Completeness Criterion for Saturated Models

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Completeness Criterion for Saturated Models Model Theory - Broadening Assessment Adam Keilthy December 11, 2019 1 Introduction The goal of this note is to develop a completeness criterion for a theory T , analogous to theLos-Vaught test for completeness, by considering saturated models of cardinality @1. However, there are issues with this approach; in particular, within standard set theory, there is no guarentee of the existence of such models. As such, we will assume the generalised continuum hypothesis (GCH) @α 2 = @α+1 in order to ensure our constructions work. This note will proceed as follows. We will first establish common notions, recalling various core definitions and notations that will be used in our discus- sion. We will then introduce the idea of ultrafilters and ultraproducts, which we use to establish the existence of saturated models. We finally provide an analogue of theLos-Vaught test for completeness. 2 Preliminary Definitions We assume the reader is familiar with the definitions of a first order language, a model, a model of a theory,completeness of a theory, along with the concepts of elementary equivalence and isomorphism of models. Definition 2.1. We define 1. M φ for a formula φ, if and only if φ is true in the realisation of M. 2. M T for a theory T if and only if M is a model of T . 3. T ` φ if and only if every model of T is a model of φ. 4. M ≡ N if and only if M and N are elementarily equivalent. 5. M =∼ N if and only if M and N are isomorphic. 1 Definition 2.2. A theory T is called κ-categorical if it has a unique model of size κ, up to isomorphism The theorem we want to emulate is the following. Theorem 2.3 (Los-Vaught test for completeness). Suppose a theory T is κ- categorical for some infinite κ and has no finite models. Then T is complete. However, we want a test involving saturated models. Definition 2.4. Let M be an L-structure for a language L. For a subset A ⊆ M, let LA := L [ fca : a 2 Ag be the expansion of L by constant symbols corresponding to elements of A. We can expand M to an LA-structure by interpreting ca as the element a 2 A. In a slight abuse of notation, we still denote the expansion by M. Definition 2.5. An n-type of M over A is a set p(x) of formulae in LA with free variables x1; : : : ; xn such that, for every finite subset p0(x) ⊆ p(x), there n exists b 2 M with M p0(b). We call an n-type p(x) complete if, for every φ an LA formula with n free variables, either φ 2 p(x) or :φ 2 p(x). Definition 2.6. For p a complete n-type over A ⊆ M, we say the model M n realises p if there exists a 2 M such that M φ(a) for all φ 2 p. We call M κ-saturated, for any cardinal κ, if for all A ⊆ M with jAj < κ, M realises all complete types over A. If jMj = κ, we call M saturated. Finally, we recall the L¨owenheim-Skolem theorems, here compiled into one statement Theorem 2.7 (L¨owenheim-Skolem). For any infinite L-structure M and any cardinal κ ≥ jLj, there exists an L-structure N such that jNj = κ and • if κ < jMj, then N is an elementary substructure of M. • if κ > jMj, then N is an elementary extension of M. 3 Ultrafilters and Ultrapowers Definition 3.1. For a set I, an ultrafilter U over I is a subset of the power set P(I) satisfying 1. I 2 U. 2. If V; W 2 U, then V \ W 2 U. 3. If V 2 U and V ⊆ W ⊆ I, then W 2 U. 4. For any V ⊆ I, either V 2 U or I n V 2 U. 2 We call an ultrafilter principal if there exists i 2 I such that V 2 U if and only if i 2 V . Definition 3.2. Given a family of sets Ai, with i 2 I an index set, and an Q Q ultrafilter U over I, we define the ultraproduct Ai = Ai=U to be the Q U i2I quotient of the cartesian product i2I Ai by the equivalence relation faigi2I ∼ fbigi2I if and only if fi 2 I : ai = big 2 U Definition 3.3. Given an ultrafilter U over an index set I and a collection of Q models Mi for a language L, define the ultraproduct Mi to the be L-structure Q U with underlying set U Mi and realisation defined for a relation symbol