PARTITIONING a REFLECTING STATIONARY SET 1. Introduction A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PARTITIONING a REFLECTING STATIONARY SET 1. Introduction A PARTITIONING A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET MAXWELL LEVINE AND ASSAF RINOT Abstract. We address the question of whether a reflecting stationary set may be parti- tioned into two or more reflecting stationary subsets, providing various affirmative answers in ZFC. As an application to singular cardinals combinatorics, we infer that it is never the case that there exists a singular cardinal all of whose scales are very good. 1. Introduction A fundamental fact of set theory is Solovay's partition theorem [Sol71] asserting that, for every stationary subset S of a regular uncountable cardinal 휅, there exists a partition hSi j i < 휅i of S into stationary sets. The standard proof involves the analysis of a certain C-sequence over a stationary subset of S; such a sequence exists in ZFC (cf. [LS09]), but assuming the existence of better C-sequences, stronger partition theorems follow. For instance: + ∙ (folklore) If 휅 = 휆 and 휆 holds, then any stationary subset S of 휅 may be par- titioned into non-reflecting stationary sets hSi j i < 휅i. That is, for all i < 휅, Si is stationary, but Tr(Si) := f훽 < sup(Si) j cf(훽) > ! & Si \ 훽 is stationary in 훽g is empty. ∙ [Rin14, Lemma 3.2] If (휅) holds, then for every stationary S ⊆ 휅, there exists a ~ coherent C-sequence C = hC훼 j 훼 < 휅i such that Si := f훼 2 S j min(C훼) = ig is ~ stationary for all i < 휅. The coherence of C implies that the elements of hTr(Si) j i < 휅i are pairwise disjoint as well. ∙ [BR19, Theorem 1.24] If (휅) holds, then any fat subset of 휅 may be partitioned into 휅-many fat sets that do not simultaneously reflect. This raises the question of whether there is a fundamentally different way to partition large sets. A more concrete question reads as follows: Question 1.1. Suppose that S is a subset of a regular uncountable cardinal 휅 for which T Tr(S) is stationary. Can S be split into sets hSi j i < 휃i in such a way that 푖<휃 Tr(Si) is stationary? And how large can 휃 be? Remark. Note that for any sequence hSi j i < 휃i of pairwise disjoint subsets of 휅, the T 휅 intersection 푖<휃 Tr(Si) is a subset of E≥휃. Therefore, the only cardinals 휃 of interest are the ones for which 휅 n 휃 still contains a regular cardinal. The above question leads us to the following principle: Date: February 15, 2019. The second author was partially supported by the European Research Council (grant agreement ERC- 2018-StG 802756) and by the Israel Science Foundation (grant agreement 2066/18). 1 2 MAXWELL LEVINE AND ASSAF RINOT Definition 1.2. Π(S; 휃; T ) asserts the existence of a partition hSi j i < 휃i of S such that T T \ 푖<휃 Tr(Si) is stationary. In Magidor's model [Mag82, x2], Π(S; @ ;T ) holds for any two stationary subsets S ⊆ E@2 1 @0 and T ⊆ E@2 , and it is also easy to provide consistent affirmative answers to Question 1.1 @1 without appealing to large cardinals. However, the focus of this short paper is to establish that instances of the principle Π(:::) hold true in ZFC. It is proved: Theorem A. Suppose that 휇 < 휃 < 휆 are infinite cardinals, with 휇, 휃 regular. (1) If 휆 is inaccessible, then Π(휆, 휃; 휆) and Π(휆+; 휆, 휆+) both hold; 휆+ 휆+ (2) If 휆 is regular, then Π(E휇 ; 휃; E휃 ) holds; 휃 휆+ 휆+ (3) If 2 ≤ 휆 and 휃 6= cf(휆), then Π(E휇 ; 휃; E휃 ) holds; 휆+ 휆+ (4) If 휆 is singular, then Π(E휇 ; 휃; E≤휃+3 ) holds. It is worth mentioning that our proof of Clause (4) is indeed fundamentally different than all standard proofs for partitioning a stationary set. We build on the fact that any singular cardinal admits a scale and that the set of good points of a scale is stationary relative to any cofinality; we also use a combination of club-guessing with Ulam matrices to avoid any cardinal arithmetic hypotheses. We initiated this project since we realized that ZFC instances of Π(:::) would allow us to prove that the