<<

Personhood and (Non-) Natural A Philosophical Journey Towards A Conceptual Normative Structure of Personhood

Christiaan van der Does de Willebois 10579907

ABSTRACT Master thesis Philosophy Summer 2015 Graduate School of Humanities, University of Amsterdam Coordinator: Jacques Bos Second reader: Thomas Nys

MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Overview Acknowledgements Introduction

Chapter 1 An Example of Non-Natural Personhood Section 1.1 Legal Personhood Section 1.2 Moral Personhood Section 1.3 The History of the Corporate Personhood Section 1.4 The Merging of Legal Personhood and Moral Personhood: the Section 1.5 Corporate Moral Personhood: Should It Be? A. Arguments against Corporate Moral Personhood B. Arguments for Corporate Moral Personhood Section 1.6 Conclusions

Chapter 2 Philosophical Theory: Moral Personhood Section 2.1 Three Account of Moral Personhood Section 2.1.1 Ontological Account Section 2.1.2 Subjective Account Section 2.1.3 Objective Account Section 2.2 Conclusions

Chapter 3 A Normative Structure Section 3.1 The Three Accounts of Moral Personhood and their Consequences Section 3.2 A Fourth Account: The Political-Natural Account A. A Moral Interpretation: Natural Moral Personhood B. Consequential Interpretation: Consequential Moral Personhood Section 3.3 The Consequences of the Moral Personhood Accounts and Fundamental Rights Section 3.4 Fundamental Rights Distinctions Section 3.5 A Hierarchy of Fundamental Rights Section 3.6 Conclusions

Chapter 4 Conclusions

2 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Jacques Bos for all help given and positive feedback during the past half year that I wrote this thesis.

3 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Introduction

Non-natural persons are “hip” nowadays. Advocates of , animals, and even plants, have tried to assure that these non-natural objects are granted personhood-status. Along with the personhood-status comes a package of rights, even fundamental rights. However, until now, only one non-natural object has succeeded in becoming a in the eyes of the law: the corporation.

To give an example, in Citizens United v. Federal Elections Commission (FEC), the U.S. Supreme Court granted corporations the fundamental right of free speech in a case that had nothing to do with free speech. Citizens United sued the FEC, reasoning that, as campaign donations are a protected form of speech, the government cannot bind a corporation’s independent political contributions. As corporations and natural persons are both seen as legal persons, also corporations should be granted the freedom of speech; they should be able to freely choose, both for and to, the cause they wish to donate. The Supreme Court agreed; because political speech is a form of speech, corporations were granted a version of freedom of speech. The Citizens United case came at the height of the equality battle between corporations (or non-natural persons) and natural persons. This battle is known as the corporate personhood (CP) debate:

In the eyes of the law, the business corporation is a person. So, for example, the corporation can own property in its own right; it can sue or be sued, in contract or tort or any number of other causes of action; it can be prosecuted and punished for criminal activity; it enjoys various rights under the United States Constitution; and it is subject to tax liability. In these respects (and others), the corporation bears the legal attributes of an entity existing separately from the various natural persons who participate or have an interest in the corporation’s activities. (Millon, 2001, p. 1)

The concept of CP is exemplary for the rise of non-natural persons in contemporary times. In the United States, the notion of personhood is used as a way to claim (fundamental) rights. This implicates that, as natural persons have natural personhood and therefore certain rights, corporations should have certain rights as well, in the form of CP. The corporation will be held as an example for the rise of the non-natural person in this thesis.

Human rights, fundamental rights, and constitutional rights are used in essentially the same way: to prevent any infringements to these rights and to capacitate (natural) persons to act in society. These rights have a strong ethical footing. They are not just about biological human

4 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 beings, but also about something more. Most authors on human rights say that one has to be a “moral person” in order to have fundamental rights. This personhood-approach could be divided into multiple accounts. The classic approach bases moral personhood on humanity or human dignity. For example, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) and the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR) take this approach. Other scholars say that the essence of a person is derived from certain characteristics that one possesses, such as intentionality, sentience, or language. Some academics argue that a moral person is defined through actions and deeds with others in society. The fact that these human, fundamental, or constitutional rights are essentially meant for natural persons makes abstract the idea of granting these rights to “anyone or anything” other than natural persons, for example, to non-natural persons such as corporations, aliens, artificial intelligence (AI), robots, animals, and even plants.

