Introduction 1. John Gray, Liberalisms, Essays in Political

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction 1. John Gray, Liberalisms, Essays in Political Notes Introduction 1. John Gray, Liberalisms, Essays in Political Philosophy (London: Routledge, 1989), p. 217. 2. J. B. Schneewind, "Introduction," in Mill: A Collection ofCritical Essays, ed. J. B. Schneewind (New York: Anchor Books Edition, 1968) , p. ix; and Bertrand Russell, "John Sruart Mill," in Schneewind, Mill, p. 21. 3. Acknowledging the significance of Rawls's influence on political philosophy in twentieth cenrury, Raphael suggests that no knowledgeable scholar has accepted his theory as a sound rheory of jusrice. See David . D. Raphael, Concepts ofJustice, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), p. 196. 4. Peter Jones, "Two Conceptions of Liberalism, Two Conceprions of Justice," British Journal ofPolitical Science 25, no. 4 (October 1995) : 515 . 5. Cecile Laborde, "The Reception of John Rawls in Europe," European Journal ofPolitical Theory 1, no. 2 (October 2002) : 133-5. 6. Victoria Davion and Clark Wolf, "Introduction: From Comprehensive Justice to Political Liberalism," in The Idea ofa Political Liberalism, Essays on Rawls, ed. Victoria Davion and Clark Wolf (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000), p. 1. 7. Brooke Ackerly, "John Rawls: An Introduction," Perspectives on Politics 4, no. 1 (March 2006) : 76 . 8. Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit (eds.), A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993), p. 15. 9. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, (New York: Basic Books, 1974) , p. 183. 10. John Rawls, The Law ofPeoples, (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 175. Dombrowski rejects the assumption that Rawls is reluctant about the relationship between religion and politics, and argues thar the focal point, which Rawls's political liberalism addresses, suggests a strategy ofsilence in managing this relationship. See Daniel A. Dombrowski, Rawls and Religion, The Case for Political Liberalism, (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2001), p. vii. 11. Manus I. Midlarsky, "Democracy and Islam: Implications for Civilizational Conflict and the Democratic Peace," International Studies Quarterly 42, no. 3 (September 1998) : 485 . 194 • Notes 12. Valerie Bunce,"ComparativeDemocratization, Bigand Bounded Generalization," Comparative Political Studies 33, no. 617 (AugustSeptembet 2000): 703-4. 13. Steven Ryan Hofmann, "Islam and Democracy: Micro-Level Indications of Compatibility," Comparative Political Studies 37, no. 6 (August 2004): 652. 14. Richard Rose, "How Muslims View Democracy: Evidence from Central Asia," Journal ofDemocracy 13, no. 4 (October 2002): 102. 15. Ibn Al-Manzur, Lisan Al-Arab, ed. Ali Shiri, vol. 4 (Beirut: Dar al-Ihya al-Turath al-Arabi, 1988), p. 460. 16. Islmail Ibn Hammad al-jouhari, Al-Sibah Taj al-Lughah wa Sihah al-Arabiyyah, 4th ed., vol. 3 (Beirut: Dar al-Ilrn Lilmalayin, 1985), p. 1236. 17. Ibn Al-Manzur, Lisan Al-Arab, vol. 6, p. 345. 18. The Qur'an, chapter "The House of Imran," verse 19. 19. Muhammad Hussein Tabatabai, Qur'an dar Islam, 2nd ed. (Tehran: Dar al-Kutub al-Islamiyyah, 1974), p. 12. 20. Muhammad Hussein Tabatabai, Al-Mizanfi Tafiir al-Our'an, vol. 18, 2nd ed. (Beirur: Muassasah al-Aalarni lil-Marbuaat, 1982), pp. 29-30. 21. The Qur'an, chapter "T he Consultation," verse 13. 