statement \all scales are very good" is inconsistent. And, indeed, the following is an easy consequence of Theorem A: Corollary. Suppose that 휆 is a singular cardinal, and ~휆 is a sequence of a regular cardinals of length cf(휆), converging to 휆. If Q ~휆 carries a scale, then it also carries a scale which is not very good. In this short paper, we also consider a simultaneous version of the principle Π(:::) which is motivated by a simultaneous version of Solovay's partition theorem recently obtained by Brodsky and Rinot: Lemma 1.3 ([BR19, Lemma 1.15]). Suppose that hSi j i < 휃i is a sequence of stationary 0 subsets of a regular uncountable cardinal 휅, with 휃 ≤ 휅. Then there exists a sequence hSi j i 2 Ii of pairwise disjoint stationary sets such that: 0 ∙ Si ⊆ Si for every i 2 I; ∙ I is a cofinal subset of 휃.1 Evidently, Solovay's theorem follows by invoking the preceding theorem with a constant sequence of length 휃 = 휅. The simultaneous version of Definition 1.2 reads as follows. ` Definition 1.4. (S; 휈; T ) asserts that for every 휃 ≤ 휈, every sequence hSi j i < 휃i of 0 T 0 subsets of S and every stationary T ⊆ T \ 푖<휃 Tr(Si), there exists a sequence hSi j i 2 Ii of pairwise disjoint stationary sets such that: 0 ∙ Si ⊆ Si for every i 2 I; 1Note that if we demand that I be equal to 휃, then we do not get a theorem in ZFC. PARTITIONING A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET 3 ∙ I is a cofinal subset of 휃; 0 T 0 ∙ T \ i2I Tr(Si) is stationary. It is proved: Theorem B. Suppose that 휈 < 휆 are uncountable cardinals with 휈 6= cf(휆), and 2휈 ≤ 휆. ` + 휆+ Then, any of the following implies that (휆 ; 휈; E휈 ) holds: (1) 휆 is a regular cardinal; (2) 휆 is a singular cardinal admitting a very good scale. 휅 휅 Notation and conventions. For cardinals 휃 < 휅, we let E휃 := f훼 < 휅 j cf(훼) = 휃g; E6=휃, 휅 휅 휅 + E>휃, E≥휃 and E≤휃 are defined similarly. For a set of ordinals a, we write acc (a) := f훼 < sup(a) j sup(a \ 훼) = 훼 > 0g and acc(a) := a \ acc+(a). The class of all ordinals is denoted by ORD. We also let Reg(휅) := f휃 < 휅 j @0 ≤ cf(휃) = 휃g. 2. pcf scales In this section, we recall the notion of a scale for a singular cardinal (also known as a pcf scale) and the classification of points of a scale. These concepts will play a role in the proof of Theorems A and B. In turn, we also present an application of the partition principle Π(:::) to the study of very good scales. ~ Definition 2.1. Suppose that 휆 is a singular cardinal, and 휆 = h휆i j i < cf(휆)i is a strictly increasing sequence of regular cardinals, converging to 휆. For any two functions f; g 2 Q ~휆 and i < cf(휆), we write f <i g iff, for all j 2 cf(휆) n i, f(j) < g(j). We also write f <* g to expresses that f <i g for some i < cf(휆). ~ + Definition 2.2. Suppose that 휆 is a singular cardinal. A sequence f = hf훾 j 훾 < 휆 i is said to be a scale for 휆 iff there exists a sequence ~휆 as in the previous definition, such that: + Q ~ ∙ for every 훾 < 휆 , f훾 2 휆; + * ∙ for every 훾 < 훿 < 휆 , f훾 < f훿; Q ~ + * ∙ for every g 2 휆, there exists 훾 < 휆 such that g < f훾. An ordinal 훼 < 휆+ is said to be: ∙ good with respect to f~ iff there exist a cofinal subset A ⊆ 훼 and i < cf(휆) such that, i for every pair of ordinals 훾 < 훿 from A, f훾 < f훿; ∙ very good with respect to f~ iff there exist a club C ⊆ 훼 and i < cf(휆) such that, for i every pair of ordinals 훾 < 훿 from C, f훾 < f훿. We also let: ~ 휆+ ~ ∙ G(f) := f훼 2 E6=cf(휆) j 훼 is good with respect to fg; ~ 휆+ ~ ∙ V (f) := f훼 2 E6=cf(휆) j 훼 is very good with respect to fg. 휆+ ~ ~ ~ Clearly, E<cf(휆) ⊆ V (f) ⊆ G(f). It is also not hard to see that if f;~g are two scales in the same product Q ~휆, then they interleave each other on a club, so that G(f~) 4 G(~g) is nonstationary. This means that, up to a club, the set of good points is in fact an invariant 4 MAXWELL LEVINE AND ASSAF RINOT of ~휆. We shall soon discuss the question of whether the same is true for the set of very good points, but let us first recall a few fundamental results of Shelah.2 Fact 2.3 (Shelah, [She93],[She94]). For every singular cardinal 휆: (1) There exists a scale for 휆; ~ ~ 휆+ (2) For any scale f for 휆 and every 휃 2 Reg(휆) n fcf(휆)g, the intersection G(f) \ E휃 is stationary; ~ + Q 휆+ (3) If f = hf훾 j 훾 < 휆 i is a scale for 휆 in a product i<cf(휆) 휆i and 훼 2 E6=cf(휆), ~ Q then 훼 2 G(f) iff there exists e 2 i<cf(휆) 휆i satisfying cf(e(i)) = cf(훼) whenever ~ 휆i > cf(훼), and such that e forms an exact upper bound for f 훼, i.e.: * ∙ for all 훾 < 훼, f훾 < e; Q * * ∙ for all g 2 i<cf(휆) 휆i with g < e, there is 훾 < 훼 with g < f훾.
