<<

chapter 6 What is ?1

Katja Maria Vogt

1 Introduction

When philosophers use the term hedonism, they usually imply the pursuit of something lowly, as if the best a human being can aim for was like the life of grazing cattle.2 And yet there are philosophers who endorse hedonism. To them, it seems that hedonists must not be destined for a lowly life at all. Instead, they argue for a life of reasoning and friendship.3 Given these discrep- ancies, what then is hedonism?4 This question bears, I propose, not only on the reconstruction of ancient views that self-identify as hedonist. More generally, it bears on how we understand ancient . Compared to modern moral , the ancients are greatly—some may say, excessively—interested in and . As will emerge, I think that ancient ethics benefitted from the presence of hedonism as a contender. In response to hedonism, Plato and Aristotle seem to get something right: ethics needs to get clear about the role of pleasure and pain in human psychology, the nature of pleasure and pain, and its value. The first premise of hedonism, I propose, is that pleasure is the only good that does not derive its value from another good (section 2). This premise is justified, in ways that explicitly reject the charge of a , by an appeal to nature: because pleasure is by nature pursued, it should be pursued

1 I am grateful to William Harris for inviting me to at the conference that lead up to this publication, and to all participants for interesting comments and discussions. Giulia Bonasio, Sam McVane, and Isabel Kaeslin provided helpful feedback on a draft. Jens Haas offered invaluable feedback, both for the version that I presented at the conference and for the paper. 2 That hedonism is often understood as advocating a life like that of grazing cattle is Plato’s concluding remark in the . ‘And did not pleasure turn out to receive fifth position, according to the verdict we reached in our discussion?—Apparently.—But not first place, even if all the cattle and horses and the rest of the animals gave testimony by following plea- sure.’ (Plato, Philebus 67a11–b2) Cf. NE 1095b16–23. 3  says one should care more who one is eating and drinking with than what one eats and drinks. To ‘feed’ without a friend is the life of a lion and a wolf. (Seneca, Letters 19.10). 4 On the of reasoning as well as the role of reasoning in the pursuit of pleasure cf. Warren 2014.

© the Trustees of Columbia University in the City of New York, 2018 | doi:10.1163/9789004379503_007 94 Vogt

(section 3). Sophisticated hedonism, as I call the kind of theory formulated by Epicurus, develops ideas that Plato employs (section 4). Critics of hedonism differ in how they respond to hedonism’s first premise. Anti-hedonists, as I use this notion, endorse its opposite, namely that pleasure is bad. Non-hedonists, as I call them, reject hedonism while admitting that there are good pleasures (section 5). The well-known objection against hedonism, that there are good and bad pleasures, thus cannot count as anti-hedonist; neither hedonism nor anti-hedonism can account for both good and bad pleasures (section 6). The hardest problem for hedonism, on my account, lies elsewhere: in the variety of pleasure. Pleasures may differ so deeply that there is no unified notion of plea- sure. Without such a notion, hedonism does not get off the ground (section 7).5 My distinction between hedonism, non-hedonism, and anti-hedonism ad- dresses an inauspicious tendency in the literature. Often, the views of Plato and Aristotle are labeled as anti-hedonist, while on my account they are non- hedonist.6 Terminology aside, this matters because there is room for mark- edly more negative views of pleasure than Plato and Aristotle hold, views that diverge sufficiently from their proposals to merit a different designation. It is an ordinary intuition, today and in antiquity, that wanting one’s life to be plea- surable is not the same as pursuing pleasure for its own sake.7 Ethics should accommodate this distinction, and refrain from classifying too many views as anti-hedonist. More than that, non-hedonism may well provide a model for ethical theorizing. Informed by psychology, it proposes norms that are distinc- tively norms for beings with our kind of mental life.

2 Only Pleasure is Non-derivatively Good

Ancient discussions of hedonism tend to start with one of the following exchanges, or a mix thereof:8

5 An influential account of hedonism today is offered in Feldman 1997 and Feldman 2004. 6 Recent contributions that ascribe anti-hedonism to Plato are Figal 2008; Evans 2008; Harte 2008; Shaw 2015. Moss emphasizes the ways in which Aristotle characterizes pleasure as deceptive and misleading (2012). Rapp describes Aristotle’s positive assessment of pleasure in NE VII.13, 1153b8–15 as ‘shocking’ (2009); on my reading, it is not. 7 Thucydides employs his distinction, seemingly picking up on fifth century discussions. In his terms, it is one thing to want to live in a way that is accompanied by pleasure, καθ’ἡδονήν (History of Peloponnesian War, ΙΙ.37.2) and another thing to live for the sake of pleasure, διὰ ἡδονήν (I.120.4). Cf. de Romilly 1966. I owe this reference to Giulia Bonasio. 8 Philebus 11a–12a as well as Nicomachean Ethics (NE), Book I treat these questions as near-equivalent.