Fitness to Stand Trial and Mentally Challenged Defendants

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Fitness to Stand Trial and Mentally Challenged Defendants FITNESS TO STAND TRIAL AND MENTALLY CHALLENGED DEFENDANTS: EVALUATION OF THE FORENSIC PROCESS AND THE CRIMINAL CODE OF CANADA by Denise LaCombe Hitchen B.A., Carleton University, 1991 THESIS SUBMllTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the School of Criminology O Denise LaCombe Hitchen 1994 Simon Fraser University April, 1994 All rights reserved. This work may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without permission of the author. APPROVAL NAME: Denise LaCombe Hitchen DEGREE: Master of Arts TITLE OF THESIS: Fitness to Stand Trial and Mentally Challenged Defendants: Evaluation of the Forensic Process and the Criminal Code of Canada Examining Committee: Chair: Robert J. Menzies, Ph.D. ----------------z--------------------------------------- Derek Eaves, F.R.C.P. (C) External Examiner Executive Director British Columbia Forensic Psychiatric Services Commission 1 hereby grant to Simn Fraser University the right to lend my thesis, project or extended essay (the title of wfiich is shcwn below) to users of the Simon Fraser University Library, and to make partial or single copies only fo; such users or in response to a request fr~mthe library of any other university, or other educational institution, on its own behalf or for one of its users. I further agree that permissi~n for multiple copying of this wcr4 for scholarly purposes nay be granted by me or the Gean of Graduate Studies. It is understood that copying or publication of this work for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permlsrion. Tit J e of Thes i S/V$$A$~~/F$~+~B$B/B$$#~ Fitness to Stand Trial and Mental ly Chall enged Defendants : Eva1 uation of the Forensic Process and the Criminal Code of Canada Denis LaCombe Hi tchen Abstract The goals of this exploratory research were to identify the relationship between fitness to stand trial and mental retardation among criminal defendants, and to evaluate the forensic processing of mentally challenged (MC) accused persons referred for fitness assessments. Over three one-year study periods, 52 files iere reviewed, comprised of files of 30 non-mentally challenged subjects, 8 MC subjects, and 14 dual-diagnosed subjects (i.e., persons diagnosed with an Axis I clinical syndrome as well as mental retardation) referred for court-ordered assessments at the Forensic Psychiatric Institute in British Columbia. A coding manual was used to code information on sociodemographic characteristics, psychiatric history, criminal history, and psychiatric assessment. MC patients were younger than other patients at the time of admission, had longer periods of institutionalization in mental health facilities, and exhibited different criminal behaviour as determined by past criminal convictions and current charges. Concerns were raised about diagnostic practices and the lack of standardized evaluations for fitness to stand trial. It was suggested, first, that symptoms of mental retardation, including borderline intellectual functioning, should be investigated, and second, that standardized psycholegal measures specifically designed for fitness evaluations of defendants with mental retardation should be utilized. The CAST-MR, for example, involves increased reliance on multiple-choice questions and vocabulary and syntax appropriate for MC adults whose fitness to stand trial is questioned. iii Utilization of standardized procedures has been advocated for some time. While the Criminal Code of Canada states the criteria for a finding of unfitness (i.e., on account of mental disorder, the accused is unable to understand the nature or object of the proceedings, to understand the possible consequences of the proceedings, or to communicate with counsel), the emphasis remains on mental disorder (i.e., disease of the mind), which is quite different from mental retardation. Standardized assessments and established procedures would assist in the forensic processing of defendants with mental retardation and would also restrict the flow of extraneous information or inappropriate recommendations from the clinic to the court, such as offering non-solicited opinions concerning long-term treatment plans beyond the competence issue. Acknowledgments First, I would like to thank my mentor and senior supervisor, Dr. Simon Verdun-Jones for his support and encouragement throughout my graduate programme and during my research. His wisdom in the area of law and mental health continues to be inspiring. Also, Dr. Bill Glackman of my Supervisory Committee was very helpful as I wandered in the field of research methods and statistics, and made the world of statistics a more interesting place for me. I am grateful to the Forensic Psychiatric Services Commission and Dr. Derek Eaves, the Executive Director, for supporting this project. Without the special help of Ms. Faye Grant, this project would still be underway. Ms. Linda Westfal and the staff at the Medical Records Department at the Forensic Psychiatric Institute were very accommodating. Dr. Hans Veiel and Dr. Michael Coles at the Psychology Department of the lnstitute kindly answered the many questions I asked. Finally, I would like to thank my family for their patience, support, and understanding, without which this project would not have been completed. Table of Contents Chapter Approval II Abstract iii Acknowledgments v Chapter One: Introduction Statement of Problem Research Objectives Chapter Two: The Meaning of Mental Retardation Intellectual Functioning Adaptive Functioning The Difference Between Mental Disorder and Mental