Recommended publications
  • Forcing Axioms and Stationary Sets
    ADVANCES IN MATHEMATICS 94, 256284 (1992) Forcing Axioms and Stationary Sets BOBAN VELICKOVI~ Department of Mathematics, University of California, Evans Hall, Berkeley, California 94720 INTRODUCTION Recall that a partial ordering 9 is called semi-proper iff for every suf- ficiently large regular cardinal 0 and every countable elementary submodel N of H,, where G9 is the canonical name for a Y-generic filter. The above q is called (9, N)-semi-generic. The Semi-Proper Forcing Axiom (SPFA) is the following statement: For every semi-proper 9 and every family 9 of Et, dense subsets of 9 there exists a filter G in 9 such that for every DE 9, GnD#@. SPFA+ states that if in addition a Y-name 3 for a stationary subset of wi is given, then a filter G can be found such that val,(S)= {c(<wi: 3p~Gp I~-EE$) is stationary. In general, if X is any class of posets, the forcing axioms XFA and XFA + are obtained by replacing “semi-proper LY” by “9 E X” in the above definitions. Sometimes we denote these axioms by FA(X) and FA+(.X). Thus, for example, FA(ccc) is the familiar Martin’s Axiom, MAN,. The notion of semi-proper, as an extension of a previous notion of proper, was defined and extensively studied by Shelah in [Shl J. These forcing notions generalize ccc and countably closed forcing and can be iterated without collapsing N, . SPFA is implicit in [Shl] as an obvious strengthening of the Proper Forcing Axiom (PFA), previously formulated and proved consistent by Baumgartner (see [Bal, Del]).
    [Show full text]
  • On Disjoint Stationary Sets in Topological Spaces
    International Journal of Scientific and Innovative Mathematical Research (IJSIMR) Volume 7, Issue 9, 2019, PP 1-2 ISSN No. (Online) 2454-9444 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.20431/2347-3142.0709001 www.arcjournals.org On Disjoint Stationary Sets in Topological Spaces Pralahad Mahagaonkar* Department of Mathematics, Ballari Institute of Technology and Management, Ballari *Corresponding Author: Pralahad Mahagaonkar, Department of Mathematics, Ballari Institute of Technology and Management, Ballari Abstract : In this paper we study some new techniques from set theory to general topology and its applications , here we study some the partition relations ,cardinal functions and its principals and some more theorems . Further we develop the combinatory of stationary sets we have aimed at person with some knowledge of topology and a little knowledge of set theory. Keywords: Stationary sets ,homeomorphic, topologicalspaces, Bairespaces. 1. INTRODUCTION Here we will discuss some interesting subsets of ω1 – sets, Borel subsets, stationary and bi-stationary subsets of ω1 – and some theorems . In addition, we will mention some topological applications of stationary sets . Let us know that ω1 is an uncountable well-ordered set with the special property that if α < ω1, then the initial segment [0, α) of ω1 is countable, and that the countable union of countable sets is countable. Like any linearly ordered set, ω1 has an open interval topology. Le us consider that α is a limit point of the space ω1. 2. MAIN RESULTS Theorem 1.1 : A Borel subset of B(k) which is not in LW( k) is a homeomrphic to B(k). Definition : B(k) is the Baire zero dimensional space of weight k, is a function from k with the given d( f , g) 2n ,where n is the least of f / n g / n.
