Skepticism, Metaphors and Vertigo : Wittgenstein and Cavell on The

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Skepticism, Metaphors and Vertigo : Wittgenstein and Cavell on The RicoGutschmidt, Dresden Skepticism, Metaphorsand Vertigo Wittgenstein and Cavell on the Human Condition Abstract: The relation of Wittgenstein’slaterphilosophytoskepticism seems to be ambiguous, since he rejects radical skepticism but also highlights the ground- lessness of our beliefs. In this paper,Iam going to discuss Wittgenstein’shinge propositions in this respect.Against the usual view,Iwill show that they do not function as acontextualist or foundationalist refutation of skepticism. Whatis more, they also do not confirm skepticism. In contrast,Iwill arguethat following Wittgenstein skepticism is neither false nor true, but still has apoint,which can be elucidated with Stanley Cavell’sconcept of a truth of skepticism. This concept roughly states that we can not know about the existenceofthe world and the others, but that we have to acknowledge them. With the help of Wittgenstein, Iamgoingtoclarify this position. The key idea is that the problem of skepticism can be understood as ametaphorical wayofpresentingthe finiteness of the human condition and thatvertiginous skeptical irritations lead to an adequate human self-understanding in this respect. Something is obscure with the statusofskepticism. What does it mean for the human to be confronted with unanswerable questions?Should he somehow deal with his incapability of answeringthem?Shouldn’thenonetheless try to find answers?Orare these questions senseless in the end, since they can not be answered anyhow?Inthe following,Iamgoing to discuss this obscure status of skepticism. In the first part of this paper,Iwill the deal with the ambiguous position of Wittgenstein’slater philosophytothe problem of skepticism, which seems neither to reject nor to confirm skepticism. This problem willbeelucidated by referringtoWittgenstein’sconcept of the hinge propositions. In the second part,Iam goingtoclarify the ambiguous role of these propositions. Forthis pur- pose, Iwill show that skepticism can be understood as ametaphorical wayof presentingthe finiteness of the human condition. This will be explicated with the help of Thomas Nagel’smetaphor of the view from nowhereand with John McDowell’sconcept of the sideways-onview.Furthermore, Stanley Cavell’s concept of atruth of skepticism will be discussed in this respect.Finally, refer- ring to Cavell, McDowell comments on afeelingofvertigointhe face of the groundless human situation. This givesrise to my overall claim thatvertiginous skeptical irritations lead to an adequate human self-understanding in the light of the finiteness of the human condition. Konstanzer Online-Publikations-System (KOPS) URL: http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:bsz:352-2-1qrjs8h7eqkdb1 132 Skepticism, Metaphorsand Vertigo 1. The HingePropositionsinOn Certainty Forastart,Iam going to discuss the ambiguous position of Wittgenstein’slater philosophytothe problem of skepticism. On the one hand, Wittgenstein rejects radical skepticism: “Adoubtthat doubted everything would not be adoubt” and “Adoubt withoutanend is not even adoubt.” (OC1969: 450and 625) On the other hand, it is Wittgenstein’soverall concern to highlight the groundlessness of our beliefs: “The difficulty is to realize the groundlessness of our believing” and “At the foundationofwell-founded belief lies belief that is not founded.” (OC1969: 166 and 253) On the one hand,herefers to the self-defeating character of skepticism, on the other hand, he uses the argument of the infinite regress to show that our beliefs are unwarranted in the end. Therefore, Wittgenstein has apeculiarposition between the traditionalat- tempts to refuse skepticism and the confession thatthe problem of skepticism can not be solved. Instead of refusing skepticism as senseless in the line of the pragmatic tradition,¹ Wittgenstein’sposition seems to includeboth, the re- fusal as well as the confirmation of skepticism. Against that, in epistemology Wittgenstein is typicallyconsidered to be anti-skeptical,² whereas for example Kripke discusses Wittgenstein’sskepticism with regardtomeaning³ and Fogelin relates Wittgenstein to Pyrrhonism.⁴ Apossibility to embrace both aspectsin Wittgenstein’sphilosophycan be found in the work of Stanley Cavell, who speaksabout a truth of skepticism and introduces the concept of acknowledgment in this context.This interpretation represents aposition between skepticism and anti-skepticism and hence promises to captureWittgenstein’sambiguous posi- tion more adequately.