013; Petty et al., 1984). Five studies were

752 conducted investigating cognitive load and moral dumbfounding. The target response was MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 45

753 “It’s wrong and I can provide a valid reason” on the critical slide. We hypothesised that

754 cognitive load would inhibit participants’ ability to provide reasons for their judgements, and

755 that under cognitive load reduced incidences of participants stating they could provide a

756 reason would be observed. We also hypothesised that providing reasons would be related to

757 Need for Cognition scores, such that participants who score higher on Need for Cognition

758 would be more likely to provide reasons than select any other response on the critical slide.

759 Study 1 showed a clear reduction in providing reasons for a judgement depending on

760 cognitive load (resulting in an increase in selecting “There is nothing wrong”). The results of

761 Study 2 indicated that any effect cognitive load had on ability to generate reasons for a

762 judgement was related to level of engagement with the cognitive load task. Study 3

763 demonstrated that when controlling for engagement with the cognitive load task, cognitive

764 load led to higher rates of dumbfounding. However, Studies 4 and 5 failed to replicate these

765 findings. Three studies described here therefore showed that participants actively engaging

766 with cognitive load task were consistently less effective at identifying reasons for their

767 judgements. Studies 4 and 5 showed a similar pattern of responses, however this was not

768 statistically significant.

769 Need for Cognition in the Dumbfounding Paradigm. There was no

770 significant relationship between Need for Cognition and the critical slide for Studies 1, 2, 4,

771 and 5. In Study 3, higher Need for Cognition predicted higher rates of providing reasons

772 than dumbfounded responding. In the combined analysis, higher Need for Cognition scores

773 predicted higher rates of both providing reasons and selecting “there is nothing wrong” and

774 reduced rates of dumbfounded responding.

775 Key Findings. The combined results of Studies 1-5 appear to indicate that engaging

776 in a cognitive load task leads to reduced incidences of providing reasons (as hypothesised).

777 Studies 4 and 5 to failed replicate this effect, so caution is advised when interpreting this

778 result, however, given the consistency in the pattern of responses, the clear result in the

779 combined analysis, and in the meta-analysis, it is likely that the failure to replicate the effect MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 46

780 was due to a lack of statistical power. Furthermore, dumbfounded responding appeared to be

781 linked to lower Need for Cognition scores. Again, caution is advised in interpreting this

782 result, particularly given that only 1 (Study 3) of the Studies 1-5 individually found any

783 relationship between Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide.

784 Implications

785 Overall, the results of the studies described here provide some evidence for the conflict

786 in dual-processes explanation of moral dumbfounding identified here, however the

787 inconsistencies in the results poses a challenge to this finding. Despite the inconsistencies,

788 the studies described here do not provide convincing evidence that this explanation of moral

789 dumbfounding is wrong. From these somewhat mixed results, what seems clear is that moral

790 dumbfounding is not a simple matter of habitual or deliberative responses. The complexity

791 of moral dumbfounding becomes apparent when attempting to describe the various possible

792 responses in the paradigm in terms of the relative roles of deliberation and intuition. The

793 possibility that a failure of deliberation to provide reasons for an intuition may lead to

794 alternative and competing intuitions to become salient means that in some cases, moral

795 dumbfounding may involve conflict between competing intuitions.

796 The apparent conflict between competing intuitions is more complicated than conflict

797 between intuition and deliberation. Recall that the examples of conflict identified above

798 clearly pitted an intuitive response against a deliberative response, and resolution of this

799 conflict was relatively straight forward. For example, in base-rate neglect problems there is

800 only one correct answer. The intuitive response is incorrect and deliberation leads to an

801 alternative response. This conflict is easily resolved because deliberation has clearly identified

802 the intuitive response as incorrect. In contrast moral judgements are not clearly correct or

803 incorrect and the failure of deliberation to identify reasons for an intuition is not necessarily

804 evidence that the intuition is incorrect. That moral dumbfounding is more complicated than

805 classic cases of conflict in dual-processes does not necessarily mean that attempting to MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 47

806 explain moral dumbfounding as the result of dual-process conflict is without merit. It is

807 possible that conflict in dual-processes is still implicated in moral dumbfounding. However,

808 where conflict is normally resolved through suppression of erroneous intuitive responses, in

809 the dumbfounding paradigm this conflict is not easily resolved leading participants are faced

810 with a conflict between competing intuitions. Given that this explanation identifies

811 dumbfounding as arising from conflict between competing intuitions (same underlying

812 mechanisms) as opposed to conflict between intuition and deliberation (different underlying

813 mechanisms) means that testing this explanation is particularly problematic.