    [Show full text]
  • Nonreflecting Stationary Subsets Of
    F U N D AM E NTA nnoindentMATHEMATICAEF U N D AM E NTA 1 65 open parenthesis 2 0 0 closing parenthesis nnoindentNonreflectingMATHEMATICAE stationary subsets of P sub kappa lambda by n centerline f1 65 ( 2 0 0 ) g Yoshihiro A b eF open U N D parenthesis AM E NTA Yokohama closing parenthesis Abstract period We explore the possibility of forcing nonreflecting stationary sets of P sub kappa lambda n centerline f NonreflectingMATHEMATICAE stationary subsets of $ P f nkappa g nlambda $ g period 1 65 ( 2 0 0 ) We also present a P sub kappa lambda generalization of Kanamori quoteright s weakly normal filters comma n centerline fby g Nonreflecting stationary subsets of Pκλ which induces by stationary reflection period Yoshihiro A b e ( Yokohama ) n centerline1 period .. Introductionf Yoshihiro period A b .. e Throughout ( Yokohama .. this ) g .. paper .. kappa .. denotes .. a .. regular .. un hyphen Abstract . We explore the possibility of forcing nonreflecting stationary sets of Pκλ. countable cardinal and .... lambda a cardinal .... greater equal kappa period .... For any such pair .... open We also present a Pκλ generalization of Kanamori ' s weakly normal filters , which induces parenthesisn hspace ∗fn kappaf i l l commag Abstract lambda . closing We explore parenthesis the comma possibility P sub kappa of lambda forcing nonreflecting stationary sets of $ P f nkappa stationaryg nlambda reflection. $ denotes .... the .... set .... open1 . brace Introduction x subset lambda . Throughout : bar x bar less this kappa paper closingκ bracedenotes period .... a For .... x in P sub kappa lambdaregular comma un - .... let .... kappa sub x = bar x cap kappa bar comma nnoindentP sub kappaWe sub also x x = present open brace a s $ subset P f x : n barkappa s barg less nlambda kappa sub$ x closing generalization brace comma and of x-hatwideKanamori ' s weakly normal filters , which induces countable cardinal and λ a cardinal ≥ κ.
    [Show full text]
  • FUNCTIONS on STATIONARY SETS Mustapha Alami
    Palestine Journal of Mathematics Vol. 7(1)(2018) , 222226 © Palestine Polytechnic University-PPU 2018 FUNCTIONS ON STATIONARY SETS Mustapha Alami Communicated by Najib Mahdou MSC 2010 Classications: Primary: 03G05, 06A06. Secondary: 06E05, 08A05, 54G12. Keywords and phrases: Stationary sets, closed and unbounded sets, Fodor's theorem, combinatorial set theory. The author would like to thank the referees for their helpful remarks and comments. Abstract A characterization of stationary sets is established using regressive functions, se- lection property, continuous functions on ordinals and real continuous functions. 1 Introduction Whenever a number of pigeons, to be put into cages, is greater that the number of cages consid- ered for this purpose; one cage, at least, has to contain more than one pigeon. This self-evident principle inspired many mathematicians over time and has been a basis for many generaliza- tions indeed. The rst extension of this principle to ordinals dates back to P. Alexandroff and P. Uryshon (1926), see [1]:A regressive function f on limit ordinals (i.e., f(α) α) has a constant value on some uncountable set of ordinal numbers. Four years later, Ben Dushnik (1930), see [3], gave a more explicit generalization: Any regressive function on !ν+1 into it- self is constant on some set of size @ν+1. In 1950 P. Erdös extended Ben Dushnik result to any !ν of uncountable conality, see [4]. In the same year (1950) J. Novak, see [9], generalized Alexandroff-Uryshon's theorem to closed (under the order topology) and unbounded subsets of !1: Any regressive function on a club, closed and unbounded, C of !1 into itself is constant on some uncountable subset of C.