Retardation Dual Diagnoses The Relationship Between Mental Handicap and Criminality MC Persons in the Criminal Justice System Summary Chapter Three: The Legal Framework of Fitness to Stand Trial Historical Background Criteria for Unfitness to Stand Trial The Meaning of "Disease of the Mind" Ability to Understand the Nature or Object of the Proceedings Ability to Understand the Possible Consequences of the Proceedings Ability to Communicate with Counsel Summary 0 Disposition of Unfit Accused Persons Fitness of MC Accused Persons Summary Chapter Four: Methods Setting Subjects Method Sampling Procedure The Research Question Research Concerns Chapter Five: Results Sociodemographic Characteristics Psychiatric History Previous Admission to Mental Health Institutions Intelligence Quotient Criminal History Current Charges Psychiatric Assessment Assessment Orders Admission to F.P.I. Psychological Testing DSM Diagnoses Developmental Disorders Psychoactive Substance Use Disorders Psychotic Disorders Mood Disorders Somatoform Disorders Sexual Disorders Psychological Factors Affecting Physical Condition Personality Disorders No Disorder or Diagnosis Clinical lmpressions Letter to Court and Discharge Status Treatment Recommendations Summary Non-MC Group MC Group Dual-Diagnosed Group Chapter Six: Discussion Sociodemographic Characteristics Gender Pge Race Psychiatric History Previous Admission to Mental Health Institutions Intelligence Quotient Criminal History Reaction of the Criminal Justice System Psychiatric Assessment Assessment Orders ;r Psychological Testing DSM Diagnoses Clinical lmpressions Letter to Court and Discharge Status Treatment Recommendations Implications of the Study Scope and Limitations of the Study Suggestions for Future Research vii Chapter Seven: Case Studies Case Vignette 1 Borderline MC Accused Recommended as Being Fit to Stand Trial Case Vignette 2 MC Accused Recommended as Being Fit to Stand Trial Case Vignette 3 MC Accused Recommended as Being Unfit to Stand Trial Discussion of Case Vignettes Summary Chapter Eight: Conclusions Appendix A: Coding Manual Appendix B: OffenceKharge Codes Appendix C: DSM-III-R Diagnostic Codes Appendix D: Psychometric Testing Codes Appendix E: Research Proposal and Approval References List of Cases viii List of Tables and Figures Table 1 Demographic Characteristics by Group Table 2 IQ Rating by Group Table 3 Previous Convictions by Criminal Code Offence and Group Table 4 Number of Charges by Criminal Code Offence and Group Table 5 Distribution of Psychometric Tests by Group Table 6 Summary of Diagnoses by Group Table 7 Fitness Decisions by Group Figure 1 Length of Admission by Group Chapter One Introduction In the past, mentally challenged (MC) individuals who committed criminal offences were considered "stupid and bad" (Brown & Courtless, 1968:1169). In 1690, for example, John Locke explained the difference between mental disorder and mental handicap: The insane (mentally disordered) had the power to reason but reasoned incorrectly, whereas the idiotic (mentally challenged) lacked the power to reason at all. The insane suffered a temporary loss of sense and the idiotic lacked a mind or sense at all (National Institute on Mental Retardation (NIMR), 1981:87). Ruedrich and Menolascino (1 984:49) state that, by the early 19001s, people came to support four distinct conclusions: (1) [tlhere were more retarded persons in our society than people realized; (2) the mentally retarded accounted for virtually all of the current social ills; (3) heredity was the major cause of mental retardation; and (4) because the "decadent" retarded appeared to reproduce faster than nonretarded citizens, society would soon be destroyed unless dramatic measures were taken. There was also much support during the first three decades of this century for the belief that "virtually every mentally retarded individual was a potential juvenile delinquent, and that most criminals had overt manifestations
Recommended publications
  • Why We Choose to Be Stupid
    Why we choose to be stupid : the responsibility of andragogy and a search for answers in paradox, Canon, multiculturalism and the philosophy of postmodern critical education theory by Gregory Norton Garcia A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Education in Adult, Community, and Higher Education Montana State University © Copyright by Gregory Norton Garcia (1997) Abstract: In this study ideas and concepts that can be used to describe the phenomenon of stupidity and explore the possibility that we choose to be stupid, were developed from the social and political philosophy of Western Civilization. The research methods applied were based on the phenomenological school of qualitative inquiry using a narrative style. Findings suggest we choose to be stupid and stupidity can be generally described in the following ways: Conceptually, it is a paradox or antilogy that can be behaviorally chronicled in a number of ways. Culturally, stupidity is a philosophically implied concept that has consistently been instrumental in shaping our ideas of intelligence. Andragogically, stupidity is voluntary behavior that may be conscious and/or unconscious, but is manifestly anti-moral if not immoral and so it is counterproductive. Individually and personally, stupidity is a seemingly anatomic behavioral response to serendipitous personal and cultural predicaments. Stupidity can result from confused thinking. It can result from a misinterpretation of reality and it can also be generated by the human incapacity to live a moral existence. While stupidity may not be curable, by developing more precise awareness, we can compensate for stupidity by more fully realizing consequences.