814 Limitations and Future Directions

815 There are a number of related limitations of the studies conducted here that may have

816 contributed to the inconclusive results in different ways. Firstly, it is possible that the

817 inconclusive result is due to limitations in the method of data collection employed across

818 Studies 2, 3, and 4. Online data collection through MTurk is useful for ease of access to

819 willing participants resulting in highly efficient data collection. However, the absence of

820 oversight or supervision of participants taking part in the studies means that complex

821 manipulations such as cognitive load manipulations may not be as successful as in a

822 controlled laboratory setting (Crump et al., 2013; Goodman et al., 2013). In response to the

823 difficulties in manipulating cognitive load in an online study, we conducted an additional

824 study (Study 5) returning to a college sample where the study took place in a controlled

825 environment, under the supervision of the experimenter.

826 The failure of Study 5 to replicate the findings of Studies 1, 2, and 3 may be due to the

827 nature of the variables used. The dependent variable in these studies is nominal/categorical.

828 This variable type is not well suited for identifying small or subtle effects; consider the

829 extensive research identifying disgust effects on moral judgements (e.g., Cameron et al., 2013;

830 David & Olatunji, 2011; Landy & Goodwin, 2015; Rozin, Haidt, & MacCauley, 2009; Russell

831 & Giner-Sorolla, 2011; Sabo & Giner-Sorolla, 2017; Schnall, Haidt, Clore, & Jordan, 2008; MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 48

832 Wheatley & Haidt, 2005). May (2014) noted that the effect of incidental disgust is largely on

833 the severity of a judgement, as opposed to altering the valence of the judgement. The use of

834 a binary right/wrong measure of judgements therefore would fail to identify any effect for

835 disgust on moral judgements. As such, the measures used in the dumbfounding paradigm

836 mean that identifying influences on dumbfounding is particularly challenging, because minor

837 influences on people’s ability to provide reasons may not yield measurable effects.

838 Conclusion

839 The studies described here aimed to investigate if cognitive load influenced the degree

840 to which people successfully identified reasons for their judgements. The individual

841 difference variable Need for Cognition was also investigated.

842 For 4 of the 5 studies conducted, there did not appear to be a relationship between

843 Need for Cognition and response to the critical slide, however in Study 3, and the final

844 analysis of all the studies together, lower Need for Cognition scores were associated with

845 dumbfounded responding. The effect size was quite small, and this effect only emerged in 1

846 study, and when all the data were combined. However, this may prove useful in furthering

847 our understanding of moral dumbfounding and the making of moral judgements more

848 generally. That dumbfounding may be weakly related to scoring lower on Need for Cognition

849 is interesting and may provide a useful area for follow-up work.

850 The primary aim of this paper was to test a dual-process conflict explanation of moral

851 dumbfounding. According to this view, providing reasons for a judgement is grounded in

852 deliberation, and dumbfounded responding is grounded in habitual responding. The extent

853 to which revising a judgement is grounded in deliberation or habitual responding is unclear,

854 and may vary depending on the individual. The key prediction of this explanation is that

855 inhibiting deliberative responding, through a cognitive load manipulation, would inhibit the

856 identification of reasons. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 49

857 The studies presented here offer suggestive evidence that cognitive load inhibits the

858 identification of reasons in the dumbfounding paradigm. Engagement with the cognitive load

859 manipulation on the part of the participants is essential for it to successfully inhibit the

860 identification of reasons. The pattern of responses across the studies is consistent with the

861 possibility that revising a judgement requires more deliberation than providing a

862 dumbfounded response, however this claim was not tested directly, and there is no clear

863 evidence in support of it. Some evidence in support of the primary prediction, that

864 inhibiting deliberative responding should inhibit the identification of reasons was found.