There is a history behind the rise of non-natural personhood. Since corporations were the first non-natural persons, they will be held as the model in order to grasp this concept better. A fair question to ask would be, for example, if it is possible to become a citizen as a corporation. Other issues needing answers are how it is possible that corporations have moral personhood, and therefore, fundamental rights. If non-natural personhood has already resulted in corporations gaining fundamental rights, then one wonders what that means for our future. It needs to be determined if there are limits to the rights of non-natural persons or if they will eventually be fully equated to natural persons, in the sense that they can also be granted the right to life. We need to be concerned where those boundaries are drawn. In this thesis, all these questions and issues will be answered.

The main question of this thesis is: In what respect should non-natural persons and animals be equal to natural persons?

There are four sub-questions. 1) What is a person, and how did non-natural persons gain personhood-status? 2) What are the leading accounts of moral personhood? 3) Could we construct a normative conceptual structure to analyse personhood? 4) What are the implications of this normative conceptual structure for the hierarchy of fundamental rights?

5 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Outline

First, the Citizens United case will be used as the example of a non-natural person that has been ascribed fundamental rights. In the first chapter, the origins of personhood will be discussed; and, the historical development leading to corporate personhood will be examined. Also, the arguments pro and contra of the ascription of fundamental rights to non-natural persons will be addressed.

In the second chapter, the three main accounts of moral personhood will be discussed. Moral personhood is leading in the attribution of fundamental rights to natural persons, and it is moral personhood-status that non-natural persons pursue. Defining moral personhood will be key to understanding the current personhood debate. Furthermore, it will help in the development of a conceptual normative framework that merges the three accounts of moral personhood into one: the political-natural account of moral personhood. This will be discussed to a greater extent in chapter three.

Because there is a lack of normative personhood theories, this thesis is important, as it will develop such a framework. After elaborating on personhood and defining the limits of legal and moral personhood, the next step will show the legal implications of such a theory. In order to do so, it is necessary to first look at the underlying value of fundamental rights. After defining this underlying value, it will become clearer what steps should be taken to show the boundaries of non-natural personhood and the attribution of fundamental rights.

The corporation will be held exemplary for the non-natural person. This thesis, and the normative framework that is proposed here, is suitable for all non-natural persons, even if they come from Pluto, or are of the animal species. Having defined this framework, it will demonstrate why corporations should have a form of moral personhood.

Terminology

In this thesis I will refer to natural persons, non-natural persons, and animals. Humans, in this thesis, are seen as natural persons. A natural person is anyone who, based on humanity and human dignity, is a living human being. Under non-natural persons are only artificial persons, such as corporations, artificial intelligence, and robots. Animals are not (yet) persons in the eyes of the law; however, they do have certain moral rights.

6 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Mainly fundamental rights will be referenced to in this thesis; which includes also human rights and constitutional rights. There are two reasons that fundamental rights are used as an umbrella concept. First, “human rights” is a very confusing term in relation to anything that is not natural or human. Second, “constitutional rights” is, for many people, too vague of an expression, as it does not define exactly what is constitutional and non-constitutional; it is impossible to determine where the dynamic line is drawn. Therefore, the concept of fundamental rights is used here, as it has an exact and limited content: the most essential rights to persons.

For purposes of clarification, the idea of the construction of the normative framework is not meant to be all encompassing or exhaustive. It is merely to sketch the lines of thought along which the theory could be coloured in.

7 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Chapter 1 An Example of Non-Natural Personhood

The subject of this chapter is the corporation, a non-natural person that has been granted personhood. This chapter will first introduce three different notions of personhood: natural, moral, and legal. Second, it will provide an overview of the development of the first non- natural person in history that has claimed fundamental rights: the corporation. Third, arguments pro and contra corporate personhood will be discussed.