22. Muhammad Taqi Misbah, Amuzishi Aqaid, vols. 1-2, 7th ed. (Qum : Markazi Chap wa Nashri Sazmani Tablighati Islami, 1991), pp. 29-31. 23. Ibn Al-Manzur, Lisan Al-Arab, vol. 7, p. 257. 24. Nasir Makarim Shirazi, Iatiqadi Ma, 2nd ed. (Qum : Intisharari Nasli Jawan, 1997), pp. 115-16. 25. Muhammad Hussein Tabarabai, Shia dar Islam, 2nd edition, (Qum : Markazi Matbouaati-yi Dar al-Tablighi Islami, 1969), p. 39. 26. Makarim Shirazi, Iatiqadi Ma , pp. 116-19. 27. Tabatabai, Shia dar Islam, pp. 31-2. 28. The Largest Shiite Communities, http://www.adherents.comllargecom/com_ shiite.htrnl . 29. Makarim Shirazi, Iatiqadi Ma, p. 119; also see: Tabatabai, Shia dar Islam, p.32. 30. Nasir Makarim Shirazi, Panjah Darsi Usouli Aqaid barayi [atoanan, 9th ed. (Qum : Madrasah Imam Ali, 1997), pp. 223-4. 31. Muhammad Rida Muzaffar, Aqaidal-Imamiyyah, 8th ed. (Beirut: Dar Al-Zahra, 2000), pp. 102-1 7. 32. Tabarabai, Shia dar Islam, p. 149. 33. Muhamm ad Taqi Misbah, Amuzishi Aqaid: Imamshinasi (Qum : Markazi Mudiriyyati Hawzi-yi Ilmiyyi-yi Qum, 1988), pp. 17-27, 121-34, and 439-41. 34. Muzaffar, Aqaid al-Imamiyyah, p. 89. 35. Imam Khomeini, Chihil Hadith, 13th ed. (Tehran: Institute of Compilation and Publication ofImam Khomeini's Works, 1997), pp. 456-7, 462-3. 36. Misbah, Amuzishi Aqaid, pp. 207-13. 37. Muzaffar, Aqaid al-Imamiyyah, P: 87. 38. Muzaffar, Aqaid al-Imamiyyab, p. Il l . Notes • 195 39. Al-Fazil Al-Miqdad , Sharhi Babi al-Hadi Ashar (Q urn: Matbaah ai-Islam, 1974), p. 75. 40. Murraza Mutahhari, wahy wa Nubuwwah, (Q um: Intisharati Hikmah, 1979), pp. 36-8. 41. For a list of these traits and practices see Muhammad Mahdi Naraqi, Jami al-Saadat (The Collector of Felicities), hnp: llwww.al-islam.org/al-tawhidl felicities. 42. Imam Khomeini, Wilayati Faqih: Hokoumati Islami, 7th ed. (Tehran: Institut e of Compilation and Publication of Imam Khorneini's Works, 1998), pp. 17, 22-5,28, 31. 43. Muhammad Hussein Tabarabai is a prominent philosopher and interpreter of the Q ur'an, usually called allama, meaning highly knowledgeable, and mufas­ siri kabir. meaning the great interpreter of the Qur'an. His masterpiece is his interpretation of the Qur'an, Al-Mizanfi Tafiir al-Qur'an, in 20 volumes, that has been repeatedly published in Beirut, Tehran, and Qum in the second half of the twentieth centu ry. A well-known Iranian philosopher, Murtaza Murahhari, describes Tabarabai's interpretation of the Qur'an as the greatest interpretation that has been ever written in Islamic history. See Abul Qasim Razzaqi, "Ba Allama-yi Tabatabai dar al-Mizan," in Yadnami-yi Mufassiri Kabir Ustad Allama-yi Tabatabai (Qurn: Intisharati Shafaq, 1982), p. 212. Misbah, an influential thinker in contemporary Iran, describes Tabarabai as the greatest interpreter and philosopher in the contemporary Shiite world. See Muhammad Taqi Misbah, "Sukhani Piramoun i Shakhsiyyati Ustad Allama-yi Tabarabai," in Yadnami-yi Mufassiri Kabir Ustad Allama-yi Tabatabai (Q um: Intisharari Shafaq, 1982), p. 41. Sobhani, a distinguished philosopher and jurist, argues rhar Tabarabai has delivered an original sryle of the interpretation of the Q ur'an, SeeJaafar Sobhani, "Nazari wa Gozari bar Zindigani-yi Ustad Allama-yi Tabatabai," in Yadnami-yi Mufassiri Kabir Ustad Allama-yi Tabatabai (Q um: Intisharati Shafaq, 1982), pp. 70-2. Jawadi Amoli, a prominent Shiite phi­ losopher and interpreter of the Qur'an, argue that in addition to his innova­ tion in the interpretation of the Qur'an, Tabarabai has promoted Islamic philosophy and made a strong anempt to reconcile between the teachings of the Q ur'an and Islamic philosophy and mysticism. See Muhammad Taqi Misbah, "Naqshi Ustad Allarna-yi Tabarabai dar Nihzati Fikri-yi Hawzi-yi Ilmiyyi-yi Qum', in Yadnami-yi Mufassiri Kabir Ustad Allama-yi Tabatabai (Q urn: Inrisharati Shafaq, 1982), pp. 141-3; and Abdullah Jawadi-yi Amoli, "Siri-yi Falsafi-yi Ustad Allama-yi Tabatabai," in Yadnami-yi Mufassiri Kabir Ustad Allama-yi Tabatabai, (Qum : Intisharati Shafaq, 1982), pp. 167-8. 