    [Show full text]
  • ``Foolishness'' in Early Modern Medicine and the Concept of Intellectual Disability
    Medical History, 2004, 48: 289±310 ``Foolishness'' in Early Modern Medicine and the Concept of Intellectual Disability C F GOODEY* The texts by Paracelsus, Felix Platter and Thomas Willis under consideration here have two things in common, despite their separate historical and cultural settings.1 First, they describe people who seem to relate both to their own world and to the external world in problematical ways which the authors variously call stultitia, fatuitas or stupiditas: ``foolishness''. My translation is intentionally imprecise and will, Ihope, restrain the reader from jumping to the conclusion that it signifies any clinical concept recognizable in modern medicine; it is, rather, an algebraic x whose content needs further investigation. The second common factor is that these are precisely the texts which some commentators do indeed believe to contain ``early'' diagnoses of a modern concept of intellectual disability 4``mental retardation'', ``learning disability'' etc.). This belief, of axiomatic status, presupposes that some such concept has existed across different historical periods in a more or less mutually recognizable form, and therefore that ``foolishness'', in the medical writers discussed here, just is, if primitively, our ``intellectual disability''.2 However ``foolishness'' needs closer examination, which Iattempt to provide here. 3 The claim that there are medical descriptions of intellectual disability this early involves assumptions about its defining characteristics, and the definition needs to be spelled out if we are to establish the degree of connection or disconnection between intellectual disability * C F Goodey, MA, 1 Whitfield Road, East Ham, F E James, `Some observations on the writings of Felix London E6 1AS.
    [Show full text]
  • French Romanticism and the Reinvention of Love by Maxime A
    French Romanticism and the Reinvention of Love By Maxime A. Foerster A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Romance Languages and Literatures: French) In the University of Michigan 2012 Doctoral Committee: Professor Michèle A. Hannoosh, Chair Professor Cristina Moreiras-Menor Associate Professor Jarrod L. Hayes Associate Professor Nadine M. Hubbs Lecturer Esther Newton © Maxime A. Foerster 2012 Dedication Au charchour ii Acknowledgements I would like to express my gratitude to David Halperin, David Caron and Frieda Ekotto for having encouraged me to start my PhD at UM, Ann Arbor. I have been honored and stimulated to work with Michèle Hannoosh who taught me coherence and rigor throughout these years of thinking and writing. I feel privileged to have been able to write my dissertation with those I called my dream team, composed of Professors Michèle Hannoosh, Jarrod Hayes, Cristina Moreiras, Esther Newton and Nadine Hubbs. For their friendship, support and fabulousness, I would like to thank Aaron Boalick, Jennifer Bonnet, Virginie Brinker, Neil Doshi, Matthieu Dupas, Gilles Freissinier, Aston Gonzales, Melanie Hawthorne, Trevor Hoppe, Lauren Kennedy, Gérard Koskovich, Charline Lafage, Larry La Fountain, Nicolas Lamorte, Bertrand Metton, Pedro Monaville, Marie-Pierre Pruvot, Pantxika Passicot, Steve Puig, Marie Stoll, Marcelino Viera, and Yannick Viers. I will never thank my parents enough for their love and understanding. Above all, thank you, H.N. iii Table of Contents
    [Show full text]
  • Stupiditythe Paradox
    stupiditythe paradox Stupidity Paradox.indd 1 07/04/2016 20:00 About the authors Mats Alvesson is Professor of Business Administration at the University of Lund, Sweden, University of Queensland and Cass Business School, City University, London. He has published extensively across a wide range of organisational behaviour topics and issues, is one of the most frequently cited European researchers in management and organisation studies and a sought-a"er speaker around the globe. He is the author of !e Triumph of Emptiness, Oxford University Press and Re"exive Leadership, Sage (with Martin Blom and Stefan Sveningsson). André Spicer is Professor of Organisational Behaviour at Cass Business School, City University, London, known for his research in the areas of the human side of work, leadership and ethics. He is widely published in both academic literature and the general business media and is a frequent commentator on sustainable business, behaviours at work and business culture. He is the author of !e Wellness Syndrome, Polity Press (with Carl Cederström). Stupidity Paradox.indd 2 07/04/2016 20:00 stupiditythe paradox THE POWER AND PITFALLS OF FUNCTIONAL STUPIDITY AT WORK Mats Alvesson & André Spicer PROFILE BOOKS Stupidity Paradox.indd 3 07/04/2016 20:00 First published in Great Britain in #$%& by PROFILE BOOKS LTD ' Holford Yard Bevin Way London ()%* +,- www.pro.lebooks.com Copyright © Mats Alvesson and André Spicer, #$%& %$ + / 0 & 1 2 ' # % Typeset in Minion by MacGuru Ltd Printed and bound in Great Britain by Clays, St Ives plc 3e moral right of the author has been asserted. All rights reserved. Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored or introduced into a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise), without the prior written permission of both the copyright owner and the publisher of this book.
    [Show full text]
  • Difference and Repetition
    Gilles Deleuze Difference and Repetition Translated by PauiPatton COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY PRESS Columbia University Press New York English translation copyright © 1994 The Athlone Press Limited All rights reserved Difference et Repetition © 1968, Presses Universitaires de France The publishers wish to express their appreciation of assistance given by the government of France through the French Ministry of Culture in the preparation of this translation. library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Deleuze, Gilles. [Difference et repetition. English] Difference and repetition/Gilles De1euze : translated by Paul Patton. p. em. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-231-08158-8 I. Difference (Philosophy) 2. Repetition (Philosophy) . 3. Philosophy, French-20th century. I. Title. B2430.D453D4513 1993 111-dc20 93 & 41815 CIP Printed in Great Britain on acid-free paper. c to 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Contents Translator's Preface xi Preface to the English Edition xv Preface xix INTRODUCTION: REPETITION AND DIFFERENCE 1 Repetition and generality: first distinction from the point of View of conduct - The two orders of generality: resemblance and equality - Second distinction, from the point of view of law - Repetition, law of nature and moral law - The programme of a philosophy of repetition according to Kierkegaard, Nietzsche and Peguy - True movement, theatre and representation - Repetition and generality: third distinction from the point of view of concepts - The comprehension of concepts and the phenomenon of 'blockage' - The three cases of 'natural blockage' and repetition: nominal concepts, concepts of nature and concepts of freedom - Repetition is not explained by the identity of the concept, any more than it is by a purely negative condition - The functions of the 'death instinct': repetition in its relation to difference and as requiring a positive principle.
    [Show full text]
  • In Early Modern Medicine and the Concept of Intellectual Disability
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PubMed Central Medical History, 2004, 48: 289±310 ``Foolishness'' in Early Modern Medicine and the Concept of Intellectual Disability C F GOODEY* The texts by Paracelsus, Felix Platter and Thomas Willis under consideration here have two things in common, despite their separate historical and cultural settings.1 First, they describe people who seem to relate both to their own world and to the external world in problematical ways which the authors variously call stultitia, fatuitas or stupiditas: ``foolishness''. My translation is intentionally imprecise and will, Ihope, restrain the reader from jumping to the conclusion that it signifies any clinical concept recognizable in modern medicine; it is, rather, an algebraic x whose content needs further investigation. The second common factor is that these are precisely the texts which some commentators do indeed believe to contain ``early'' diagnoses of a modern concept of intellectual disability 4``mental retardation'', ``learning disability'' etc.). This belief, of axiomatic status, presupposes that some such concept has existed across different historical periods in a more or less mutually recognizable form, and therefore that ``foolishness'', in the medical writers discussed here, just is, if primitively, our ``intellectual disability''.2 However ``foolishness'' needs closer examination, which Iattempt to provide here. 3 The claim that there are medical descriptions of intellectual disability this early involves assumptions about its defining characteristics, and the definition needs to be spelled out if we are to establish the degree of connection or disconnection between intellectual disability * C F Goodey, MA, 1 Whitfield Road, East Ham, F E James, `Some observations on the writings of Felix London E6 1AS.