⁵ Cavell mainlydeals with the Philosophical Investigations,whereas in the fol- lowing Wittgenstein’srelation to skepticism will be considered with the help of his later work On Certainty. The position between skepticism and anti-skepticism can be explicated here with the concept of the notorious hingepropositions. These propositions can not be doubtedand are substantiating every thinking and questioning,but are themselveswithout reason. They do not have afounda- tion and can even changeovertime. Because of this double-edgedcharacter,the Cf. e.g. the positions of Peirceand James,cf. also McGinn . Forexample in non-epistemic, contextualistic or neomoorean approaches,cf. e.g. Pritchard . Kripke . Fogelin and . Cavell . Skepticism, Metaphors and Vertigo 133 consideration of the statusofthese propositions will shed some light on Wittgen- stein’srelation to skepticism between refusal and confirmation. Wittgenstein’sengagement with skepticism was motivated by his reading of the papers of George EdwardMoore about the DefenceofCommon Sense and the Proof of the External World. Moore’sapproach of refuting skepticism starts with propositions, which can not be doubtedinMoore’sopinion,for example “Hereis one hand,and here is another” or “Ihavealways been on or nearthe surface of the earth.” Wittgenstein alsorefers to these propositions.But while he like Moore argues that they can not be doubted, he claims at the same time that they are groundless and fallible. This peculiardouble-edgedcharacter shall now be in- vestigated more closely. Wittgenstein’sbest known metaphor for the status of the Moorean proposi- tions is that of the hinge, which he uses threetimes in On Certainty: That is to say, the question that we raise and our doubts depend on the fact that some prop- ositions areexempt from doubt,are as it were likehinges on which those turn. That is to say, it belongs to the logic of our scientific investigations that certain things are in deed not doubted. But it isn’tthat the situation is like this: We just can’t investigateeverything, and for that reason we are forced to rest content with assumption.IfIwant the door to turn, the hingesmust stayput.(OC 1969: 341–343) The mathematical proposition has,asitwere officially, been giventhe stamp of incon- testability.I.e.: “Disputeabout other things; this is immovable – it is ahinge on which your disputecan turn.” (OC1969: 655) Other importantnotions for the same concept are picture of the world, mythol- ogy, rules of agame and riverbed, which alsoshall be cited here: But Idid not getmypictureofthe world by satisfyingmyself of its correctness;nor do I have it because Iamsatisfied of its correctness.No: it is the inherited background against which Idistinguish between true and false. The propositions describingthis world-picture might be part of akind of mythology. And their roleislike that of rules of agame; and the gamecan be learned purelypracti- cally, without learningany explicit rules. It might be imagined that some propositions,ofthe form of empiricalpropositions, werehardened and functioned as channelsfor such empirical propositions as were not hardened but fluid; and that this relation altered with time, in that fluid propositions hard- ened, and hard ones became fluid. The mythology maychange back into astate of flux, the river-bed of thoughts may shift.But Idistinguish between the movement of the waters on the river-bed and the shift of the bed itself; though thereisnot asharp division of the one from the other.(OC 1969: 94–97) 134 Skepticism, Metaphorsand Vertigo Wittgenstein givesawide rangeofdifferent examples of hingepropositions.He refers to the above-quoted Moorean propositions as wellastosuch diverse state- ments as the declaration of one’sown name,the statement that no one has ever been on the moon (this was aplausible assumption twodecades before the first moon landing), or that you’re not dreamingatthe moment (OC1969: 628, 286 and 676).⁶ What is more, the hingepropositions are not isolated from each other,but form anestofpropositions (OC1969: 225). More exactly, they consti- tute aframe of referenceand give one another mutual support (OC1969: 83 and 142).⁷ Moreover,all importantcharacteristics of the hinge propositions can be ex- plicated with the passages cited so far.Itisnot Wittgenstein’spoint thatitisim- possibletoput certain beliefs into question, but thatsome beliefs “belong to the logic of our scientific investigations”.Inthe implementation of ascientific ex- periment,for example, the existence of the apparatus is not taken for granted due to abare assumption. In contrast,Wittgenstein further explicates that it is part of the experiment to belief in the existenceofthe apparatus, since otherwise it would not be an experiment(OC 1969: 337). This is alsotrue for every judg- ment,since following Wittgenstein every judgment presupposes something which is not doubted – otherwise it would not be ajudgment (OC1969: 150 and 232). It simply belongs to the structure of our knowledge that our conclusions relyonhinges or moveinariverbed. In Wittgenstein’sdescription of the struc- ture
Recommended publications
  • Lexington Books