R by Q 1 n U Mi 1 n Mi (a ; : : : ; a ) 2 R if and only if fi 2 I :(ai ; : : : ; ai ) 2 R g 2 U and similarly for functions and constants. In the case where there exists M such that Mi = M for every i 2 I, we call this the ultrapower of M and denote it by MjIj=U. We have the following theorem Theorem 3.4 (Los'sTheorem) . For all sentences φ of L, Y Mi φ if and only if fi 2 I : Mi φg 2 U U In the case of ultrapowers, we have M ≡ MjIj=U. Definition 3.5. We call an ultrafilter U countably incomplete if there exists a countable V ⊆ U such that \W 2V W = ;. Fact 3.6. There exist countably incomplete ultrafilters Remark 3.7. There also exist countably complete ultrafilters, on N. That is, an ultrafilter on N such that every countable intersection is non-empty. Indeed, every principal ultrafilter on N is countably complete. In the case of ultrafilters over countable sets, this is an exact criterion: countably complete ultrafilters are precisely principal ultrafilters. We will demonstrate this in the case over ultrafitlers over N. Let U be a non-principal ultrafilter. Then U cannot contain any finite subsets of N, and so the set fN n f1; : : : ; ng : n 2 Ng is a countable subset of U with empty intersection. Thus non-principal ultra- filters are countably incomplete. However, the existence of cardinals admitting non-principal countably complete ultrafilters is not provable within ZFC, so this criterion may not hold for higher cardinals. Lemma 3.8. Every countably incomplete ultraproduct over a countable language is @1-saturated. 3 Proof. We need to show that, given a language jLj ≤ @0, a cardinal κ ≥ @1 so that there exists a countably incomplete ultrafilter U over I (jIj = κ), and an Q ultraproduct M = U Mi, then M realises all complete types over any A ⊆ M with jAj < @1. Since A is countable, LA. Thus, we can take p(x), a complete n-type, and enumerate p(x) = fφi(x): i 2 Ng where φi(x) are LA formulae. Defining ^ i(x) = φi(x) j≤i we see that, byLos'stheorem, since 9x i(x) is true in M, we have that the set of Mt realising 9x i(x) must be an element of the ultrafilter, i.e. ft < @0 : Mt 9x i(x)g 2 U where we restrict constants, etc, in i(x) as necessary. Here, we have technically pulled the wool over the reader's eyes, as we have been identifying our models over L with their expansions to models over LA. Fortunately for us, Theorem 3.9 allows us to get away with this, performing the following argument on the expansions, then restricting to our original language. Now , as U is countably incomplete, we can construct a descending chain I = I0 ⊃ I1 ⊃ · · · 1 with each In 2 U, but \n = 0 In = ;. Now define X0 = I0, and for all n ≥ 0, define Xn = In \ ft < @0 : Mt 9x n(x)g Each Xn 2 U, and there form a descending chain with empty intersection. Now, for each i 2 I,where exists ni, the greatest integer for which i 2 Xni . Define a sequence fligi2I by the following rules If ni = 0, then li can be any element of Mi. Otherwise, choose li in the projection of A onto Mi so that Mi ni (li). Thus, for any n > 0, and i 2 Xn, we have n ≤ ni, so Mi φn(li). We then applyLos's Theorem to conclude M φn(l) for all n > 0, and hence, l realises p(x) in M, proving the result. Theorem 3.9. Given a language L, and an expansion L0 ⊃ L, let I be a non-empty set, U an ultrafilter over I, so that, for each i 2 I, we have an L- 0 0 Q 0 structure Mi and an elementary extension Mi to an L -structure. Then U Mi Q 0 is an elementary extension of U Mi to an L -structure. Theorem 3.10. Given elementarily equivalent saturated models M; N of the same cardinality, we must have M =∼ N A full proof of this statement can be found in Chang and Keisler's Model Theory, however we will only sketch the main idea, and contrast to the countable case. We first require two lemmas, both proven by transfinite induction. 4 Definition 3.11. For two sets, X, Y , denote by X Y the set of functions f : X ! Y . Definition 3.12. For a cardinal α, denote by α+ the least cardinal greater than α. Lemma 3.13. Suppose the M is α-saturated, M =∼ N and b 2 αN.