865 This suggests that a dumbfounded response is a more habitual/intuitive response whereas

866 providing reasons relies more on deliberative responding. But that the processes that give

867 rise to judgements and reason-giving in complex situations are not simply the operation

868 dual-systems or a conflict between them, but a complex of interacting processes in which

869 these aspects play a role.

870 Data Accessibility Statement

871 All participant data, and analysis scripts can be found on this paper’s project page on

872 the Open Science Framework at https://osf.io/wge5t/.

873 All statistical analysis was conducted using R (Version 3.6.1; R Core Team, 2017) and

874 the R-packages afex (Version 0.25.1; Singmann, Bolker, & Westfall, 2015), car (Version 3.0.3;

875 Fox & Weisberg, 2011; Fox, Weisberg, & Price, 2018), carData (Version 3.0.2; Fox et al.,

876 2018), citr (Version 0.3.0; Aust, 2016), DescTools (Version 0.99.28; et mult. al., 2019),

877 desnum (Version 0.1.1; McHugh, 2017), dplyr (Version 0.8.3; Wickham, Francois, Henry, &

878 Müller, 2017), emmeans (Version 1.4.1; Lenth, 2019), extrafont (Version 0.17; Chang, 2014),

879 foreign (Version 0.8.72; R Core Team, 2018), Formula (Version 1.2.3; Zeileis & Croissant,

880 2010), ggplot2 (Version 3.2.1; Wickham, 2009), knitr (Version 1.23; Xie, 2015), koRpus

881 (Version 0.11.5; Michalke, 2018a, 2019), koRpus.lang.en (Version 0.1.3; Michalke, 2019), lme4

882 (Version 1.1.21; Bates, Mächler, Bolker, & Walker, 2015), lmtest (Version 0.9.36; Zeileis & MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 50

883 Hothorn, 2002), lsmeans (Version 2.30.0; Lenth, 2016), lsr (Version 0.5; Navarro, 2015),

884 Matrix (Version 1.2.17; Bates & Maechler, 2017), metap (Version 1.1; Dewey, 2017), mlogit

885 (Version 0.4.1; Croissant, 2013), nnet (Version 7.3.12; Venables & Ripley, 2002), papaja

886 (Version 0.1.0.9842; Aust & Barth, 2018), plyr (Version 1.8.4; Wickham et al., 2017;

887 Wickham, 2011), powerMediation (Version 0.2.9; Qiu, 2018), pwr (Version 1.2.2; Champely,

888 2018), reshape2 (Version 1.4.3; Wickham, 2007), scales (Version 1.0.0; Wickham, 2016),

889 sjstats (Version 0.17.4; Lüdecke, 2018), sylly (Version 0.1.5; Michalke, 2018b), tibble (Version

890 2.1.3; Müller & Wickham, 2017), VGAM (Version 1.1.1; Yee & Wild, 1996; Yee, 2010, 2013;

891 Yee & Hadi, 2014; Yee, Stoklosa, & Huggins, 2015), wordcountaddin (Version 0.3.0.9000;

892 Marwick, 2019), and zoo (Version 1.8.6; Zeileis & Grothendieck, 2005). MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 51

893 References

894 Abelson, R. P. (1988). Conviction. American Psychologist, 43 (4), 267–275.

895 doi:10.1037/0003-066X.43.4.267

896 Amazon Web Services Inc. (2016). Amazon Mechanical Turk.

897 Aust, F. (2016). Citr: ’RStudio’ Add-in to Insert Markdown Citations. Retrieved from

898 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=citr

899 Aust, F., & Barth, M. (2018). Papaja: Create APA manuscripts with R Markdown.

900 Retrieved from https://github.com/crsh/papaja

901 Bates, D., & Maechler, M. (2017). Matrix: Sparse and Dense Matrix Classes and Methods.

902 Retrieved from https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=Matrix

903 Bates, D., Mächler, M., Bolker, B., & Walker, S. (2015). Fitting Linear Mixed-Effects Models

904 Using lme4. Journal of Statistical Software, 67 (1), 1–48. doi:10.18637/jss.v067.i01

905 Bonner, C., & Newell, B. R. (2010). In conflict with ourselves? An investigation of

906 and analytic processes in decision making. Memory & Cognition, 38 (2), 186–196.