    NEW FROM LEXINGTON BOOKS WHITEHEAD AND THE PITTSBURGH SCHOOL: PREEMPTING THE PROBLEM OF INTENTIONALITY By Lisa Landoe Hedrick “Whitehead and the Pittsburgh School: Preempting the Problem of Intentionality is an excellent addition to studies on the relationship between Whitehead and analytic philosophy in general. In particular, it shows how Whitehead’s critique of early trends in analytic thought is relevant to habits that impede progress in analytic thought today.”—Daniel A. Dombrowski, Seattle University “Hedrick makes good on her stated aim: to interpret Whitehead’s epistemology in a new way and to make her own original contribution. This is explosive philosophy!”—Robert Cummings Neville, Boston University “Hedrick is destined to become a leading author on the interpretation of the thought of Whitehead. In this extraordinary debut book, she examines Whitehead’s relevance to recent developments in analytic philosophy epitomized in the ‘Pittsburgh School’ of Robert Brandom and John McDowell and contextualized against the philosophy of Donald Davidson and Richard Rorty. Not since the pioneering work of the late George W. Shields has a Whitehead scholar tackled the critical relation of Whitehead to analytic philosophy. Hedrick does it here in a thoroughly up-to-date and decisive way with a brilliant focus on the meaning of intentionality and the need to make sense of the relationship between mind and world.” —Nancy Frankenberry, Dartmouth College “With a technically precise focus on contemporary epistemology and the problems of normativity and intentionality, Hedrick demonstrates that the TABLE OF CONTENTS sustained critique of prevailing habits of thought within mainstream analytic Acknowledgments philosophy implicitly shares much in common with a similar but long- Introduction forgotten critique of Bertrand Russell’s sensedata theory, launched a century Chapter 1: Reading Plato, Aristotle, and Kant ago by Russell’s erstwhile collaborator, Whitehead.
    [Show full text]
  • Reason and Nature Lecture and Colloquium in Munster¨ 1999
    JOHN MCDOWELL: Reason and Nature Lecture and Colloquium in Munster¨ 1999 Edited by Marcus Willaschek LIT – Verlag Munster¨ Preface John McDowell is one of the most influential philosophers writing to- day. His work, ranging widely from interpretations of Plato and Aris- totle to Davidsonian semantics, from ethics to epistemology and the philosophy of mind, has set the agenda for many recent philosophical debates. In recent years, McDowell’s views have been hotly discussed among students and faculty in Munster,¨ too. Therefore, we were very glad when McDowell agreed to give the third M¨unsteraner Vorlesungen zur Philosophie in 1999. On May 5, McDowell gave a public lecture; on the following two days, he participated in a colloquium where students and faculty from Munster¨ presented brief papers on his philosophy. McDowell listened carefully and responded to questions and criticisms. This volume contains McDowell’s lecture, revised versions of the col- loquium papers and McDowell’s written responses to them. I should like to thank John McDowell for coming to lecture in Munster,¨ for participating in the colloquium, and for putting his re- sponses in writing. Discussing his views with him has been stimulation and pleasure for all of us. Next, I want to thank the participants in the colloquium who worked hard to come up with interesting and chal- lenging presentations. Further, thanks are due to Karsten Wantia and Florian Wessels for putting much effort and time in type-setting and designing this volume. And finally, I want ot thank the Ministerium fur¨ Schule und Weiterbildung, Wissenschaft und Forschung in Nordrhein- Westfalen for funding the 1999 M¨unsteraner Vorlesungen zur Philosophie.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Disjunctive Conception of Experience As Material for A
    The disjunctive conception of experience as material for a transcendental argument John McDowell University of Pittsburgh 1. In Individuals1 and The Bounds of Sense,2 P. F. Strawson envisaged transcendental arguments as responses to certain sorts of scepticism. An argument of the sort Strawson proposed was to establish a general claim about the world, a claim supposedly brought into doubt by sceptical reflections. Such an argument was to work by showing that unless things were as they were said to be in the claim that the argument purported to establish, it would not be possible for our thought or experience to have certain characteristics, not regarded as questionable even by someone who urges sceptical doubts. So the argument’s conclusion was to be displayed as the answer to a “How possible?” question. That has a Kantian ring, and the feature of such arguments that the formulation fits is the warrant for calling them “transcendental”. Barry Stroud responded to Strawson on the following lines.3 Perhaps we can see our way to supposing that if our thought or experience is to have certain characteristics it does have (for instance that experience purports to be of a world of objects independent of us), we must conceive the world in certain ways (for instance as containing objects that continue to exist even while we are not perceiving them). But it is quite another matter to suggest that by reflecting about how it is possible that our thought and experience are as they are, we could establish conclusions not just about how we must conceive the world but about how the world must be.