44. Among their students are the following: Murtaza Mutahhari, a unique Islamic thinker in the contemporary Shiite world whose books have been broadly studied in the last three decades; Muhammad Hussein Beheshti and Abdulkarim Mousavi Ardabili, the first and the second head of the judiciary of the Islamic Republic of Iran; Ibrahim Amini, the depury director of the Assembly of Experts for the appointment of the supreme leader in Iran; Hassan Hassanzadi 196 • Notes Amoli and Abdullah Jawadi Amoli, rhe mosr disringuished philosophers of present Iran; Muhammad Taqi Misbah, rhe mosr influential religious scholar in presenr Iranian polirics; Nasir Makarim Shirazi, and Hussein Nouri Hamidani, two top jurisrs of present Iran; and finally Jaafar Sobhani, the most prominent theologian in the contemporary Shiite world. See Sobhani , "Nazari wa Gozari bar Zindigani-yi Ustad Allama-yi Tabarabai," p. 73. 45. J. A. Simpson and E. S. C. Weiner (eds.), The Oxford English Dictionary, 2nd ed., Vol. 8, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), p. 88 I. 46. Seymour Martin Lipset, The Encyclopedia ofDemocracy (London: Routledge, 1995), p. 756; Patrick Neal and David Paris, "Liberalism and the Communitarian Critique: A Guide for the Perplexed," Canadian Journal of Political Science 23, no. 3 (September 1990): 43 I. 47. John Kekes, Against Liberalism (Irhaca: Cornell University, 1997), p. 2. 48. Richard Bellamy, Rethinking Liberalism (London: Pinter, 2000) , p. 43. 49. John Gray, Liberalism, 2nd ed. (Berkshire: Open University Press, 1995), pp. xi, 46. 50. Anthony Arblaster, The Rise and Decline ofWestern Liberalism (Oxford : Basil Blackwell, 1984), p. 56. 51. Richard Bellamy, Liberalism and Modern Society: An Historical Argument (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1992), p. 2. 52. Benjamin Constant , "Liberty Ancient and Modern," in The History of European Liberalism. cd. G. de Ruggiero(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1927), pp. 167- 8. 53. Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (London : Oxford University Press, 1969), p.lvi. 54. Ibid., pp. lvii, 132, 144. 55. Andrew Mason, "Imposing Liberal Principles," in Pluralism and Liberal Neutrality, ed. Richard Bellamy and Martin Hollis (London : Frank Cass, 1999), p. 99. 56. Chandran Kukarhas. "AreThere Any Cultural Rights?" Political Theory 20, no. I (February 1992): 116, 128. 57. A. H . Robertson and J. G. Merrills, Human Rights in the World, 4th ed. (Manchester : Manchester University Press, 1996), pp. 2-7. 58. Eric Heinze, The Logic ofLiberal Rights: A Study in the Formal Analysis ofLegal Discourse (London: Routledge, 2003) , p. 13. 59. Bellamy, Rethinking Liberalism, pp. 146, 176-7. 60. Gray, Liberalism, pp. xii, xiii. 61. Richard Bellamy, "Liberalism," in Contemporary Political Ideologies, ed. Roger Earwell and Anthony Wright (London : Pinter, 1993), p. 24. 62. John Gray, Post-Liberalism, Studies in Political Thought, 2nd ed.