Three different sorts of persons can be distinguished: natural, moral, and legal. Every natural person is moral and legal, but not every is a moral and, therefore, natural person. For example, corporations are legal persons. They have rights and responsibilities and can sue and be sued; however, they are not moral or natural persons. Corporations are non-natural (artificial) persons, and are primarily created for the benefit of natural persons. Similarly, humans, as natural persons, are usually also considered as legal persons.

Section 1.1 Legal Personhood

The classical discussion of the idea of legal personhood is found in John Chipman Gray’s The Nature and Sources of the Law. He formulated it as follows: “In books of the Law, as in other books, and in common speech, ‘person’ is often used as meaning a human being, but the technical legal meaning of a ‘person’ is a subject of legal rights and duties” (Gray, 1921, p. 27). “The question whether an entity should be considered a legal person can be reduced to other questions about whether or not the entity can and should be made the subject of a set of legal rights and duties” (Solum, 2015). The set of rights and duties that come with legal personhood differs from the kind of person it is ascribed to; for a non-natural person, such as a corporation, it will be different than for a natural person. However, in general, it can be said that legal personhood minimally consists of the right to sue and to be sued in court and the right to own property (Ripken, 2010, pp. 101-102; Solum, 2015). Over the course of history, many different things have possessed legal rights, from temples in Rome to Church buildings, and even to ships. The City of London, for example, has had legal personhood since the 12th Century (London, 2015; Robinson, 1936, p. 719). In present times, the most famous non- natural person is the corporation (Gray, 1921; Cline, 2010, p. 10). Legal personhood implies that one has certain rights and duties; however, this does not directly imply that fundamental rights are also included. Until the Citizens United case, only natural persons were granted fundamental rights. In order to be ascribed fundamental rights, one had to be a moral person, next to being a legal person. Therefore, a more in depth definition of moral person needs to be examined and stated.

8 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Section 1.2 Moral Personhood

While legal personhood is already slightly controversial, moral personhood is “one of the most contested ideas in contemporary legal, moral, and political theory” (Solum, 2015). One of the critical problems is how to define a moral person: are there some specific criteria that can be used? Can humanity be defined in terms of a set of traits, and can we then try to apply these criteria to non-natural persons? Examples of possible criteria are as follows: intelligence, consciousness, intentionality, autonomy, language, or self-awareness (Solum, 2015). The question then arises of when someone is fully human. Also, is it possible to be “half” human when one does not possess all these traits? It is evident that this is a very difficult and complex discussion. The topic of moral personhood will be discussed to a greater extent in Chapter 2.

Section 1.3 The History of Corporate Personhood

The original idea of a corporation was to create a fictional “person” that could be recognized by the law and exists in eternity, according to the famous English jurist William Blackstone.

It has been found necessary, when it is for the advantage of the public to constitute artificial persons, who may maintain a perpetual succession, and enjoy a kind of legal immortality. These artificial persons are called bodies politic, bodies corporate, corpora corporata or corporations: of which there is a great variety subsisting, for the advancement of religion, of learning, and of commerce; in order to preserve entire and for ever those rights and immunities, which, if they were granted only to those individuals of which the body corporate is composed, would upon their death be utterly lost and extinct. (Blackstone, 1756, p. 455)

The corporation as a concept has been developed for some time, as the earliest traces can be found in Roman history (Risk Encyclopedia). However, the origins of the for-profit corporation, as we currently know it, are found at the start of the 17th century when the idea of limited liability surfaced. The first limited liability corporations were the British East-India Company and the Dutch East-India Company, founded respectively in 1600 and 1602. Since the Americas were discovered in 1492 by Christopher Columbus, vessels hopped on and off across the ocean to trade slaves, cotton, and more. It was the British who reigned over the seas after they defeated the Dutch Republic at sea in the Four War. This happened over the course of the 17th and 18th centuries (Boxer, 1974; Hainsworth, 1998). In those times, various European countries were colonizing the world. At the end of the 18th century, independence