907 doi:10.3758/MC.38.2.186

908 Brand, C. (2016). Dual-Process Theories in Moral : Interdisciplinary Approaches

909 to Theoretical, Empirical and Practical Considerations. Springer.

910 Cacioppo, J. T., & Petty, R. E. (1982). The need for cognition. Journal of Personality and

911 , 42 (1), 116–131. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.42.1.116

912 Cameron, C. D., Payne, B. K., & Doris, J. M. (2013). Morality in high definition: Emotion

913 differentiation calibrates the influence of incidental disgust on moral judgments.

914 Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 49 (4), 719–725. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 52

915 doi:10.1016/j.jesp.2013.02.014

916 Champely, S. (2018). Pwr: Basic Functions for Power Analysis. Retrieved from

917 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=pwr

918 Chang, W. (2014). Extrafont: Tools for using fonts. Retrieved from

919 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=extrafont

920 Crockett, M. J. (2013). Models of morality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17 (8), 363–366.

921 doi:10.1016/j.tics.2013.06.005

922 Croissant, Y. (2013). Mlogit: Multinomial logit model. Retrieved from

923 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=mlogit

924 Crump, M. J. C., McDonnell, J. V., & Gureckis, T. M. (2013). Evaluating Amazon’s

925 Mechanical Turk as a Tool for Experimental Behavioral Research. PLOS ONE, 8 (3),

926 e57410. doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0057410

927 Cushman, F. A. (2013). Action, Outcome, and Value A Dual-System Framework for

928 Morality. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17 (3), 273–292.

929 doi:10.1177/1088868313495594

930 Cushman, F. A., Young, L., & Greene, J. D. (2010). Multi-system . In J.

931 M. Doris (Ed.), The Moral Psychology Handbook (pp. 47–71). Oxford; New York:

932 Oxford University Press.

933 David, B., & Olatunji, B. O. (2011). The effect of disgust conditioning and disgust

934 sensitivity on appraisals of moral transgressions. Personality and Individual

935 Differences, 50 (7), 1142–1146. doi:10.1016/j.paid.2011.02.004

936 De Neys, W. (2006). Dual Processing in Reasoning: Two Systems but One Reasoner.

937 Psychological Science, 17 (5), 428–433. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01723.x MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 53

938 De Neys, W. (2012). Bias and Conflict: A Case for Logical Intuitions. Perspectives on

939 Psychological Science, 7 (1), 28–38. doi:10.1177/1745691611429354

940 De Neys, W., & Glumicic, T. (2008). Conflict monitoring in dual process theories of

941 thinking. Cognition, 106 (3), 1248–1299. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2007.06.002

942 De Neys, W., & Schaeken, W. (2007). When people are more logical under cognitive load:

943 Dual task impact on scalar implicature. Experimental Psychology, 54 (2), 128–133.

944 doi:10.1027/1618-3169.54.2.128

945 Dewey, M. (2017). Metap: Meta-analysis of significance values.

946 Drolet, A., & Frances Luce, M. (2004). The Rationalizing Effects of Cognitive Load on

947 Emotion-Based Trade-off Avoidance. Journal of Consumer Research, 31 (1), 63–77.

948 doi:10.1086/383424

949 et mult. al., A. S. (2019). DescTools: Tools for Descriptive Statistics. Retrieved from

950 https://cran.r-project.org/package=DescTools

951 Evans, J. S. B. T. (2007). On the resolution of conflict in dual process theories of reasoning.

952 Thinking & Reasoning, 13 (4), 321–339. doi:10.1080/13546780601008825

953 Evans, J. S. B. T. (2008). Dual-Processing Accounts of Reasoning, Judgment, and Social

954 Cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59 (1), 255–278.

955 doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.59.103006.093629

956 Evans, J. S. B. T., & Curtis-Holmes, J. (2005). Rapid responding increases :

957 Evidence for the dual-process theory of reasoning. Thinking & Reasoning, 11 (4),

958 382–389. doi:10.1080/13546780542000005

959 Evans, J. S. B. T., & Stanovich, K. E. (2013). Dual-Process Theories of Higher Cognition:

960 Advancing the Debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8 (3), 223–241. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 54