Recommended publications
  • Seven Atheisms
    SEVEN ATHEISMS Andrew Walker SEVEN ATHEISMS Exploring the varieties of atheism in John Gray’s book Seven Types of Atheism Andrew Walker Emeritus Professor of Theology, Culture and Education, King’s College London Christian Evidence Society christianevidence.org Text copyright © Andrew Walker 2019 Published by the Christian Evidence Society, London, 2019 christianevidence.com All rights reserved Editing and design: Simon Jenkins Cover photograph by PhotoDu.de / CreativeDomainPhotography.com. Creative Commons Attribution 2.0 Generic (CC BY 2.0) license Contents Introduction 5 The seven atheisms 19th century atheism 6 Secular humanism 8 Science as religion 12 Modern politicial religion 15 God-haters 18 Atheism without progress 22 The atheism of silence 25 Conclusion 27 Index 30 Introduction John Gray’s Seven Types of Atheism (Allen Lane, 2018) is an important book for both religious and non-religious readers. John Gray, who describes himself as an atheist, is nevertheless critical of most versions of atheism. His attitude to atheism is the same as his attitude to certain types of religion. This attitude is predicated upon Gray’s conviction that human beings are intrinsically dissatisfied and unpredictable creatures who can never get along with each other for any length of time. His view is based on a reading of human nature that sails close to the wind of the Christian concept of original sin, and is out of step with most modern forms of atheism. In particular, Gray is allergic to any forms of cultural progress in human behaviour especially if they are couched in positivistic or evolutionary terms. 5 ATHEISM 1 19th century atheism Gray sets out his stall in his first chapter, ‘The New Atheism: A Nineteenth- century Orthodoxy’.
    [Show full text]
  • Christianity, Natural Law and the So-Called Liberal State
    Christianity, Natural Law and the So-called Liberal State James Gordley According to the Book of Genesis, “God said, ‘Let us make man in our image, after our likeness.’ So God created man in his own image, in the image of God created he him; male and female created he them.” (Gen. 1:26–7) Here, my former colleague Jeremy Waldron has said, is “a doctrine [that]is enormously attractive for those of us who are open to the idea of religious foundations for human rights.”1 What is special about man is that he is created in the image of God. Waldron noted that “[m]any object to the political use of any deep doctrine of this kind. For some, this is a special case of a Rawlsian commitment to standards of public reason generally.”2 He quotes Rawls: “In discussing constitutional essentials and matters of basic justice we are not to appeal to comprehensive religious or philosophical doctrines” but only to “plain truths now widely accepted, and available, to citizens generally.”3 I will come back to this objection later. Rawls’ claim is particularly important for present purposes since he has said the most about what other people can and cannot say in the public forum. Waldron’s own difficulty is with “the further question of what work [this doctrine] can do.”4 Why does it matter? He quoted Anthony Appiah who said, “[w]e do not have to agree that we are created in the image of God ... to agree that we do not want to be tortured by government officials.”5 Towards the end of his article Waldon noted that “[c]onsistently, for almost the whole of the Christian era imago Dei [the image of God] has been associated with man’s capacity for practical reason...”6 He quoted Thomas Aquinas: “man is united to God by his reason or mind, in which is God’s image.”7 I think if he had pursued this point further he could have answered his question.
    [Show full text]
  • From Liberalisms to Enlightenment's Wake
    JOURNAL OF IBERTARIAN TUDIES S L S JL VOLUME 21, NO. 3 (FALL 2007): 79–114 GRAY’S PROGRESS: FROM LIBERALISMS TO ENLIGHTENMENT’S WAKE JEREMY SHEARMUR The progress of that darkness . from its first approach to the period of greatest obscuration. William Robertson, History of the Reign of Charles the Fifth I HAVE KNOWN JOHN Gray for quite a few years, and have long admired his work. We were among the (very few) political theorists in the U.K. who, in the early 1970s, had an interest in the work of Hayek, and more generally in issues relating to classical liberalism. During the 1980s, he emerged as the most powerful and effective theorist of classical liberalism in the U.K., notably through his re- interpretations of John Stuart Mill in Mill on Liberty (1983a), his Hayek and Liberty (1984), and his overview and critical assessment of the lib- eral tradition, Liberalism (1986). We had, over the years, various dis- cussions about Hayek and liberalism—as Gray mentions in his Hayek on Liberty—and in that connection we shared many intellectual con- cerns; notably, with problems about how classical liberalism related to particular traditional cultures, and about the value of lives that did not involve autonomy in any significant sense. Our discussions about these and related matters were occasional, and typically by telephone or at Liberty Fund conferences. In the course of one of these conversations, I suggested to Gray that he might consider col- lecting some of his essays on liberalism into a volume, as he kindly JEREMY SHEARMUR is Reader in Philosophy at the Australian National University.