Recommended publications
  • Notices of the American Mathematical Society
    OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY ISSU! NO. 116 OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Edited by Everett Pitcher and Gordon L. Walker CONTENTS MEETINGS Calendar of Meetings ••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••.• 874 Program of the Meeting in Cambridge, Massachusetts •••.•.••••..•• 875 Abstracts for the Meeting- Pages 947-953 PRELIMINARY ANNOUNCEMENTS OF MEETINGS •••••••••••••••••.•• 878 AN APPEAL FOR PRESERVATION OF ARCHIVAL MATERIALS .•••••••••• 888 CAN MATHEMATICS BE SAVED? ••••••••••.••••••••..•.•••••••.. 89 0 DOCTORATES CONFERRED IN 1968-1969 ••••••••••••••.••••••.•••• 895 VISITING MATHEMATICIANS .•••••••••••••••••••••••••..•••••.. 925 ANNUAL SALARY SURVEY ••••••••••••.••••.••••.•.•.••••••.•• 933 PERSONAL ITEMS •••••••••••••••••••••••••••••...•••••••••• 936 MEMORANDA TO MEMBERS Audio Recordings of Mathematical Lectures ••••••••..•••••.•••.• 940 Travel Grants. International Congress of Mathematicians ••..•.•••••.• 940 Symposia Information Center ••••.•• o o • o ••••• o o •••• 0 •••••••• 940 Colloquium Lectures •••••••••••••••••••••••.• 0 ••••••••••• 941 Mathematical Sciences E'mployment Register .•.••••••..•. o • o ••••• 941 Retired Mathematicians ••••• 0 •••••••• 0 ••••••••••••••••• 0 •• 942 MOS Reprints .•••••• o •• o ••••••••••••••••••••••• o •••••• 942 NEWS ITEMS AND ANNOUNCEMENTS •••••. o •••••••••••••••• 877, 932, 943 ABSTRACTS PRESENTED TO THE SOCIETY •••••.••••.•.•.••..•..•• 947 RESERVATION FORM. o •••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••••• 1000 MEETINGS Calendar of Meetings NOTE: This Calendar lists all of the meetings which have
    [Show full text]
  • Product of Invariant Types Modulo Domination–Equivalence
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by White Rose Research Online Archive for Mathematical Logic https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-019-00676-9 Mathematical Logic Product of invariant types modulo domination–equivalence Rosario Mennuni1 Received: 31 October 2018 / Accepted: 19 April 2019 © The Author(s) 2019 Abstract We investigate the interaction between the product of invariant types and domination– equivalence. We present a theory where the latter is not a congruence with respect to the former, provide sufficient conditions for it to be, and study the resulting quotient when it is. Keywords Domination · Domination–equivalence · Equidominance · Product of invariant types Mathematics Subject Classification 03C45 To a sufficiently saturated model of a first-order theory one can associate a semigroup, that of global invariant types with the tensor product ⊗. This can be endowed with two equivalence relations, called domination–equivalence and equidominance.This paper studies the resulting quotients, starting from sufficient conditions for ⊗ to be well-defined on them. We show, correcting a remark in [3], that this need not be always the case. Let S(U) be the space of types in any finite number of variables over a model U of a first-order theory that is κ-saturated and κ-strongly homogeneous for some large κ. For any set A ⊆ U, one has a natural action on S(U) by the group Aut(U/A) of automorphisms of U that fix A pointwise. The space Sinv(U) of global invariant types consists of those elements of S(U) which, for some small A, are fixed points of the action Aut(U/A) S(U).