961 doi:10.1177/1745691612460685

962 Forsterlee, R., & Ho, R. (1999). An Examination of the Short form of the Need for

963 Cognition Scale Applied in an Australian Sample. Educational and Psychological

964 Measurement, 59 (3), 471–480. doi:10.1177/00131649921969983

965 Fox, J., & Weisberg, S. (2011). An R Companion to Applied Regression (Second.). Thousand

966 Oaks CA: Sage. Retrieved from

967 http://socserv.socsci.mcmaster.ca/jfox/Books/Companion

968 Fox, J., Weisberg, S., & Price, B. (2018). carData: Companion to Applied Regression Data

969 Sets. Retrieved from https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=carData

970 Goodman, J. K., Cryder, C. E., & Cheema, A. (2013). Data Collection in a Flat World: The

971 Strengths and Weaknesses of Mechanical Turk Samples. Journal of Behavioral

972 Decision Making, 26 (3), 213–224. doi:10.1002/bdm.1753

973 Greene, J. D. (2008). The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral

974 Psychology Volume 3: The neurosciences of morality: Emotion, brain disorders, and

975 development (pp. 35–79). Cambridge (Mass.): the MIT press.

976 Greene, J. D., Morelli, S. A., Lowenberg, K., Nystrom, L. E., & Cohen, J. D. (2008).

977 Cognitive load selectively interferes with utilitarian moral judgment. Cognition,

978 107 (3), 1144–1154. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2007.11.004

979 Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to

980 moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108 (4), 814–834.

981 doi:10.1037/0033-295X.108.4.814

982 Haidt, J., & Björklund, F. (2008). Social Intuitionists Answer Six Questions about Moral

983 Psychology. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong (Ed.), Moral psychology Volume 2, The MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 55

984 cognitive science of morality: Intuition and diversity (pp. 181–217). London: MIT.

985 Haidt, J., Björklund, F., & Murphy, S. (2000). Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds

986 no reason. Unpublished Manuscript, University of Virginia.

987 Just, M. A., & Carpenter, P. A. (1992). A capacity theory of comprehension: Individual

988 differences in . Psychological Review, 99 (1), 122–149.

989 doi:10.1037/0033-295X.99.1.122

990 Kruglanski, A. W., & Webster, D. M. (1996). Motivated closing of the mind: "Seizing" and

991 "freezing.". Psychological Review, 103 (2), 263–283. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.103.2.263

992 Kruglanski, A. W., Webster, D. M., & Klem, A. (1993). Motivated resistance and openness

993 to persuasion in the presence or absence of prior information. Journal of Personality

994 and Social Psychology, 65 (5), 861–876. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.65.5.861

995 Landy, J. F., & Goodwin, G. P. (2015). Does Incidental Disgust Amplify Moral Judgment?

996 A Meta-Analytic Review of Experimental Evidence. Perspectives on Psychological

997 Science, 10 (4), 518–536. doi:10.1177/1745691615583128

998 Lenth, R. (2019). Emmeans: Estimated Marginal Means, aka Least-Squares Means.

999 Retrieved from https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=emmeans

1000 Lenth, R. V. (2016). Least-Squares Means: The R Package lsmeans. Journal of Statistical

1001 Software, 69 (1), 1–33. doi:10.18637/jss.v069.i01

1002 Lerner, M. J., & Goldberg, J. H. (1999). When Do Decent People Blame Victims? The

1003 Differing Effects of the Explicit/Rational and Implicit/Experiential Cognitive

1004 Systems. In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process Theories in Social

1005 Psychology (pp. 627–640). Guilford Press.

1006 Lüdecke, D. (2018). Sjstats: Statistical Functions for Regression Models. Retrieved from MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 56

1007 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=sjstats

1008 Marwick, B. (2019). Wordcountaddin: Word counts and readability statistics in R markdown

1009 documents.