    [Show full text]
  • I INDISPENSABLE IDIOCY: COGNITIVE DISABILITY and the SOCIAL CONTRACT by Stacy Clifford Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty Of
    INDISPENSABLE IDIOCY: COGNITIVE DISABILITY AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT By Stacy Clifford Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Vanderbilt University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in Political Science December, 2011 Nashville, Tennessee Approved: Professor Brooke A. Ackerly Professor W. James Booth Professor Emily C. Nacol Professor Susan Saegert i Copyright © 2011 by Stacy Anne Clifford All rights reserved ii In memory of my cousin Courtney Clifford. “Tough times don’t last; tough people do.” iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This work would not have been possible without the support and encouragement of my dissertation committee: Brooke Ackerly, James Booth, Emily Nacol and Susan Saegert. Their feedback and commitment to my project have been invaluable. I am especially indebted to my advisor, Brooke Ackerly, who has worn many mentoring hats during my graduate career and has read and listened to many half-baked and completely unbaked versions of this dissertation. Thanks. I owe a special thanks to the Department of Political Science at Vanderbilt University, especially Marc Hetherington, Jon Hiskey, Darlene Davidson, and Natasha, who have helped me at all stages of graduate school. Surviving grad school, however, would have been impossible without my graduate cohort, especially Gbemende Johnson, Ying Zhang, John Judak, Jason Husser, Miguel Cruz, and Grace Jenson. The Robert Penn Warren Center, which provided financial support and invaluable free time during this last year of writing, enabled me to complete this dissertation. The director, Mona Frederick, welcomed me to the Warren Center during my first year at Vanderbilt and has continued to show her support of my project.
    [Show full text]
  • Carl Gustav Jung, Avant-Garde Conservative
    Carl Gustav Jung, Avant-garde Conservative by Jay Sherry submitted to the Doctoral Committee of the Department of Educational Science and Psychology at the Freie Universität Berlin March 19, 2008 Date of Disputation: March 19, 2008 Referees: 1. Prof. Dr. Christoph Wulf 2. Prof. Dr. Gunter Gebauer Chapters Page 1. Introduction 3 2. Basel Upbringing 5 3. Freud and the War Years 30 4. Jung’s Post-Freudian Network 57 5. His Presidency 86 6. Nazi Germany and Abroad 121 7. World War II Years 151 8. The Cold War Years 168 9. Jung’s Educational Philosophy 194 Declaration of independent work 210 Jay Sherry Resumé 211 Introduction Carl Gustav Jung has always been a popular but never a fashionable thinker. His ground- breaking theories about dream interpretation and psychological types have often been overshadowed by allegations that he was anti-Semitic and a Nazi sympathizer. Most accounts have unfortunately been marred with factual errors and quotes taken out of context; this has been due to the often partisan sympathies of those who have written about him. Some biographies of Jung have taken a “Stations-of-the-Cross” approach to his life that adds little new information. Richard Noll’s The Jung Cult and The Aryan Christ were more specialized studies but created a sensationalistic portrait of Jung based on highly selective and flawed assessment of the historical record. Though not written in reaction to Noll (the research and writing were begun long before his books appeared), this dissertation is intended to offer a comprehensive account of the controversial aspects of Jung’s life and work.