9 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 wars were booming, starting in America with the American Revolution in 1775. Corporations were used as ways to deal weapons and privately fund wars (Ferguson, 2008, pp. 20-80). The people of North America saw corporations as tools of oppression by the King of England. Before the United States Constitution, the King gave corporations specific monopolies in the form of charters for a limited amount of time. This was done with the purpose of exploiting the “New World” and moving wealth back into the “Old World.” The King’s agents for the joint-stock corporations had plenty of autonomy to do their work in the 17th and 18th century; they could pass laws, levy taxes, and raise armies to manage and control property and commerce. However, these corporation owners were not popular with the colonists. Therefore, when the founding fathers drafted the United States Constitution in 1787, they wanted to be free of the influences of the English King (Bruns, 1986, p. 33). A chief aim of the Constitution was to create a government with enough power to act on a national level, but without so much power that fundamental rights would be at risk. One way in which this was accomplished was to separate the powers of government into three branches, and then include checks and balances on those powers to assure that no one branch of government gained supremacy. This concern arose largely out of the experience that the delegates had with the King of England and his powerful Parliament. The powers of each branch are enumerated in the Constitution, with powers not assigned to them reserved for the states (The White House). The founding fathers left the control of corporations to state legislatures1 where they would receive the closest supervision by the people (The National Constitution Center). Early corporate charters were very explicit about the limitations of a corporation. Most importantly, the corporations had to represent a clear benefit for the public good, such as building a road, canal, or bridge. In the event that corporations violated any of these terms, their charters were revoked by the state legislatures. During and after the Civil War, there was a rapid increase in the number and size of corporations, with this form of business starting to become an increasingly important way of holding and protecting property (Hammond, 1991, pp. 580-594). At that time, corporations had more rights than women and slaves, which caused great frustration among the population.

As time passed and memories of royal oppression faded, wealthy people increasingly started eyeing corporations as a convenient way to shield their personal fortunes; the benefits of the

1 The 10th Amendment was included in the Bill of Rights to further define the balance of power between the federal government and the states. The amendment says that the federal government has only those powers specifically granted by the Constitution. These powers include the power to declare war, to collect taxes, to regulate interstate business activities and others that are listed in the articles. Any power not listed, says the 10th Amendment, is left to the states or the people. Although the 10th Amendment does not specify what these “powers” may be, the U.S. Supreme Court has ruled that laws affecting family relations (such as marriage, divorce, and adoption), commerce that occurs within a state’s own borders, and local law enforcement activities, are among those specifically reserved to the states or the people.

10 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 limited-liability corporation were increasingly being discovered. States saw the rise of the limited liability corporation and the amount of money it generated. In order to attract more businesses, state legislatures increased corporate charter length while, at the same time, they decreased corporate liability and reduced citizen authority over corporate structure, governance, production, and labour. This meant that corporations were not limited by time anymore while gaining more rights. As corporations acquired more rights, other inhabitants of the United States also started to claim more rights. Next to men, women and slaves were also publicly protesting for the attribution of these rights. States gradually started loosening property requirements for voting, so more and more men could participate in the political process. Women were publicly protesting for the right to vote. In 1865, the 13th Amendment was ratified, freeing the slaves (Davis, 2015). A few years later, the 14th Amendment provided citizenship rights to all persons born or naturalized in the United States; and two years after that, the 15th Amendment provided voting rights to black males (Turner, Giacopassi, & Vandiver, 2006, pp. 181-195).

Because corporations were a creation of the government—chartered by the state legislatures—they had duties to which they were held accountable.2 While dealing with these duties, corporations wanted more rights so that they could expand their businesses even further. The corporation’s tool to realize this was the 14th Amendment that was ratified in 1868 (Paul vs. Virginia, 1868). The 14th Amendment, in addition to stating that all persons born or naturalized in the US are citizens, says that no state shall “deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without the due process of law; nor deny to any person . . . the equal protection of the laws.”3 The phrase about not depriving any person of life, liberty, or property without the due process of the law is exactly the same wording as the 5th Amendment, which protects people from that kind of abuse by the federal government. In the 14th Amendment, the states cannot abuse people in that way, either. These are important rights; they were written in a short, straightforward manner; and, after the Civil War and all the agony over slavery, it was clear to the people in the states that ratified the 13th, 14th, and