    [Show full text]
  • An Unrealistic Account of Moral Reasons
    An Unrealistic Account of Moral Reasons PRINCIPIA LXVI (2019): 5–33 PL‑ISSN 0867‑5392 DOI 10.4467/20843887PI.19.001.11634 Susana Cadilha An Unrealistic Account of Moral Reasons1 Nierealistyczne ujęcie racji moralnych Summary In this paper I will analyze John McDowell’s broad account of prac‑ tical rationality and moral reasons, which he displays mainly in his articles “Are Moral Requirements Hypothetical Imperatives?” (1978) and “Might There Be External Reasons?” (1995). My main aim is to argue that from a philosophical perspective, no less than from an empirical one, McDowell’s account of practical rationality is not a realistic one. From a philosophical point of view, I will argue that his intellectualist account is not convincing; and if we consider his virtue‑ethical ideal of practical rationality in light of the model of human cognition, we also realize that moral behavior is not immune to cognitive biases and does not always flow from robust traits of character like virtues. At the same time, this puts at stake his strong thesis of moral autonomy – the idea that with the ‘onset of reason’ moral beings are no longer determined by ‘first nature’ features. Keywords: John McDowell, practical rationality, moral reasons, vir‑ tue ethics, second nature Streszczenie W niniejszym artykule analizuję szerokie ujęcie praktycznej racjo‑ nalności i racji moralnych Johna McDowella, które przedstawia głównie w swoich artykułach „Are Moral Requirements Hypotheti‑ cal Imperatives?” (1978) i „Might There Be External Reasons?” (1995). Moim głównym celem jest pokazanie, że z perspektywy fi‑ 1 This paper is a substantially extended and improved version of my previous paper “John McDowell on Practical Rationality – Is He (Really) Talking about Us?” (2018).
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge and the Space of Reasons: the Ideas of John Mcdowell and Paul Hirst Geoffrey Hinchliffe University of East Anglia
    Geoffrey Hinchliffe 107 Knowledge and the Space of Reasons: The Ideas of John McDowell and Paul Hirst Geoffrey Hinchliffe University of East Anglia In this essay I develop an epistemological perspective that argues for the cen- tral role that knowledge plays in education. I do this first of all by elaborating John McDowell’s ideas on the “space of reasons.”1 I then use this concept to reinterpret and develop the concept of the “forms of knowledge” associated with Paul Hirst.2 I argue that the forms of knowledge can be seen as inhabiting the space of reasons. I then show how one of the key features of the space of reasons — the making of judgments — is also a key feature of education and learning. SECOND NATURE AND THE SPACE OF REASONS I will begin by giving a brief account of McDowell’s epistemological position. His exposition is wide-ranging but the force of his argument is lost unless its different strands are held together. His starting point is Immanuel Kant’s well-known remark that “thoughts without content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind,”3 which McDowell thinks underpins what he sees as a pernicious, oscillating dualism. On the one side is, borrowing from Wilfred Sellars, the “Myth of the Given,” and on the other side is a coherentism that McDowell attributes to Donald Davidson.4 The problem with relying on the “given” is that it is not clear how the relation between sense experience and concept can be considered as one of genuine justification since unalloyed, bare sense data is simply “other” to conceptual thought.
    [Show full text]
  • The Pragmatic Century
    The Pragmatic Century Richard J. Bernstein There are many ways of telling the story of the vicissitudes of pragmatism in the United States. I want to begin with a brief account of what may be considered the standard story, because I intend to challenge it. The stan- dard story goes something like this. Pragmatism was popularized primar- ily through the lecturing and writing of William James at the beginning of the twentieth century. We can even date the explicit introduction of the term “pragmatism” by James in his 1898 address, delivered at the Univer- sity of California, Berkeley, “Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results.” In that address, James generously acknowledged his debt to Peirce, “one of the most original contemporary thinkers,” and he refers to “the principle of practicalism—or pragmatism as he called it, when I first heard him enunciate it at Cambridge in the early 1970s.” James initially gives a rather metaphorical description of “Peirce’s principle”: “the soul and meaning of thought, he says, can never be made to direct itself towards anything but the production of belief, belief being the demica- dence which closes a musical phrase in the symphony of our intellectual life.” Furthermore, “beliefs, in short are really rules of action; and the whole function of thinking is but one step in the production of habits of action” (James 1967: 348). In 1898, Peirce was barely known as a philoso- pher (except to a small group of admirers like James). As James’s popular version of pragmatism spread, Peirce was so appalled and outraged that he renamed his own doctrine of meaning “‘pragmaticism,’ which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers” (Peirce 1931: 5.414).