    [Show full text]
  • UPAYA MEMBANGUN EPISTEMOLOGI ISLAM (Studi Pada Pembelajaran Buku “Our Philosophy” Di Rausyanfikr Yogyakarta)
    UPAYA MEMBANGUN EPISTEMOLOGI ISLAM (Studi Pada Pembelajaran Buku “Our Philosophy” di RausyanFikr Yogyakarta) RUSTAN EFENDY UIN Alauddin Makassar ABSTRACT RausyanFikr Institute is an agency of the study and publication of the book lies in Kaliurang Yogyakarta. The institute focuses on the study of philosophy and Islamic thought. Study participants were students from various regions in Indonesia. In this study, the authors focused on building the Islamic epistemology through the book “Our Philosophy” by Baqir Sadr, an Iraqi cleric concerned about world issues and an architect revolutionary thinking. This book thoroughly dissected in RausyanFikr Institute and has been a curriculum epistemology at the agency. The author will show the opinion epistemology Baqir Sadr to view some Western thinkers such as Plato, Descartes, Immanuel Kant, and John Locke. He himself offered his thoughts as he constructions as “disposesion” (nazhariyah intiz’ā). Keyword : Islamic Epistemology ABSTRAK RausyanFikr Institute adalah lembaga penelitian dan penerbitan buku terletak di Kaliurang Yogyakarta. Lembaga ini berfokus pada studi filsafat dan pemikiran Islam. Peserta penelitian adalah mahasiswa dari berbagai daerah di Indonesia. Dalam penelitian ini, penulis berfokus pada membangun epistemologi Islam melalui buku “Filosofi” oleh Baqir Sadr, seorang ulama Irak khawatir tentang isu-isu dunia dan pemikiran revolusioner arsitek. Buku ini benar-benar dibedah di RausyanFikr Institute dan telah menjadi epistemologi kurikulum di lembaga tersebut. Penulis akan menunjukkan epistemologi opini Baqir Sadr untuk melihat beberapa pemikir Barat seperti Plato, Descartes, Immanuel Kant, dan John Locke. Dia sendiri ditawarkan pikirannya saat ia konstruksi sebagai “disposesion” (nazhariyah intiz’ā). Keyword: Epistemologi Islam PENDAHULUAN pola pikir mereka. Akibatnya kita tidak tahu ideologi atau kecenderungan apa yang dibawa Banyak orang yang mengasumsikan bahwa oleh produk-produk pemikiran tersebut dan pembelajaran filsafat dan pemikiran Islam bagaimana kita menyikapinya.
    [Show full text]
  • 276 DAFTAR PUSTAKA Abdullah, Muhammad, and Muhammad Junaid Nadvi. “Understanding the Principles of Islamic World-View.”