    [Show full text]
  • Stable Theories
    Sh:1 STABLE THEORIES BY S. SHELAH* ABSTRACT We study Kr(~,) = sup {I S(A)] : ]A[ < ~,) and extend some results for totally transcendental theroies to the case of stable theories. We then inves- tigate categoricity of elementary and pseudo-elementary classes. 0. Introduction In this article we shall generalize Morley's theorems in [2] to more general languages. In Section 1 we define our notations. In Theorems 2.1, 2.2. we in essence prove the following theorem: every first- order theory T of arbitrary infinite cardinality satisfies one of the possibilities: 1) for all Z, I A] -- z ~ I S(A)[ -<__z + 2 ITI, (where S(A) is the set of complete consistent types over a subset A of a model of T). 2) for all •, I AI--x I S(A I =<x ~T~, and there exists A such that I AI--z, IS(A) I _>- z "o. 3) for all Z there exists A, such that [A[ = Z, IS(A)] > IAI. Theories which satisfy 1 or 2 are called stable and are similar in some respects to totally transcendental theories. In the rest of Section 2 we define a generalization of Morley's rank of transcendence, and prove some theorems about it. Theorems whose proofs are similar to the proofs of the analogous theorems in Morley [2], are not proven here, and instead the number of the analogous theorem in Morley [2] is mentioned. In Section 3, theorems about the existence of sets of indiscernibles and prime models on sets are proved. * This paper is a part of the author's doctoral dissertation written at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, under the kind guidance of Profeossr M.
    [Show full text]
  • Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics
    Found Sci DOI 10.1007/s10699-012-9316-5 Tools, Objects, and Chimeras: Connes on the Role of Hyperreals in Mathematics Vladimir Kanovei · Mikhail G. Katz · Thomas Mormann © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012 Abstract We examine some of Connes’ criticisms of Robinson’s infinitesimals starting in 1995. Connes sought to exploit the Solovay model S as ammunition against non-standard analysis, but the model tends to boomerang, undercutting Connes’ own earlier work in func- tional analysis. Connes described the hyperreals as both a “virtual theory” and a “chimera”, yet acknowledged that his argument relies on the transfer principle. We analyze Connes’ “dart-throwing” thought experiment, but reach an opposite conclusion. In S, all definable sets of reals are Lebesgue measurable, suggesting that Connes views a theory as being “vir- tual” if it is not definable in a suitable model of ZFC. If so, Connes’ claim that a theory of the hyperreals is “virtual” is refuted by the existence of a definable model of the hyperreal field due to Kanovei and Shelah. Free ultrafilters aren’t definable, yet Connes exploited such ultrafilters both in his own earlier work on the classification of factors in the 1970s and 80s, and in Noncommutative Geometry, raising the question whether the latter may not be vulnera- ble to Connes’ criticism of virtuality. We analyze the philosophical underpinnings of Connes’ argument based on Gödel’s incompleteness theorem, and detect an apparent circularity in Connes’ logic. We document the reliance on non-constructive foundational material, and specifically on the Dixmier trace − (featured on the front cover of Connes’ magnum opus) V.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Similarity in the Foundations
    Self-similarity in the Foundations Paul K. Gorbow Thesis submitted for the degree of Ph.D. in Logic, defended on June 14, 2018. Supervisors: Ali Enayat (primary) Peter LeFanu Lumsdaine (secondary) Zachiri McKenzie (secondary) University of Gothenburg Department of Philosophy, Linguistics, and Theory of Science Box 200, 405 30 GOTEBORG,¨ Sweden arXiv:1806.11310v1 [math.LO] 29 Jun 2018 2 Contents 1 Introduction 5 1.1 Introductiontoageneralaudience . ..... 5 1.2 Introduction for logicians . .. 7 2 Tour of the theories considered 11 2.1 PowerKripke-Plateksettheory . .... 11 2.2 Stratifiedsettheory ................................ .. 13 2.3 Categorical semantics and algebraic set theory . ....... 17 3 Motivation 19 3.1 Motivation behind research on embeddings between models of set theory. 19 3.2 Motivation behind stratified algebraic set theory . ...... 20 4 Logic, set theory and non-standard models 23 4.1 Basiclogicandmodeltheory ............................ 23 4.2 Ordertheoryandcategorytheory. ...... 26 4.3 PowerKripke-Plateksettheory . .... 28 4.4 First-order logic and partial satisfaction relations internal to KPP ........ 32 4.5 Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory and G¨odel-Bernays class theory............ 36 4.6 Non-standardmodelsofsettheory . ..... 38 5 Embeddings between models of set theory 47 5.1 Iterated ultrapowers with special self-embeddings . ......... 47 5.2 Embeddingsbetweenmodelsofsettheory . ..... 57 5.3 Characterizations.................................. .. 66 6 Stratified set theory and categorical semantics 73 6.1 Stratifiedsettheoryandclasstheory . ...... 73 6.2 Categoricalsemantics ............................... .. 77 7 Stratified algebraic set theory 85 7.1 Stratifiedcategoriesofclasses . ..... 85 7.2 Interpretation of the Set-theories in the Cat-theories ................ 90 7.3 ThesubtoposofstronglyCantorianobjects . ....... 99 8 Where to go from here? 103 8.1 Category theoretic approach to embeddings between models of settheory .