    [Show full text]
  • Dewey, Continuity, and Mcdowell
    Dewey, Continuity, and McDowell Peter Godfrey-Smith Philosophy Department Harvard University Keynote address at the Harvard/MIT Graduate Philosophy Conference, March 2006. To appear (with minor changes) in Normativity and Nature, edited by David MacArthur and Mario de Caro, Columbia University Press. 1. Introduction 2. Dewey on Mind and Nature 3. Criticism of Mind and World 4. Aboutness and Ideals 1. Introduction John Dewey's voluminous output includes substantial work in metaphysics, epistemology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of science. Within analytic philosophy, the implicit conclusion drawn for some decades now has been that Dewey is not especially relevant or useful in these areas. He is seen, I suspect, as well-meaning but woolly-minded, and as just not grappling effectively with the issues that are most alive to us now. I argue here for the contemporary relevance, as well as the intrinsic merit, of some of Dewey's ideas on these topics. The area I will look at is general discussions of the relation between "mind and world." Here I primarily have in mind questions about representation, belief, and knowledge, as opposed to the overtly metaphysical side of the mind/body problem. Dewey sought to assert "continuity" between mind and world. This was his response to a number of famous "dualisms" in philosophy. As the term suggests, Dewey's is a "no gulf" view of the relation between mind and world, a denial of problematic separation. But this does not mean that he refused to see a problem, and baldly asserted 1 that the mind is in straightforward contact with the world at large.
    [Show full text]
  • Rule-Following, Normativity & Objectivity
    Rule-Following, Normativity & Objectivity An Analysis of McDowell’s ‘Wittgenstein on Following a Rule’ James Alexander Cross UCL Department of Philosophy MPhil Stud Rule-Following, Normativity & Objectivity DECLARATION I, James Alexander Cross, confirm that the work presented in this thesis is my own. Where information has been derived from other sources, I confirm that this has been indicated in the thesis. 2 Rule-Following, Normativity & Objectivity ABSTRACT This essay offers a close analysis and critique of the complex theoretical arguments in John McDowell’s 1984 paper, Wittgenstein on Following a Rule, a seminal discussion of rule-following, normativity and objectivity that still stands in need of a thorough, clear analysis on its own terms. My aim is to clarify and assess the arguments McDowell makes against the views expressed by Crispin Wright in Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics and Saul Kripke in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. I also offer analysis of relevant parts of these works as necessary. All three texts juxtapose attempts to expound the views of the historical Wittgenstein with attempts to argue for them on his behalf, but the philosophical issues under debate are entirely separated from that interpretive context in my discussion as they merit analysis in their own right. For simplicity I treat the views each commentator attributes to Wittgenstein as if they were the commentator’s own. Chapter 1 outlines and analyses the basic premises, terminology and some central arguments of the debate, focusing on analysis of the idea that understanding the meaning of an expression involves a kind of contract.
    [Show full text]
  • John Mcdowell”
    ”John McDowell” - On Quietism, Nonconceptual Content, and Semantics Eirik Julius Risberg M.A. Thesis in Philosophy Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Art and Ideas The Faculty of Humanities University of Oslo Autumn 2007 Abstract In Mind and World John McDowell proposes to exorcise ‘some characteristic anxieties of modern philosophy’ that make the relation between mind and world seem problematic. According to McDowell, we are confronted by two strong but contrary intuitions when it comes to explaining the relation between mind and world. On the one hand, we are faced with a coherentism that threatens to leave the mind out of touch with the world, and on the other, we are confronted with the intuition that justification for our beliefs is simply given in experience. However, although McDowell’s book has been at the centre of philosophical discussion since its publication in 1994, there are aspects of his philosophy that seems difficult to fit together, and which, even today, poses challenges for even the most sympathetic reader. How are we to reconcile McDowell’s interesting suggestion that experience is already conceptual, thereby exorcising the apparent problem of mind’s relation to the world, with his quietism? And what is McDowell committed to with his claim that the content of our experience is conceptual? I discuss the first of these questions in essay I, whereas the second – what McDowell takes the debate on nonconceptual content to be about – is addressed in the second essay, distinguishing it from other conceptions in play in an increasingly ramified debate. However, the question that governs McDowell’s inquiry in Mind and World – how the mind is related to the world – is not a new question to McDowell, but runs like a red thread through his philosophical career.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comparison of Davidson's and Mcdowell's Accounts of Perceptual