    DAFTAR PUSTAKA Abdullah, Muhammad, and Muhammad Junaid Nadvi. “Understanding the Principles of Islamic World-View.” The Dialogue VI, no. 3 (n.d.). Adian, Donny Gahral. Menyoal Objektivisme Ilmu Pengetahuan: Dari David Hume sampai Thomas Kuhn. Bandung: Teraju, 2002. ———. Muhammad Iqbal. Bandung: Teraju, 2003. Adib, Shohibul. “Diskursus Epistemologi Barat Dan Islam.” Islamuna. Last modified March 18, 2010. Accessed November 2, 2012. http://islamuna- adib.blogspot.com/2010/03/diskursus-epistemologi-barat-dan- islam.html. Akhtar, Sayyid Wahid. “The Islamic Concept of Knowledge.” Al-Tawhid: A Quarterly Journal of Islamic Thought & Culture 12, no. 3 (1997). Accessed December 28, 2013. http://www.al-islam.org/al-tawhid/islam-know- conc.htm. Ali, K. Sejarah Islam, Tarikh Pra Modern. Jakarta: Srigunting, 1997. Anshary, Muhammad Isa. “Sumbangan Dunia Islam Terhadap Kebangkitan Peradaban Eropa.” Muslimdaily.net. Accessed December 26, 2013. http://muslimdaily.net/artikel/studiislam/sumbangan-dunia-islam- terhadap-kebangkitan-peradaban-eropa.html. Aquinas, Thomas. “Commentary on the Posterior Analytics.” Diterjemahkan oleh Fabian R. Larcher O.P. Aquinas: Commentary on the Posterior Analytics Book I Lectures 1-8. Accessed December 22, 2013. http://www. logicmuseum.com/authors/aquinas/posterioranalytics/aquinasPA1-1- 8.htm#lib1l1n1. Aristoteles. “De Anima, Book II.” Diterjemahkan oleh J. A. Smith. Classics in the History of Psychology. Accessed December 22, 2013. http://psychclassics. yorku.ca/Aristotle/De-anima/de-anima2.htm. Armis, Adnin. Krisis Epistemologi Dan Islamisasi Ilmu. Ponorogo: CIOS, 2007. al-Asfahani, Abu Qasim Abu al-Husain bin Muhammad alRaghib. Al-Mufradat Fi Gharib Al-Qur’an. Mesir: Musthafa al-Bab al-Halabi, 1961. Asse, Ambo. “Konsep Adil Dalam Al-Qur’an.” Al-Risalah 10, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Property and Ownership
    Property and Ownership Gerald Gaus 1 PRIVATE PROPERTY: FUNDAMENTAL OR PASSÉ? For the last half century, thinking within political philosophy about private property and ownership has had something of a schizophrenic quality. The classical liberal tradition has always stressed an intimate connection between a free society and the right to private property.1 As Ludwig von Mises put it, “the program of liberalism....if condensed to a single word, would have to read: property, that is, private ownership....”2 Robert Nozick’s Anarchy, State and Utopia, drawing extensively on Locke, gave new life to this idea; subsequently a great deal of political philosophy has focused on the justification (or lack of it) of natural rights to private property.3 Classical liberals such as Eric Mack — also drawing extensively on Locke’s theory of property — have argued that “the signature right of any rights-oriented classical liberalism is the right of self-ownership.”4 In addition, Mack argues that “we have the same good reasons for ascribing to each person a natural right of property” in “extrapersonal objects.”5 Each individual, Mack contends, has “an original, nonacquired right … to engage in the acquisition of extrapersonal objects and in the disposition of those acquired objects as one sees fit in the service of one’s ends.”6 Essentially, one has a natural right to become an owner of external property. Not all contemporary classical liberals hold that property rights are natural, but all insist that strong rights to private property are essential for a free society.7 Jan Narveson has recently defended the necessity in a free society of property understood as “a unitary concept, explicable as a right over a thing owned, against others who are precluded from the free use of it to which ownership entitles the owner.”8 GAUS/2 The “new liberal” project of showing that a free society requires robust protection of civil and political rights, but not extensive rights of private property (beyond personal property) has persistently attacked this older, classical, liberal position.