    [Show full text]
  • 8. Stationary Sets
    8. Stationary Sets In this chapter we develop the theory of closed unbounded and stationary subsets of a regular uncountable cardinal, and its generalizations. Closed Unbounded Sets If X is a set of ordinals and α>0 is a limit ordinal then α is a limit point of X if sup(X ∩ α)=α. Definition 8.1. Let κ be a regular uncountable cardinal. A set C ⊂ κ is a closed unbounded subset of κ if C is unbounded in κ and if it contains all its limit points less than κ. AsetS ⊂ κ is stationary if S∩C = ∅ for every closed unbounded subset C of κ. An unbounded set C ⊂ κ is closed if and only if for every sequence α0 <α1 <...<αξ <... (ξ<γ)ofelementsofC,oflengthγ<κ,wehave limξ→γ αξ ∈ C. Lemma 8.2. If C and D are closed unbounded, then C ∩ D is closed un- bounded. Proof. It is immediate that C∩D is closed. To show that C∩D is unbounded, let α<κ.SinceC is unbounded, there exists an α1 >αwith α1 ∈ C. Similarly there exists an α2 >α1 with α2 ∈ D. In this fashion, we construct an increasing sequence (8.1) α<α1 <α2 <...<αn <... such that α1,α3,α5,... ∈ C, α2,α4,α6,... ∈ D.Ifweletβ be the limit of the sequence (8.1), then β<κ,andβ ∈ C and β ∈ D. The collection of all closed unbounded subsets of κ has the finite inter- section property. The filter generated by the closed unbounded sets consists of all X ⊂ κ that contain a closed unbounded subset.
    [Show full text]
  • Mutually Stationary Sequences of Sets and the Non-Saturation of the Non-Stationary Ideal on Px(A)
    Acta Math., 186 (2001), 271-300 @ 2001 by Institut Mittag-Leflter. All rights reserved Mutually stationary sequences of sets and the non-saturation of the non-stationary ideal on Px(A) by MATTHEW FOREMAN and MENACHEM MAGIDOR Uniw~rsity of California Hebrew University Irvine, CA, U.S.A. Jerusalem, Israel 1. Introduction and preliminary remarks An important combinatorial property of an ideal I on a set Z is the saturation of the ideal, i.e. the least upper bound on the cardinality of a well-ordered chain in the completion of the Boolean algebra P(Z)/I. This is particularly interesting in the case where I is a naturally defined ideal, such as the non-stationary ideal. It is known to be consistent for the non-stationary ideal on wl to be w2-saturated. This was shown first from strong determinacy hypotheses by Steel and Van Wesep [SV], and later from large cardinals by Foreman, Magidor and Shelah [FMS]. Shelah has the optimal result, showing this property consistent relative to the existence of a Woodin cardinal. Shelah has shown that the non-stationary ideal on a successor cardinal •>wl can never be saturated, by showing that any saturated ideal on a successor cardinal must concentrate on a critical cofinality. Further, Gitik and Shelah (extending earlier work of Shelah) have shown that for x a successor of a singular cardinal, the non-stationary ideal cannot be x+-saturated even when restricted to the critical cofinality. They have also shown that the non-stationary ideal on an inaccessible cardinal can never be saturated.
    [Show full text]
  • The Failure of Diamond on a Reflecting Stationary Set
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 364, Number 4, April 2012, Pages 1771–1795 S 0002-9947(2011)05355-9 Article electronically published on November 17, 2011 THE FAILURE OF DIAMOND ON A REFLECTING STATIONARY SET MOTI GITIK AND ASSAF RINOT Abstract. 1. It is shown that the failure of ♦S ,forasetS ⊆ℵω+1 that reflects stationarily often, is consistent with GCH and APℵω ,relativetothe ∗ existence of a supercompact cardinal. By a theorem of Shelah, GCH and λ + entails ♦S for any S ⊆ λ that reflects stationarily often. 2. We establish the consistency of existence of a stationary subset of ω [ℵω+1] that cannot be thinned out to a stationary set on which the sup- function is injective. This answers a question of K¨onig, Larson and Yoshinobu in the negative. 3. We prove that the failure of a diamond-like principle introduced by Dˇzamonja and Shelah is equivalent to the failure of Shelah’s strong hypothesis. 0. Introduction 0.1. Background. Recall Jensen’s diamond principle [10]: for an infinite cardinal + λ and a stationary set S ⊆ λ , ♦S asserts the existence of a sequence Aδ | δ ∈ S + such that the set {δ ∈ S | A ∩ δ = Aδ} is stationary for all A ⊆ λ . λ + It is easy to see that ♦λ+ implies 2 = λ , and hence it is natural to ask whether the converse holds. Jensen proved that for λ = ℵ0, the inverse implication fails (see [2]). However, for λ>ℵ0, a recent theorem of Shelah [19] indeed establishes the λ + inverse implication, and moreover, it is proved that 2 = λ entails ♦S for every λ+ { + | } stationary S which is a subset of E=cf( λ) := α<λ cf(α) =cf(λ) .
