Democratic Classrooms: 50 Promises and Challenges of Student Voice and Choice, Part One
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Democratic Classrooms: 50 Promises and Challenges of Student Voice and Choice, Part One by Kristan A. Morrison Abstract If we ever hope to have schools that are engaging and that truly embody democracy, then the classes within them must provide opportu- nities for students to experience autonomy, freedom, and choice in what is studied, when, and how. This article explores both the historical and theo- retical framework of democratic freedom-based education and the prom- ises and challenges of implementing democratic practices in schools. Keywords: democratic education, freedom-based education Introduction Schools and society are reflections of one another. Certain values and beliefs are dominant in our society and inculcated in school. They include • a competitive ethos and firm conviction that a meritocracy exists in our society • a view that instrumental and extrinsic motivations are more important than intrinsic motivations • an excessive valuing of academics • A belief in the atomization and fragmentation of subjects of study, people, and nature • the conviction that the characteristic of obedience (doing as one is told or believing as one is told) is of more value in our society than that of criticality • the belief that one’s worth can be defined by others (as good stu- dent or bad student) Democratic Classrooms, Part One Once students become adults, they perpetuate those same dominant values in both society and school. This cycle is complicated, however, because beyond those dominant values, schools are “terrains of struggle” (Giroux 1988), places where contradictory values and ideals compete for prominence. Critical educational theorists, who include John Dewey and more- contemporary authors such as Henry Giroux, Paulo Freire, Peter McLaren, bell hooks, David Purpel, and Maxine Greene, argue that certain moral, 51 political, and intellectual ideals should take precedence over others in schools. They assert that our schools should emphasize commitment to a democratic system in which each citizen’s autonomy and dignity are hon- ored in an open, just, respectful, and pluralistic community, a community that values and encourages a critical approach in the intellectual search for truth and meaning in each individual’s life (Purpel 1989). The community these theorists seek is a delicately balanced synthe- sis between the individual (thesis) and a collection of individuals (anti- thesis). In other words, an individual’s autonomy is delimited by others’ rights to dignity, respect, safety, and the search for truth and meaning to everyone’s lives; if person A decides to do something that somehow infringes on person B’s rights, then person A is prohibited from taking that action and encouraged to find actions that can both express his or her autonomy and honor the rights of others. educational HORIZONS Fall 2008 Many of us know from experience that our society’s schools often fall far short of fostering the development of people who value diversity, who are both autonomous yet cognizant of others’ needs and rights, and who are open-minded yet equipped with critical-thinking skills to ana- lyze contradictory ideas. Instead, many of our schools foster the devel- opment of very different sorts of individuals. Does that indicate that the critical educational theorists are wrong? 52 No, it just means that they and like-minded educators must struggle to actualize their ideals in schools. One way to do that, I would argue, is to institute more democratic and freedom-based practices within our edu- cational system. This article explores the historical and theoretical framework of such practices, and then goes on to detail their promises and challenges. Definitions and Historical/Theoretical Framework The term “democratic education” as used in this article is linked with and synonymous with the term “freedom-based education,” for just as democracy as a political system is grounded in individual freedoms, democracy as an educational system is also grounded in freedoms. The linkage between the two terms is supported by the self-descriptions of most freedom-based schools in the United States (e.g., “free schools,” Sudbury Valley-modeled schools, “unschooling” families, etc.), which also identify themselves as sites of democratic education. In democratic and freedom-based education, students are free to decide what they study, and how, and when they study it. This form of schooling has a number of historical antecedents, outlined by Bennis (2006). He argues that one genesis of this model of education is the form of learning found in most pre-industrial societies. In these societies (past and present), children are actively engaged in the life of a given society; they learn skills and knowledge by means of imitation, apprenticeship, modeling, and conversation rather than in any formal school setting. Freedom-based education is also rooted in the Western philosophical tradition of the ancient Greeks, in the Romantic thinkers (e.g., Rousseau and Froebel), in the libertarian-anarchist tradition, in the transcendental- ist movement of nineteenth-century America, and in the twentieth-cen- tury free-school movement (e.g., Summerhill School, led by A. S. Neill, and the many U.S. free schools that cropped up during the countercul- tural revolution of the 1960s and 1970s) (pp. 23–32). Democratic and freedom-based education is grounded in the prem- ise that people are naturally curious and have an innate desire to learn and grow. If left un-fettered, un-coerced, and un-manipulated (e.g., by conventional educational practices that often diminish those innate characteristics), people will pursue their interests vigorously and with Democratic Classrooms, Part One gusto, and thus learn and make meaning on their own and in concert with others. Individuals honored and respected in this process become socialized to honor and respect the dignity and autonomy of others (Dennison 1969; Hern 1996; Holt 1972, 1989; Illich 1971; Llewellyn 1997; Mercogliano 1998; Neill and Lamb 1992). Although most contemporary freedom-based education is found in the form of private schools or the home-schooling version, “unschool- ing” (Morrison 2007b), American public schools could shift more closely 53 to this model by adopting more-democratic practices and organizational structures (Reitzug 2003). Thus, enacting democratic practices within conventional, more-authoritarian and -bureaucratic schools could serve as a steppingstone toward adopting the model of democratic and free- dom-based education more fully. Democratic education can take multiple forms, ranging from the micro level of within-class democracy to the more-ideal macro level of whole-school democracy, and within each level, a number of different democratic practices can be enacted. For example, at the micro level, a teacher can utilize discussion; offer students test and assignment choices that attend to their unique learning preferences; allow students “protest rights” (Shor 1996); practice contract grading (Shor 1996) or self-grad- ing; allow students to call the teacher by first name; and ask students to co-construct the course (have a voice in course content, grading, rubric creation, etc.). At the macro, whole-school level, schools can allow stu- dents to construct their entire curricula. (See Morrison 2007a, which examines the Albany Free School, a school where pre-K through eighth- grade students choose what, how, and when they study subjects, or see Goddard College for university-level self-development of curricula.) Promises of Democratic Education Proponents of democratic and freedom-based education argue that with autonomy and choice, people experience a much-different, much- better form of education than that offered by the conventional, hierar- chical, more-coercive education system present in most public schools. First, they argue that a democratic education promises much more meaningful learning. If people have choice and freedom to study what interests them, then they become more deeply engaged in, and thus less alienated from, their learning. More engagement leads to better retention and better critical reflection and analysis. For example, Watson wrote in Summerhill: For and Against (1970) that “pupils given freedom to decide what they will do, when, and how develop increasing independence, stronger interests, and better quality of work” (p. 177). educational HORIZONS Fall 2008 Gatto, in Dumbing Us Down: The Hidden Curriculum of Compulsory Schools (1992), echoes that argument, stating that our con- ventional education system infantilizes students by constantly com- pelling them and that this compulsion “guarantees that they will do [work] poorly, with a bad will, or indifferently” (p. 93). Democratic edu- cation, conversely, has no infantilizing effect; instead, it places great trust in the students, and they, more often than not, rise to the challenge. In 54 the process, students become more mature, self-disciplined, and intrinsi- cally motivated, seeing the value of learning above and beyond its use- fulness to getting a “good job” (Bhave 1996; Labaree 1997). Proponents of democratic education further argue that people who are given freedom and choice will ultimately become better democratic citizens because they have learned how to negotiate with others, to name obstacles, and to know themselves (Bhave 1996; Dewey 1916; Gatto 1992; Goodman 1962; Holt 1972; Holzman 1997; Illich 1971; Morrison 2007a; Shor 1996). That ultimately benefits all of society by developing people who are open to change