1010 May, J. (2014). Does Disgust Influence Moral Judgment? Australasian Journal of

1011 Philosophy, 92 (1), 125–141.

1012 McGregor, I. (2006a). Offensive Defensiveness: Toward an Integrative Neuroscience of

1013 Compensatory Zeal After Mortality Salience, Personal Uncertainty, and Other

1014 Poignant Self-Threats. Psychological Inquiry, 17 (4), 299–308.

1015 doi:10.1080/10478400701366977

1016 McGregor, I. (2006b). Zeal Appeal: The Allure of Moral Extremes. Basic and Applied Social

1017 Psychology, 28 (4), 343–348. doi:10.1207/s15324834basp2804_7

1018 McGregor, I., Zanna, M. P., Holmes, J. G., & Spencer, S. J. (2001). Compensatory

1019 conviction in the face of personal uncertainty: Going to extremes and being oneself.

1020 Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80 (3), 472–488.

1021 doi:10.1037/0022-3514.80.3.472

1022 McHugh, C. (2017). Desnum: Creates some useful functions. Retrieved from

1023 https://github.com/cillianmiltown/R_desnum

1024 McHugh, C., McGann, M., Igou, E. R., & Kinsella, E. L. (2017). Searching for Moral

1025 Dumbfounding: Identifying Measurable Indicators of Moral Dumbfounding. Collabra:

1026 Psychology, 3 (1). doi:10.1525/collabra.79

1027 Michalke, M. (2018a). koRpus: An R Package for Text Analysis. Retrieved from

1028 https://reaktanz.de/?c=hacking&s=koRpus

1029 Michalke, M. (2018b). Sylly: Hyphenation and Syllable Counting for Text Analysis. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 57

1030 Retrieved from https://reaktanz.de/?c=hacking&s=sylly

1031 Michalke, M. (2019). koRpus.Lang.En: Language Support for ’koRpus’ Package: English.

1032 Retrieved from https://reaktanz.de/?c=hacking&s=koRpus

1033 Müller, K., & Wickham, H. (2017). Tibble: Simple Data Frames. Retrieved from

1034 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=tibble

1035 Navarro, D. (2015). Learning statistics with R: A tutorial for psychology students and other

1036 beginners. (Version 0.5). Adelaide, Australia: University of Adelaide. Retrieved from

1037 http://ua.edu.au/ccs/teaching/lsr

1038 Petty, R. E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Kao, C. F. (1984). The efficient assessment of need for

1039 cognition. Journal of Personality Assessment, 48 (3), 306–307.

1040 Petty, R. E., Feinstein, J. A., Blair, W., & Jarvis, G. (1996). Dispositional differences in

1041 cognitive motivation: The life and times of individuals varying in need for cognition.

1042 Psych. Bull, 197–253.

1043 Prinz, J. J. (2005). Passionate Thoughts: The Emotional Embodiment of Moral Concepts.

1044 In D. Pecher & R. A. Zwaan (Eds.), Grounding Cognition: The Role of Perception

1045 and Action in Memory, Language, and Thinking (pp. 93–114). Cambridge University

1046 Press.

1047 Qiu, W. (2018). powerMediation: Power/Sample Size Calculation for Mediation Analysis.

1048 Retrieved from https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=powerMediation

1049 R Core Team. (2017). R: A Language and Environment for Statistical Computing. Vienna,

1050 Austria: R Foundation for Statistical Computing. Retrieved from

1051 https://www.R-project.org/

1052 R Core Team. (2018). Foreign: Read Data Stored by ’Minitab’, ’S’, ’SAS’, ’SPSS’, ’Stata’, MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 58

1053 ’Systat’, ’Weka’, ’dBase’, ... Retrieved from

1054 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=foreign

1055 Royzman, E. B., Kim, K., & Leeman, R. F. (2015). The curious tale of Julie and Mark:

1056 Unraveling the moral dumbfounding effect. Judgment and Decision Making, 10 (4),

1057 296–313.

1058 Rozin, P., Haidt, J., & MacCauley, C. (2009). Disgust: The body and soul emotion in the

1059 21st century. na.