    [Show full text]
  • Balkan Liberalisms: Historical Routes of a Modern Ideology
    BALKAN LIBERALISMS: HISTORICAL ROUTES OF A MODERN IDEOLOGY Diana Mishkova Introduction In the Balkans, as in other places in Europe, liberalism is inextricably linked with the construction of modernity. Liberal ideas and movements triggered the emergence of the first concepts of modern rule and the first modern institutions in the region. Under their banner the struggles for national unification and independence were waged and a concept of legitimate government different from the traditional one was introduced: a representative government, as opposed to an autocratic or a bureau- cratic one, enacted by the liberals themselves on behalf of the sovereign nation. Liberalism presents a case of ideational and institutional transfer that changed the nature of politics: its premises and institutionalization meant not just new technical rules or organizational forms but a new form of politics. The liberal parties constituted the first modern political parties in the Balkans with a distinct conception about the arrangement of society based not simply on experience but on knowledge and visions of the future as well. And yet liberalism’s historical role with respect to Balkan political modernity, its local theoretical and institutional incarna- tions and its legacy continue to raise a number of basic yet under-studied questions. Why were the ‘rational’ modern legitimacy and the advent of political modernity in the newly emerging Balkan states predicated on the adoption of the liberal ideology? Which messages and institutional forms attracted the
    [Show full text]
  • The Abolition of Emerson: the Secularization of America’S Poet-Priest and the New Social Tyranny It Signals
    THE ABOLITION OF EMERSON: THE SECULARIZATION OF AMERICA’S POET-PRIEST AND THE NEW SOCIAL TYRANNY IT SIGNALS A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Georgetown University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Government By Justin James Pinkerman, M.A. Washington, DC February 1, 2019 Copyright 2019 by Justin James Pinkerman All Rights Reserved ii THE ABOLITION OF EMERSON: THE SECULARIZATION OF AMERICA’S POET-PRIEST AND THE NEW SOCIAL TYRANNY IT SIGNALS Justin James Pinkerman, M.A. Thesis Advisor: Dr. Richard Boyd, Ph.D. ABSTRACT Motivated by the present climate of polarization in US public life, this project examines factional discord as a threat to the health of a democratic-republic. Specifically, it addresses the problem of social tyranny, whereby prevailing cultural-political groups seek to establish their opinions/sentiments as sacrosanct and to immunize them from criticism by inflicting non-legal penalties on dissenters. Having theorized the complexion of factionalism in American democracy, I then recommend the political thought of Ralph Waldo Emerson as containing intellectual and moral insights beneficial to the counteraction of social tyranny. In doing so, I directly challenge two leading interpretations of Emerson, by Richard Rorty and George Kateb, both of which filter his thought through Friedrich Nietzsche and Walt Whitman and assimilate him to a secular-progressive outlook. I argue that Rorty and Kateb’s political theories undercut Emerson’s theory of self-reliance by rejecting his ethic of humility and betraying his classically liberal disposition, thereby squandering a valuable resource to equip individuals both to refrain from and resist social tyranny.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critique of John Gray's "Post-Liberalism" Gregory R
    Reason Papers The Non-Sequitur of Value-Relativism : A Critique of John Gray's "Post-Liberalism" Gregory R. Johnson,' Morehouse College In recent years, John Gray has transformed himself from a liberal theorist to a critic of liberal theory. Unlike most critics of liberal theory, however, Gray criticizes it not because it is liberal, but because it is theory. In fact, Gray is a strong defender of liberal society and practices, but his defense is self-consciously historicist rather than theoretical. The main statement of Gray's critique of liberal theory and defense of liberal practices is his essay "What is Dead and What is Living in ~iberalism."~What follows is primarily an exposition and critique of this article's argument. Gray's essay has two purposes. First, he wishes to argue that "liberalism, as a political philosophy, is . dead" (284). What Gray calls "liberalism as a political philosophy," he also calls "doctrinal" liberalism, "fundamentalist" liberalism, and "foundationalist"liber- alism. This phenomenon is characterized by the ideas of umive~salism,individualism, egalitarianism, and meliorism. Doctrinal liberalism is the view that individual rights and human equality are universally valid moral principles, which serve as the standard for legitimating all political regimes, regardless of time, place, or cultural differences. Doctrinal liberalism, in short, is the view that liberalism is a rationally defensible way of life for all human beings and the yardstick for historical progress. Gray's second purpose is to argue that what is living in liberalism is modern "civil society,~~a form of life characterized by individualism, egalitarianism, pluralism, toler- ance, meliorism, and even a form of universalism.