    [Show full text]
  • More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous Information, Loosely Organized
    More Model Theory Notes Miscellaneous information, loosely organized. 1. Kinds of Models A countable homogeneous model M is one such that, for any partial elementary map f : A ! M with A ⊆ M finite, and any a 2 M, f extends to a partial elementary map A [ fag ! M. As a consequence, any partial elementary map to M is extendible to an automorphism of M. Atomic models (see below) are homogeneous. A prime model of T is one that elementarily embeds into every other model of T of the same cardinality. Any theory with fewer than continuum-many types has a prime model, and if a theory has a prime model, it is unique up to isomorphism. Prime models are homogeneous. On the other end, a model is universal if every other model of its size elementarily embeds into it. Recall a type is a set of formulas with the same tuple of free variables; generally to be called a type we require consistency. The type of an element or tuple from a model is all the formulas it satisfies. One might think of the type of an element as a sort of identity card for automorphisms: automorphisms of a model preserve types. A complete type is the analogue of a complete theory, one where every formula of the appropriate free variables or its negation appears. Types of elements and tuples are always complete. A type is principal if there is one formula in the type that implies all the rest; principal complete types are often called isolated. A trivial example of an isolated type is that generated by the formula x = c where c is any constant in the language, or x = t(¯c) where t is any composition of appropriate-arity functions andc ¯ is a tuple of constants.
    [Show full text]
  • Saturated Models in Institutions
    Archives for Mathematical Logic manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Saturated models in institutions Razvan˘ Diaconescu · Marius Petria the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Keywords Saturated models · institutions · institution-independent model theory Abstract Saturated models constitute one of the powerful methods of conventional model theory, with many applications. Here we develop a categorical abstract model theoretic approach to satu- rated models within the theory of institutions. The most important consequence is that the method of saturated models becomes thus available to a multitude of logical systems from logic or from computing science. In this paper we define the concept of saturated model at an abstract institution-independent level and develop the fundamental existence and uniqueness theorems. As an application we prove a general institution-independent version of the Keisler-Shelah isomorphism theorem “any two ele- mentarily equivalent models have isomorphic ultrapowers” (assuming Generalized Continuum Hy- pothesis). 1 Introduction 1.1 Institution-independent Model Theory The theory of “institutions” [21] is a categorical abstract model theory which formalizes the intuitive notion of logical system, including syntax, semantics, and the satisfaction between them. It provides the most complete form of abstract model theory, the only one including signature morphisms, model reducts, and even mappings (morphisms) between logics as primary concepts. Institution have been recently also extended towards proof theory [36,15] in the spirit of categorical logic [28]. The concept of institution arose within computing science (algebraic specification) in response to the population explosion among logics in use there, with the ambition of doing as much as possi- ble at a level of abstraction independent of commitment to any particular logic [21,38,19].