    A Comparison of Davidson’s and McDowell’s Accounts of Perceptual Beliefs Loren Bremmers (5687691) Honours Bachelor’s Thesis Philosophy Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies Utrecht University 2016-2017 Supervisor: dr. Menno Lievers Second reader: dr. Rob van Gerwen Honours Bachelor’s Thesis by Loren Bremmers Abstract The aim of this thesis is to compare Donald Davidson’s and John McDowell’s accounts of perceptual beliefs. In Mind and World, McDowell provides an account of the justification of beliefs about the external world that is sharply contrasted with Davidson’s coherence theory. In a response to McDowell, Davidson states that he does not understand this contrast, for he believes that the differences between McDowell’s and his own account are not very noticeable. Davidson explains that in his view the disagreement seems to be centered around what is caused by perceptual experience in their accounts of perceptual beliefs. In McDowell’s account, rather than causing a belief directly, as is the case in Davidson’s account, perceptual experience causes a propositional attitude and one can decide to convert this propositional attitude into a belief. In this thesis, I want to go further still, arguing that the differences between Davidson’s and McDowell’s accounts are greater than Davidson supposes. By providing an overview of the similarities and differences of Davidson’s and McDowell’s accounts, I show that Davidson and McDowell disagree about more than merely about what is caused by perceptual experience, since both accounts require very different kinds of theories to defend their views on the justification of perceptual beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • Idealism: a Love (Of Sophia) That Dare Not Speak Its Name
    Idealism: A Love (of Sophia) that Dare not Speak its Name PAUL REDDINl;' My first experience of philosophy at the University of Sydney was as a commencing undergraduate in the tumultuous year of 1973. At the start of that year, there was one department of philosophy, but by the beginning of the next there were two. These two departments seemed to be opposed in every possible way except one: they both professed to be committed to a form of materialist philosophy. One could think that having a common enemy at least might have been the cause for some degree of unanimity, but no: the traditional enemy of materialism - idealism - was regarded as having been long dead and buried. For the Marxists in the then Department of General Philosophy, it had been Marx who, in the second half of the nineteenth century, had 'inverted' Hegelian idealism into a form of materialism, while for the analytic philosophers in the Department of Traditional and Modern Philosophy, it had been Bertrand Russell and G. E. Moore who had triumphed over British idealism at the turn of the twentieth. There may have been many things that were atypical about philosophy as it was done at Sydney in the early 1970s, but its resistance to idealism was not among them. Twenty years later, however, there were signs that old certitudes in Anglophone philosophy were changing, and in 1994, two books were published by mainstream analytic philosophers addressing issues central to analytic concern and suggesting that the philosophy of Hegel held the key to their solution. These books were Mind and World * Paul Redding holds a Personal Chair in Philosophy at the University of Sydney.
    [Show full text]
  • Possible Worlds and Moral Philosophy*
    teorema Vol. XX/3, 2001, pp. 41-50 Possible Worlds and Moral Philosophy* Benedict Smith RESUMEN El siguiente articulo es, en parte, una respuesta a la propuesta de Steffen Borges publicada en teorema, Vol. XIX/1 (2000), con el título “A Call for a Possible World Argument in Ethics”. Quisiera sugerir aquí que la relación entre mundos posibles y deliberación ética no es, de por sí, diferenciada y auxiliar. Al contrario, propongo que la contemplación de mundos posibles es una parte esencial de la teorización ética. El carácter inmediato de la ética en relación con lo posible se evidencia a través del mo- delo de deliberación moral propuesto por una cierta idea de particularismo moral y, más específicamente, en el trabajo de John McDowell, quien demuestra los aspectos inextricablemente modales de la ética en este respecto. ABSTRACT This paper is, in part, a response to Steffen Borge’s article in teorema Vol. XIX/1 (2000), “A Call for a Possible World Argument in Ethics”. I suggest that the relationship between possible worlds and ethical deliberation is not distinctive and auxiliary in nature. Rather, I argue that the contemplation of possible worlds is an es- sential part of ethical theorising. The immediate character of ethics vis-à-vis the pos- sible is evidenced by the account of moral deliberation proposed by a certain form of moral particularism. In particular, the work of John McDowell demonstrates the inex- tricably modal aspects of ethics in this regard. I This paper is, in part, a response to Steffen Borge’s “A Call for a Possi- ble World Argument in Ethics” [Borge (2000)].
    [Show full text]