    [Show full text]
  • The Constitution and the Other Constitution
    William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal Volume 10 (2001-2002) Issue 2 Article 3 February 2002 The Constitution and The Other Constitution Michael Kent Curtis Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the First Amendment Commons Repository Citation Michael Kent Curtis, The Constitution and The Other Constitution, 10 Wm. & Mary Bill Rts. J. 359 (2002), https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj/vol10/iss2/3 Copyright c 2002 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/wmborj THE CONSTITUTION AND THE OTHER CONSTITUTION Michael Kent Curtis* In this article,Professor Michael Kent Curtisexamines how laws thatshape the distributionof wealth intersect with and affectpopularsovereigntyandfree speech and press. He presents this discussion in the context of the effect of the Other Constitutionon The Constitution. ProfessorCurtis begins by taking a close-up look at the current campaignfinance system and the concentrationof media ownership in a few corporate bodies and argues that both affect the way in which various politicalissues arepresented to the public, ifat all. ProfessorCurtis continues by talking about the origins of our constitutional ideals ofpopular sovereignty and free speech andpressand how the centralizationof economic power has limited the full expression of these most basic of democratic values throughout American history. Next, he analyzes the Supreme Court's decision in Buckley v. Valeo, the controlling precedent with respect to the constitutionality of limitations on campaign contributions. Finally, ProfessorCurtis concludes that the effect of the Other Constitution on The Constitution requires a Television Tea Party and a government role in the financingofpolitical campaigns.
    [Show full text]
  • Unlike Bentham, Mill Never Explicitly Defines Harm
    The Three (Four) Criteria of Legitimate Coercion in Mill’s Moral Theory I Introduction When analysing the scope and nature of Mill's “one very simple principle” in On Liberty, it is understandable that scholars focus on his initial articulation of the Principle in the opening pages of the essay: “that the sole end for which mankind are warranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of action of any of their numbers, is self-protection. That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.”1 This passage comprises the starting point for the understanding of what has come to be known as Mill's Principle of Liberty. It states that the only legitimate reason for coercively interfering with a person's liberty is self-protection and to prevent harm to others. Shortly thereafter, Mill clarifies that “it must by no means be supposed, because damage, or probability of damage, to the interests of others, can alone justify the interference of society, that therefore it always does justify such interference.”2 This passage is key, because it makes clear that though self-protection and the prevention of harm to others are the only reasons for legitimate coercion, and that other reasons may weigh in against this sanction. The purpose of the Principle is to assert that when no harm to others in involved, or self-protection not at risk, individual liberty cannot be restricted. By providing the only reason for legitimate coercion, and not telling us when coercion is legitimate, the Principle supplies the necessary – though not sufficient - conditions that must be met before legitimate coercion or punishment is warranted.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Study of Mutahhari's Writings on Karl Marx
    A CRITICAL STUDY OF MUTAHHARI'S WRITINGS ON KARL MARX DISSERTATION SUBMITTED FOR THE DEGREE OF M. PHIL. TO THE ALIGARH MUSLIM UNIVERSITY BY ALI NAGHI BAGHERSHAHI UNDER THE SUPERVISION OF Prof. Sayyid Waheed Akhtar DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY ALIGARH MUSLIM UNIVERSITY ALIGARH September 1987 i 3 SEF im ute« ^ Coit^P fd^ CHBCKEP 200Z DS1210 ALIGARH MUSLIM UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY Professor and Head of the Department Aligarh/. .yrd ;>io-t«nite. «r 87 This is to certify that Mr. Ali Naghi Bagher Shahi has worked under my supervision for his dissertation on "A Critical Study of Mutahhari's Writings on Karl Marx". He studied all the works of Mutahhari and the relevant literature. It was a pleasant revelation to me that his knowledge of Marxian philoso­ phy as well as his insight into contemporary Muslim Socio­ political thought was quite comprehensive. I hope that this dissertation will open new-avenues to the study of recent Iranian philosophy, ,• '- ." The dissertation, in my view, is'fit for submission for the award of M.Phil degrfeelof. Alig'arh Muslim University, Aligarh. I certify further that the entire work is his own. (Pr«f. S. vV heed Akhtar) <- Ita:, ,1,(11, Lhpurnncni of Fhiloso{shy 4. AT. a, ALJe'ARH 9=Q=0=S=S=1=§ Sigg^ig' CHAPTER (A), Mutahhari's Life and Times, 01 (B) Materialism: A Challenge to XSJLcuIl* •••• «••• •••• ••• 16 (C) His Works and Their Thrust: An Attempt to Reconstruct Islamic Ideology. • • • • • « 24 CHAPTER II Marxism as Elaborated by Mutahhari. (A). Dialectics 43 (B). Materialist Metaphysics .... 55 (C). Historical Materialism ...
    [Show full text]