    [Show full text]
  • Saturated Models in Mathematical Fuzzy Logic*
    Saturated Models in Mathematical Fuzzy Logic* Guillermo Badia Carles Noguera Department of Knowledge-Based Mathematical Systems Institute of Information Theory and Automation Johannes Kepler University Linz Czech Academy of Sciences Linz, Austria Prague, Czech Republic [email protected] [email protected] Abstract—This paper considers the problem of building satu- Another important item in the classical agenda is that of rated models for first-order graded logics. We define types as saturated models, that is, the construction of structures rich in pairs of sets of formulas in one free variable which express elements satisfying many expressible properties. In continuous properties that an element is expected, respectively, to satisfy and to falsify. We show, by means of an elementary chains model theory the construction of such models is well known construction, that each model can be elementarily extended to a (cf. [1]). However, the problem has not yet been addressed in saturated model where as many types as possible are realized. mathematical fuzzy logic, but only formulated in [15], where In order to prove this theorem we obtain, as by-products, some Dellunde suggested that saturated models of fuzzy logics could results on tableaux (understood as pairs of sets of formulas) and be built as an application of ultraproduct constructions. This their consistency and satisfiability, and a generalization of the Tarski–Vaught theorem on unions of elementary chains. idea followed the classical tradition found in [5]. However, Index Terms—mathematical fuzzy logic, first-order graded in other classical standard references such as [22], [24], [28] logics, uninorms, residuated lattices, logic UL, types, saturated the construction of saturated structures is obtained by other models, elementary chains methods.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rocky Romance of Model Theory and Set Theory
    The Rocky Romance of Model Theory and Set Theory John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at Chicago Eilat meeeting in memory of Mati Rubin May 6, 2018 John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at ChicagoThe Eilat Rocky meeeting Romance in memory of Model of Mati Theory Rubin and Set Theory May 6, 2018 1 / 46 Goal: Maddy In Second Philosophy Maddy writes, The Second Philosopher sees fit to adjudicate the methodological questions of mathematics – what makes for a good definition, an acceptable axiom, a dependable proof technique?– by assessing the effectiveness of the method at issue as means towards the goal of the particular stretch of mathematics involved. We discuss the choice of definitions of model theoretic concepts that reduce the set theoretic overhead: John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at ChicagoThe Eilat Rocky meeeting Romance in memory of Model of Mati Theory Rubin and Set Theory May 6, 2018 2 / 46 Entanglement Such authors as Kennedy, Magidor, Parsons, and Va¨an¨ anen¨ have spoken of the entanglement of logic and set theory. It depends on the logic There is a deep entanglement between (first-order) model theory and cardinality. There is No such entanglement between (first-order) model theory and cardinal arithmetic. At least for stable theories; more entanglement in neo-stability theory. There is however such an entanglement between infinitary model theory and cardinal arithmetic and therefore with extensions of ZFC. John T. Baldwin University of Illinois at ChicagoThe Eilat Rocky meeeting Romance in memory of Model of Mati Theory Rubin and Set Theory May 6, 2018 3 / 46 Equality as Congruence Any text in logic posits that: Equality ‘=’ is an equivalence relation: Further it satisfies the axioms schemes which define what universal algebraists call a congruence.
    [Show full text]
  • Model Theory of Fields and Heights Haydar Göral
    Model Theory of Fields and Heights Haydar Göral To cite this version: Haydar Göral. Model Theory of Fields and Heights. General Mathematics [math.GM]. Université Claude Bernard - Lyon I, 2015. English. NNT : 2015LYO10087. tel-01184906v3 HAL Id: tel-01184906 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-01184906v3 Submitted on 13 Nov 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Universit´e Claude Bernard Lyon 1 Ecole´ doctorale InfoMath, ED 512 Sp´ecialit´e:Math´ematiques N. d’ordre 87-2015 Model Theory of Fields and Heights La Th´eorie des Mod`eles des Corps et des Hauteurs Th`ese de doctorat Soutenue publiquement le 3 Juillet 2015 par Haydar G¨oral devant le Jury compos´ede: Mme Fran¸coise DELON CNRS Institut de Math´ematiques de Jussieu, Paris Rapporteuse M. Ayhan GUNAYDIN¨ Universit´e des Beaux-Arts Mimar-Sinan, Istanbul Examinateur M. Piotr KOWALSKI Universit´edeWroclaw, Pologne Rapporteur M. Amador MARTIN-PIZARRO CNRS, Institut Camille Jordan, Villeurbanne Directeur de th`ese M. Frank WAGNER Universit´e Claude Bernard Lyon 1 Directeur de th`ese Model Theory of Fields and Heights La Th´eorie des Mod`eles des Corps et des Hauteurs 3 Juillet 2015 Haydar G¨oral Th`ese de doctorat Model Theory of Fields and Heights Abstract : In this thesis, we deal with the model theory of algebraically closed fields expanded by predicates to denote either elements of small height or multiplicative subgroups satisfying a diophantine condition.