2 Abraham Lincoln, in a Nov. 21, 1864 letter to Col. William F. Elkins, warned that “I see in the near future a crisis approaching that unnerves me and causes me to tremble for the safety of my country. As a result of the war, corporations have been enthroned and an era of corruption in high places will follow, and the money power of the country will endeavor to prolong its reign by working upon the prejudices of the people until all wealth is aggregated in a few hands and the Republic is destroyed.” 3 The 14th Amendment contained three new limits on state power: a state shall not violate a citizen’s privileges or immunities; shall not deprive any person of life, liberty, or property without due process of law; and must guarantee all persons equal protection of the laws. These limitations on state power dramatically expanded the protections of the Constitution. Prior to the adoption of the 14th Amendment, the protections in the Bill of Rights limited only the actions of the federal government, unless the provision specifically stated otherwise. The Supreme Court, in what is called “the doctrine of incorporation” has since interpreted the Fourteenth Amendment to apply most provisions in the Bill of Rights against state and local governments as well. This has meant that the 14th Amendment has been used more frequently in modern court cases than any other constitutional provision. Guaranteed Rights of Citizenship to all Persons Born or Naturalized: The right of citizenship in the 14th Amendment was intended to overturn the case of Dred Scott v. Sanford, a decision that had long been considered as one of the Supreme Court’s worst mistakes. Dred Scott, born into slavery, argued that he should be granted freedom from the family that claimed ownership over him because he had lived in free states and, thus, had become a citizen of the United States before returning to Missouri, a state where slavery was sanctioned (Monk, 2003).

11 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

15th Amendments, that these were about righting the wrongs of slavery (Nelson, 1988, p. 4; The National Archives, 2012). By this time, over 100,000 corporations operated in the US. This far exceeded the number of corporations created in any other country during that time. The United States thus became what might be called the first corporation nation (Hall, 2000).

As the rights to due process and equal protection were so valuable, the definition of the word “person” in the 14th Amendment became the focus of hundreds of legal battles for the next twenty years. The watershed moment came in 1886, when the Supreme Court ruled on a case called Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific Railroad. The case itself was not about corporate personhood, although many before had been and the Court had ruled that corporations were not persons under the 14th Amendment. The Santa Clara case was, like many railroad cases, about taxes. But before the Court delivered its decision, the following statement was delivered by Chief Justice Waite: “The court does not wish to hear argument on the question whether the provision in the 14th Amendment to the Constitution, which forbids a State to deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws, applies to these corporations. We are all of the opinion that it does” (Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific Railroad , 1886). The statement appeared in the header of the case in the published version, while the Court made its ruling on other grounds. How this statement appeared in the header of the case is a matter of some mystery and competing theories; but because it was later cited as precedence, corporate personhood became the accepted legal doctrine of the land.

In 1976, in Buckley v. Valeo, the Supreme Court determined that spending money for political purposes was equal to exercising free speech; and, since “corporate persons” have First Amendment rights, they can basically contribute as much money as they want to political parties and candidates (Buckley vs. Valeo, 1976). Another landmark case, First National Bank of Boston v. Belotti, reaffirmed the Santa Clara doctrine in 1978. This case was used to justify granting corporations the First Amendment right to spend unlimited corporate funds on ballot initiatives. This jurisprudence laid the foundations for an important case in 2010 that continued the steady rise of corporate personhood. This was the Citizens United v. FEC case. Citizens United sued the FEC, arguing that, because people’s campaign donations are a protected form of speech (as was previously determined in Buckley v. Valeo) and corporations and people enjoy the same legal rights, the government cannot limit a corporation’s independent political donations. The Supreme Court agreed. In Citizens United, the Court integrated the “money is speech” concept from Buckley with the “furthering free and open debate” consideration of Bellotti that paved the way to unlimited corporate money for political parties in election time (Hager & Leas, 2012; Mayer, 1990).

12 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

The Citizens United ruling may be the most sweeping expansion of corporate personhood to date, but it was not the last vital case for the development of the CP-doctrine. Another important case was tried before the Supreme Court in 2014. In the Burwell v. Hobby Lobby case, the owners of the Hobby Lobby stores claimed that their personal religious beliefs would be under intrusion if they were required to provide certain forms of birth control coverage to employees. Hobby Lobby’s owners wanted the court to recognize their own beliefs on birth control, but they also wanted to keep the protections of the corporate form for everything else, including limited liability. The Supreme Court granted this, making it the first time that the court accepted a corporation’s claim to religious beliefs. However, it is limited to closely held corporations. These are corporations that have a limited amount of shareholders, and their stocks are publicly traded on occasion, but not on a regular basis (Haberkorn & Gerstein, 2014; Investopedia).