    [Show full text]
  • Saturation of the Closed Unbounded Filter on the Set of Regular Cardinals by Thomas J
    TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETY Volume 292, Number 1, November 1985 SATURATION OF THE CLOSED UNBOUNDED FILTER ON THE SET OF REGULAR CARDINALS BY THOMAS J. JECH AND W. HUGH WOODIN1 ABSTRACT. For any a < k+ , the following are equiconsistent: (a) k, is measurable of order a, (b) k is a-Mahlo and the filter C[Reg] is saturated. Introduction. Let re he a regular uncountable cardinal. C is the filter over re generated by closed unbounded subsets of re. If S C re is a stationary set then C[5] = {C n S: C G C} is the restriction of C to S. By a result of Solovay [9], the filter C[5] is not /c-saturated for any stationary set S; i.e. every stationary set is the union of re disjoint stationary subsets. A natural question is whether the filter C can be /c+-saturated, or more generally, whether C[S] can be re+-saturated for some stationary set S. The filter C[S] is re+-saturated if there exists no collection of re+ stationary subsets of S such that any two of them have nonstationary intersection. To simplify the terminology, we call C[S] saturated instead of /c+-saturated. If C is saturated then re is a measurable cardinal in an inner model [3]; moreover, if re is a successor cardinal then considerably stronger properties of re can be deduced [4, 7]. In fact, if re is a successor cardinal and re > Ni, then C itself cannot be saturated [8]. If re is an inaccessible cardinal, let Sing and Reg denote, respectively, the set of all singular and regular cardinals a < re.
    [Show full text]
  • Category Forcings, Mm , and Generic Absoluteness For
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Institutional Research Information System University of Turin CATEGORY FORCINGS, MM+++, AND GENERIC ABSOLUTENESS FOR THE THEORY OF STRONG FORCING AXIOMS MATTEO VIALE Abstract. We analyze certain subfamilies of the category of complete boolean algebras with complete homomorphisms, families which are of particular interest in set theory. In particular we study the category whose objects are stationary set preserving, atomless com- plete boolean algebras and whose arrows are complete homomorphisms with a stationary set preserving quotient. We introduce a maximal forcing axiom MM+++ as a combinatorial property of this category. This forcing axiom strengthens Martin’s maximum and can be seen at the same time as a strenghtening of Baire’s category theorem and of the axiom of choice. Our main results show that MM+++ is consistent relative to large cardinal ax- ioms and that MM+++ makes the theory of the Chang model L([Ord]≤ℵ1 ) with parameters in P(!1) generically invariant for stationary set preserving forcings that preserve this ax- iom. We also show that our results give a close to optimal extension to the Chang model L([Ord]≤ℵ1 ) of Woodin’s generic absoluteness results for the Chang model L([Ord]@0 ) and give an a posteriori explanation of the success forcing axioms have met in set theory. The main objective of this paper is to show that there is a natural recursive extension T of ZFC+ large cardinals which gives a complete theory of the Chang model L([Ord]≤ℵ1 ) with respect to the unique efficient method to produce consistency results for this structure, i.e stationary set preserving forcings.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Structure of Stationary Sets
    Science in China Series A: Mathematics Jan., 2007, Vol. 50, No. 1, 1–? www.SciChina.com www.springerlink.com On the structure of stationary sets Qi FENG1,2†, Thomas JECH3 & Jindˇrich ZAPLETAL4 1 Institute of Mathematics, AMSS, Chinese Academy of Sciences, Beijing 100080, China (email: [email protected]); 2 Department of Mathematics, National University of Singapore, 2 Science Drive 2, Singapore 117543, Republic of Singapore (email: [email protected]); 3 Mathematical Institute, The Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic, Zitn´a25,ˇ 115 67 Praha 1, Czech Republic (email: [email protected]); 4 Department of Mathematics, University of Florida, Gainesville, FL 32611, USA (email: [email protected]) ω Abstract We isolate several classes of stationary sets of [κ] and investigate implications among them. Under a large cardinal assumption, we prove a structure theorem for stationary sets. Keywords: stationary set, projective stationary set, stationary reflection principles. MSC(2000): 03E40, 03E65 1 Introduction We investigate stationary sets in the space [κ]ω of countable subsets of an uncountable car- dinal. We concentrate on the following particular classes of stationary sets: full ր ց club → local club → reflective → projective stationary ց ր spanning Figure 1.1 In Figure 1.1, the → represents the implication. We show among others that under a suitable large cardinal assumption (e.g., under Martin’s Maximum), the diagram collapses to just two classes: club projective stationary local club −→ spanning full reflective Figure 1.2 Under the same large cardinal assumption, we prove a structure theorem for stationary sets: for every stationary set S there exists a stationary set A ⊂ ω1 such that S is spanning above A and nonstationary above ω1 − A.