    [Show full text]
  • Errare Humanum Est… on Psychoanalysis As Morosophy
    Errare Humanum Est… On Psychoanalysis as Morosophy Dany Nobus What does it mean for something or someone to be (called) stupid? Were this to be a stupid question, the answer would probably be glaringly self-evident, yet since the answer is everything but straightforward, the question may easily result in the designated replier feeling stupefied, dumbfounded and thus rather stupid, so that the very lack or deferral of a clear answer effectively provides the answer one was looking for all along. Since time out of mind, stupidity has been employed with reference to an existence in defectu—as the absence, loss, or omission of a certain cognitive, affective and/or conative quality, a level of functioning below a certain average, or a state of being that is inferior to an agreed standard of normality, in short a failure to be in possession of a capability that is considered to be ubiquitously present. Stupidity is what falls outside, and generally below the boundaries of common sense and what quite literally stands out as such, because it cannot be recuperated within them. What was once accepted as wise may subsequently become stupid when the paradigms of wisdom shift towards new empirical or discursive truths, and what was once regarded as stupid may turn out to be wise when epistemic conditions, intellectual matrices, belief 1 systems and power balances shift. Even though it was universally accepted for centuries as an undisputed fact, and continued to be enforced in the face of scientific evidence appearing to prove the contrary, the Ptolemaic geocentric perspective on the heavenly spheres has now been relegated to the dustbin of human stupidities.1 Whereas persistent, seemingly excessive hand-washing was once perceived as distinctly stupid and possibly symptomatic of an underlying mental health condition, in times of a global, devastating pandemic, it might turn out to be one of the wisest things human beings can do in order to protect themselves and others against sickness and disease.
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Intelligence and Intellectual Disability
    A HISTORY OF INTELLIGENCE AND “INTELLECTUAL DISABILITY” Starting with the hypothesis that not only human intelligence but also its antithesis “intellectual disability” are nothing more than historical contingencies, C.F. Goodey’s paradigm-shifting study traces the rich interplay between labelled human types and the radically changing characteristics attributed to them. From the twelfth-century beginnings of European social administration to the onset of formal human science disciplines in the modern era, A History of Intelligence and “Intellectual Disability” reconstructs the socio-political and religious contexts of intellectual ability and disability, and demonstrates how these concepts became part of psychology, medicine and biology. Goodey examines a wide array of classical, late medieval and Renaissance texts, from popular guides on conduct and behavior to medical treatises and from religious and philosophical works to poetry and drama. Focusing especially on the period between the Protestant Reformation and 1700, Goodey challenges the accepted wisdom that would have us believe that “intelligence” and “disability” describe natural, trans-historical realities. Instead, Goodey argues for a model that views intellectual disability and indeed the intellectually disabled person as recent cultural creations. His book is destined to become a standard resource for scholars interested in the history of psychology and medicine, the social origins of human self-representation, and current ethical debates about the genetics of intelligence. C.F. Goodey has researched and published on the history of “intellectual disability,” including the ethical and social implications of the concept, for more than 20 years. His articles have appeared in a number of scholarly journals, including History of Science, Medical History, History of the Human Sciences, Political Theory and Ancient Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Accepted Manuscript
    Hannah Baldwin Was it you who died, or your brother? Abstract: This paper seeks to apply Christie Davies’ target theory to the classical jokebook Philogelos, and more specifically its most common protagonist the scholastikos, whose central flaw is stupidity caused by his inability to interact with material reality, similar to modern “dotty professor” jokes. This paper seeks to build a model of how scholastikos jokes work, how the stereotype is constructed and perpetuated, how this differs from other “stupid” stereotypes used elsewhere in the Philogelos (largely ethnic-based stereotypes), and possible social and cultural anxieties bound up in the character of the scholastikos. It will explore the relationship between ancient and modern targets in light of Christie Davies’ target theory and extend this model of how humor functions to transhistorical case studies. Keywords: Christie Davies, target theory, Philogelos, classical humor, jokebook Corresponding author: Hannah Baldwin, Department of Classics, Royal Holloway, University of London, Egham, TW20 0EX, United Kingdom. E-mail: [email protected] Διδύμων ἀδελφῶν ὁ ἕτερος ἐτελεύτησεν. Σχολαστικὸς οὖν τῶι ζῶντι συναντήσας ἠρώτα· Σὺ ἀπέθανες ἢ ὁ ἀδελφός σου; One of a pair of twin brothers died. So when he met the living twin, the scholastikos asked: “Was it you who died, or your brother?”1 1 Introduction This paper will perform a transhistorical test of target theory on the one extant jokebook from the ancient Greco-Roman world: The Philogelos, or “laughter-lover.” It has been translated into various languages: English (Baldwin 1983, Berg 2008), Italian (Bracchini 2008), German (Thierfelder 1968) and French (Zucker 2008) among others.
    [Show full text]