Section 1.4 The Merging of Legal Personhood and Moral Personhood: the Corporation

The historical development of the CP doctrine has been described. The legal development of it can be narrowed down to three concepts over the past ages. Discussed above were the differences between legal personhood and moral personhood. In this section, it will be investigated how the U.S. Supreme Court merged both definitions to one, over time. First, the corporation was seen as “an Artificial and Dependent Person.” Personhood was only attributed to a non-natural entity because of the benefits it had for the economy, as it could be used as a legal vehicle to govern wealth, and engage in legal relationships. The corporation could, as a result, enter into contracts, hold property, sue and be sued, and ultimately, transact business in the corporate name. The artificial person theory is thus constituted in two separate elements: (1) a fictional aspect, and (2) a dependence aspect (i.e., the dependence on the law for its legal personality). The fictional aspect means that natural persons created the corporation; it is their invention (Nesteruk, 1990, pp. 543, 564; Schall, 2006, pp. 105, 118). Chief Justice Waite’s statement made this clear in Trustees of Dartmouth College v. Woodward: “A corporation is an artificial being, invisible, intangible, and existing only in contemplation of law. Being the mere creature of law, it possesses only those properties which the charter of its creation confers upon it” (Trustees of Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 1819). Ripken describes the second aspect as that, “the corporation is artificial, fictional, and conditional because it cannot come into being unless and until the law sanctions it” (Ripken, 2010, p. 107). This theory was leading in American legal thinking during the first half of the 19th century (Bratton Jr., 1989, pp. 407, 434). After that, the corporation further developed. The second stage was that the corporation was viewed as an Aggregate Person. This was based on the fact that the corporation is, in fact, the

13 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 aggregate, the collective of the natural persons acting under a single name for a mutual benefit (Hessen, 1979, p. 22). The entity is “owned, managed, and administered by people, [and] its so called actions are but manifestations of actions by real persons” (Cressey, 1989, pp. 31, 36). According to this idea, “the rights and duties of an incorporated association are in reality the rights and duties of the persons who compose it, and not of an imaginary being” (Young, 1912/2014, p. 113). The U.S. Supreme Court indirectly based its view on this theory in Santa Clara v. Southern Pacific Railroad, when it declared that a corporation is a person for purposes of the Fourteenth Amendment and, therefore, its property cannot be taxed in a different way as the property of individuals (Ripken, 2010, pp. 110-113; Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific Railroad , 1886). Eventually, the Courts could not uphold the Aggregate theory anymore as it was out-dated, and they had to find a solution. The third stage saw the realization of the concept of the corporation as a Real and Independent Person. This is the view that is still supported today. It is a complete, “living” entity that has a place in society. “The large corporation is simply a natural outgrowth of the economic tendency toward business combination” (Ripken, 2010, p. 113); and it has developed into such a strong entity that the law has granted it official recognition (Geldart, 1911, pp. 90-96). The real entity theory sees corporations as something distinct from the humans that collaborate under its roof. Its (perpetual) existence and identity is not dependent on its shareholders (French P. , 1984, pp. 19-30). Under this view, a corporation can have its own will and intentions, and can pursue its own goals, distinct from the will and goals of each individual member. One might say that this leads to a “collective consciousness, intentions or will” (Ripken, 2000, pp. 790-799).

As such, there are now two ways of viewing the corporate personhood in terms of fundamental rights. The first way is to view the corporation as a real and natural entity, similar to a natural person. In this view, the corporation should be granted the same rights and privileges as natural persons. The second way is a more public-oriented view. If a corporation is regarded as a real person in society, it should be granted the same rights as natural persons. This also implies, however, that it has moral and social responsibilities. Being a citizen, and part of a larger community, it should act like this (Nesteruk & Risser, 1993, p. 77). The law is there to regulate corporations to use their power, not only to maximize profits, but also to help society move forward. This view is in support of a of corporations (Ripken, 2010, p. 116).