    [Show full text]
  • Saturation and Simple Extensions of Models of Peano Arithmetic
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 27 (1984) 109-136 109 North-Holland SATURATION AND SIMPLE EXTENSIONS OF MODELS OF PEANO ARITHMETIC Matt KAUFMANN University of Connecticut, Storm, CT 06268 and Purdue University, West Lafayette, IN 47907, USA James H. SCHMERL” University of Connecticut, Storrs, CT 06268, USA Recursive saturation has come to play an important part in the model theory of Peano Arithmetic (PA). One of the neater results is the theorem of Smoryfiski and Stavi [16] that recursive saturation is preserved by cofinal extensions. (We give a quite simple proof of this in Corollary 1.3(i).) It is natural to inquire about a converse to this theorem, but the answer comes too quickly: A model of PA has a recursively saturated, cofinal extension iff it is tall. The Smoryfiski-Stavi theorem loses nothing if the cofinal extensions are re- quired to be simple. Besides, simple cofinal extensions arise quite naturally here because of Kotlarski’s observation (Corollary 1.3(iii)) that the Smoryfiski-Stavi theorem implies that o,-saturation is preserved by simple, cofinal extensions. Notice also that a simple elementary extension must be cofinal in order to be recursively saturated (Proposition 1.6). It is thus we are led to the following two questions: (1) Does some tall model of PA that is not recursively saturated have a recursively saturated simple extension? (2) Does every tall model of PA have a recursively saturated simple extension? We will show in this paper that (1) has a positive answer whereas (2) is answered negatively. Moreover, we characterize among countable models of PA those which do have recursively saturated simple extensions: they are precisely the lofty models.
    [Show full text]
  • Constructing Regular Ultrafilters from a Model-Theoretic Point of View
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 367, Number 11, November 2015, Pages 8139–8173 S 0002-9947(2015)06303-X Article electronically published on February 18, 2015 CONSTRUCTING REGULAR ULTRAFILTERS FROM A MODEL-THEORETIC POINT OF VIEW M. MALLIARIS AND S. SHELAH Abstract. This paper contributes to the set-theoretic side of understanding Keisler’s order. We consider properties of ultrafilters which affect saturation of unstable theories: the lower cofinality lcf(ℵ0, D)ofℵ0 modulo D, saturation of the minimum unstable theory (the random graph), flexibility, goodness, goodness for equality, and realization of symmetric cuts. We work in ZFC except when noted, as several constructions appeal to complete ultrafilters and thus assume a measurable cardinal. The main results are as follows. First, we investigate the strength of flexibility, known to be detected by non-low theories. Assuming κ>ℵ0 is measurable, we construct a regular ultrafilter on κ λ ≥ 2 which is flexible but not good, and which moreover has large lcf(ℵ0) but does not even saturate models of the random graph. This implies (a) that flexibility alone cannot characterize saturation of any theory, however (b) by separating flexibility from goodness, we remove a main obstacle to proving non-low does not imply maximal. Since flexible is precisely OK, this also shows that (c) from a set-theoretic point of view, consistently, OK need not imply good, addressing a problem from Dow (1985). Second, under no additional assumptions, we prove that there is a loss of saturation in regular ultrapowers of unstable theories, and also give a new proof that there is a loss of saturation in ultrapowers of non-simple theories.
    [Show full text]