1060 Rozin, P., Markwith, M., & McCauley, C. (1994). Sensitivity to indirect contacts with other

1061 persons: AIDS aversion as a composite of aversion to strangers, infection, moral taint,

1062 and misfortune. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 103 (3), 495–504.

1063 doi:10.1037/0021-843X.103.3.495

1064 Russell, P. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2011). Social Justifications for Moral Emotions: When

1065 Reasons for Disgust Are Less Elaborated Than for Anger. Emotion, 11 (3), 637–646.

1066 doi:10.1037/a0022600

1067 Sabo, J. S., & Giner-Sorolla, R. (2017). Imagining Wrong: Fictitious Contexts Mitigate

1068 Condemnation of Harm More Than Impurity. Journal of Experimental Psychology:

1069 General, 146 (1), 134–153. doi:10.1037/xge0000251

1070 Schmidt, D. (2016). The Effects of Cognitive Load and Stereotyped Groups on Punitiveness.

1071 CMC Senior Theses.

1072 Schnall, S., Haidt, J., Clore, G. L., & Jordan, A. H. (2008). Disgust as Embodied Moral

1073 Judgment. Personality & Social Psychology Bulletin, 34 (8), 1096–1109.

1074 doi:10.1177/0146167208317771

1075 Singmann, H., Bolker, B., & Westfall, J. (2015). Afex: Analysis of Factorial Experiments. MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 59

1076 Retrieved from https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=afex

1077 Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: The

1078 conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90 (4), 293–315.

1079 doi:10.1037/0033-295X.90.4.293

1080 Venables, W. N., & Ripley, B. D. (2002). Modern Applied Statistics with S (Fourth.). New

1081 York: Springer. Retrieved from http://www.stats.ox.ac.uk/pub/MASS4

1082 Wheatley, T., & Haidt, J. (2005). Hypnotic Disgust Makes Moral Judgments More Severe.

1083 Psychological Science, 16 (10), 780–784. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2005.01614.x

1084 Wickham, H. (2007). Reshaping Data with the reshape Package. Journal of Statistical

1085 Software, 21 (12), 1–20. Retrieved from http://www.jstatsoft.org/v21/i12/

1086 Wickham, H. (2009). Ggplot2: Elegant Graphics for Data Analysis. Springer-Verlag New

1087 York. Retrieved from http://ggplot2.org

1088 Wickham, H. (2011). The Split-Apply-Combine Strategy for Data Analysis. Journal of

1089 Statistical Software, 40 (1), 1–29. Retrieved from http://www.jstatsoft.org/v40/i01/

1090 Wickham, H. (2016). Scales: Scale Functions for Visualization. Retrieved from

1091 https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=scales

1092 Wickham, H., Francois, R., Henry, L., & Müller, K. (2017). Dplyr: A Grammar of Data

1093 Manipulation. Retrieved from https://CRAN.R-project.org/package=dplyr

1094 Xie, Y. (2015). Dynamic Documents with R and knitr (2nd ed.). Boca Raton, Florida:

1095 Chapman and Hall/CRC. Retrieved from http://yihui.name/knitr/

1096 Yee, T. W. (2010). The VGAM Package for Categorical Data Analysis. Journal of Statistical

1097 Software, 32 (10), 1–34. Retrieved from http://www.jstatsoft.org/v32/i10/ MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 60

1098 Yee, T. W. (2013). Two-parameter reduced-rank vector generalized linear models.

1099 Computational Statistics and Data Analysis. Retrieved from

1100 http://ees.elsevier.com/csda

1101 Yee, T. W., & Hadi, A. F. (2014). Row-column interaction models, with an R

1102 implementation. Computational Statistics, 29 (6), 1427–1445.