    [Show full text]
  • June 23, 2010 RAMSEY-LIKE CARDINALS
    June 23, 2010 RAMSEY-LIKE CARDINALS VICTORIA GITMAN Abstract. One of the numerous characterizations of a Ramsey cardinal κ involves the existence of certain types of elementary embeddings for transitive sets of size κ satisfying a large fragment of ZFC. I introduce new large cardinal axioms generalizing the Ramsey elementary embeddings characterization and show that they form a natural hierarchy between weakly compact cardinals and measurable cardinals. These new axioms serve to further our knowledge about the elementary embedding properties of smaller large cardinals, in particular those still consistent with V = L. 1. Introduction Most large cardinals, including measurable cardinals and stronger notions, are defined in terms of the existence of elementary embeddings with that cardinal as the critical point. Several smaller large cardinals, such as weakly compact, indescrib- able, and Ramsey cardinals, have definitions in terms of elementary embeddings, but are more widely known for their other properties (combinatorial, reflecting, etc.). Other smaller large cardinals, such as ineffable and subtle cardinals, have no known elementary embedding characterizations. I will investigate the elementary embedding characterization of Ramsey cardinals and introduce new large cardinal axioms by generalizing the Ramsey embeddings. By placing these new large cardi- nals within the existing hierarchy, I try to shed light on the variety of elementary embedding properties that are possible for smaller large cardinals. In a forthcom- ing paper with Thomas Johnstone [GJ10], we use the new large cardinals to obtain some basic indestructibility results for Ramsey cardinals through the techniques of lifting embeddings. I hope that this project will motivate set theorists who work with smaller large cardinals to focus on investigating their elementary embedding properties.
    [Show full text]
  • On Reflection of Stationary Sets
    F U N D AM E NTA nnoindentMATHEMATICAEF U N D AM E NTA 1 40 open parenthesis 1 9 9 2 closing parenthesis nnoindentOn reflectionMATHEMATICAE of stationary sets by n centerlineQi .. F e nf g1 .. 40 open ( parenthesis 1 9 9 2 ) Singaporeg closing parenthesis .. and .. Menachem .. M a g i d o r .. open parenthesis JerusalemF U N closing D AM E parenthesis NTA n centerlineAbstract periodfOnMATHEMATICAE .. reflection We show that of there stationary are stationary sets subsetsg of uncountable spaces which do not reflect period 1 40 ( 1 9 9 2 ) n centerlineS 0 period ..fby Thereg are many usefulOn and interestingreflection stationary of stationary reflection setsprinci hyphen ples formulated and studied in the current research concerningby new existence n centerlineaxioms of setfQiQi theorynquad F and e nF combinatorial g e n( Singapore g nquad aspects )( Singapore ofand infinityMenachem period ) nquad Mand a gn iquad d o rMenachem( Jerusalemnquad ) M a g i d o r nquad ( Jerusalem ) g Notably comma oneAbstract of the first . reflectionWe show principles that there studied are stationary i s the following subsets of : uncountable spaces which Abstractopen parenthesis . nquaddo A notWe closing reflect show parenthesis . that there .... If kappa are stationary greater equal aleph subsets sub 2 of .... uncountable is regular comma spaces S subset which equaldo not kappa reflect is stationaryx .0 . commaThere .... then are theremany is useful some and alpha interesting less kappa stationary reflection princi - ples such that S capformulated alpha is stationary and studied in alpha in the period current research concerning new existence nS Then0 . manynquad stationaryThereaxioms ofare reflection set many theory principles useful and combinatorial of and the following interesting aspects form of have infinity stationary .
    [Show full text]