1103 Yee, T. W., Stoklosa, J., & Huggins, R. M. (2015). The VGAM Package for

1104 Capture-Recapture Data Using the Conditional Likelihood. Journal of Statistical

1105 Software, 65 (5), 1–33. Retrieved from http://www.jstatsoft.org/v65/i05/

1106 Yee, T. W., & Wild, C. J. (1996). Vector Generalized Additive Models. Journal of Royal

1107 Statistical Society, Series B, 58 (3), 481–493.

1108 Zeileis, A., & Croissant, Y. (2010). Extended Model Formulas in R: Multiple Parts and

1109 Multiple Responses. Journal of Statistical Software, 34 (1), 1–13.

1110 doi:10.18637/jss.v034.i01

1111 Zeileis, A., & Grothendieck, G. (2005). Zoo: S3 Infrastructure for Regular and Irregular

1112 Time Series. Journal of Statistical Software, 14 (6), 1–27. doi:10.18637/jss.v014.i06

1113 Zeileis, A., & Hothorn, T. (2002). Diagnostic Checking in Regression Relationships. R News,

1114 2 (3), 7–10. Retrieved from https://CRAN.R-project.org/doc/Rnews/ MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 61

1115 Appendices

1116 Appendix A: Moral Scenarios

1117 Incest

1118 Julie and Mark, who are brother and sister, are travelling together in France. They

1119 are both on summer vacation from college. One night they are staying alone in a cabin near

1120 the beach. They decide that it would be interesting and fun if they tried making love. At

1121 very least it would be a new experience for each of them. Julie was already taking birth

1122 control pills, but Mark uses a condom too, just to be safe. They both enjoy it, but they

1123 decide not to do it again. They keep that night as a special secret between them, which

1124 makes them feel even closer to each other (Haidt et al., 2000). MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 62

1125 Appendix B: Sample Statements to Challenge Judgements

1126 Incest

1127 • Do you not agree that any concerns regarding reproductive complications are eased by

1128 their using of two forms of contraception?

1129 • And do you accept that they are both consenting adults, and that they both consented

1130 and enjoyed it?

1131 • And do you concede that nobody else was affected by their actions? MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 63

1132 Appendix C: Post Discussion Questionnaire

1133 How sure were you about your judgement?

1134 1 2 3 4 5 6 7

1135 Not at all Extremely sure

1136 ______

1137 How much did you change your mind?

1138 1 2 3 4 5 6 7

1139 Not at all Extremely

1140 ______

1141 How confused were you?

1142 1 2 3 4 5 6 7

1143 Not at all Extremely confused

1144 ______

1145 How irritated were you?

1146 1 2 3 4 5 6 7

1147 Not at all Extremely irritated

1148 ______

1149 How much was your judgement based on reason? MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 64

1150 1 2 3 4 5 6 7

1151 Not at all Extremely

1152 ______

1153 How much was your judgement based on “gut” feeling?

1154 1 2 3 4 5 6 7

1155 Not at all Extremely MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 65

1156 Appendix D: Need for Cognition and Responses to the Critical Slide

1.00

0.75

Response to Critical Slide

Dumbfounded 0.50 Nothing Wrong

Reasons Predicted Probability

0.25

0.00

−2 0 2 Need for Cognition

Figure 11 . Study 1: Probability of selecting each response to the critical slide depending on Need for Cognition MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 66

1.00

0.75

Response to Critical Slide

Dumbfounded 0.50 Nothing Wrong

Reasons Predicted Probability

0.25

0.00

−4 −2 0 2 Need for Cognition

Figure 12 . Study 2: Probability of selecting each response to the critical slide depending on Need for Cognition

1.00

0.75

Response to Critical Slide

Dumbfounded 0.50 Nothing Wrong

Reasons Predicted Probability

0.25

0.00

−4 −2 0 2 4 Need for Cognition

Figure 13 . Study 3: Probability of selecting each response to the critical slide depending on Need for Cognition MANIPULATING MORAL DUMBFOUNDING 67

1.00

0.75

Response to Critical Slide

Dumbfounded 0.50 Nothing Wrong

Reasons Predicted Probability

0.25

0.00

−2 0 2 4 Need for Cognition

Figure 14 . Study 4: Probability of selecting each response to the critical slide depending on Need for Cognition

1.00

0.75

Response to Critical Slide

Dumbfounded 0.50 Nothing Wrong

Reasons Predicted Probability

0.25

0.00

−2 0 2 4 Need for Cognition

Figure 15 . Study 5: Probability of selecting each response to the critical slide depending on Need for Cognition