14 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Section 1.5 Corporate Moral Personhood: Should It Be?

Different accounts have served as bases for ascribing rights to non-natural persons, such as corporations, and will be described in more detail. This will begin by examining the arguments, for and against Corporate Moral Personhood, which have been explained very well by, among others, Susanna Ripken (Ripken, 2010; Millon, 2001; French P. A., 1979). All the arguments given are sec, so without directly concluding anything. An opinion on these arguments will be given later.

A. Arguments Against Corporate Moral Personhood

First, attributing moral blame to a corporation does not make sense, as one could similarly blame a mug, a book, or a couch. It is not the corporation that does the wrong, it is the individuals behind the corporation (Garettt, 1989, pp. 535-544). Thus, only the individuals should be held morally accountable for actions taken in the name of a corporation. Second, moral personhood desires a minimal level of autonomy. Someone can only be held morally responsible if that person has autonomous control of the body (Spicker, 1970). The argument then is as follows: as corporation do not have autonomous control over their bodies, and thus their actions, they cannot be held morally responsible for their actions (Wolgast, 1992, pp. 64-65). Similarly, this argument can be applied to another “human” attribute: intentionality. Moral responsibility means that a person must act intentionally in order to be blamed. However, in corporations it are the humans behind it who steer their actions (May, 1983, pp. 69-71). To give a comparison, when the Titanic sunk, it was the captain who was responsible for the navigation, not the ship itself. It is then also incorrect to speak of the goals and intentions of a corporation, as these are the combined goals and intentions of the natural persons behind the body. This form of individualism means that a corporation’s actions, whether good or bad, can be traced back to the humans within the corporation. As corporation cannot have the same experiences such as these, they cannot be seen as moral persons; and, therefore, cannot be held accountable for their actions (Donaldson, 2013). Third, a related argument is to say that corporations simply cannot be categorized as moral persons because of their constitution. John Ladd thinks corporate organizations are more “like machines” than like persons, and “it would be a category mistake to expect a machine to comply with the principles of morality” (Ladd, 1970, pp. 488-500). The reason for this is that corporations are only “alive” in so far as they act as a vehicle to maximize profits, or to achieve certain goals. As this is what they were made to do, they should also be evaluated in the same way. “[A]ny considerations that are not related to the aims or goals of the organization are automatically excluded as irrelevant to the organizational decision-making

15 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 process” (Ladd, 1970, p. 496). A corporation is like a machine, unable to understand moral language and, thus, it cannot take into account moral considerations while making a decision “to be honest, courageous, considerate, sympathetic, or to have any kind of moral integrity. Such concepts are not in the vocabulary, so to speak, of the organizational language-game” (Ladd, 1970, p. 499) For example, actions such as “[s]ecrecy, espionage and deception do not make organizational action wrong; rather they are right, proper and, indeed, rational, if they serve the objectives of the organization” (Ladd, 1970, p. 500). Fourth, another difficulty is that if corporations are granted moral personhood, that implies that they have moral rights in addition to their moral responsibilities. To tackle this dilemma, use is made of Kant’s categorical imperative: we should treat all human beings as an end in themselves and never as a means to another end (Kant, 1785/1948). Corporations are the inventions of humans, formed as a means to achieve the end of those human beings that chose to participate in them (Ripken, 2010, pp. 122-123). If corporations are regarded as equal to humans, then corporations have the same moral rights and, therefore, the right to be treated as an end in themselves. This would lead to odd consequences. Corporations could not file bankruptcy anymore, as this would be equal to murder, and a merger would be a form of suicide (Pfeiffer, 1988, pp. 69-75). Some argue, like Ladd, that moral personhood should not be extended to corporations in order to avoid such results. Corporations should be seen as creations serving only human ends. An alternative for this is to say that corporations can be seen as moral persons, and therefore, have certain moral rights; however, this would be only for serving a particular purpose in law. Others say, that as corporations are not regarded as autonomous persons in the Kantian sense, ends instead of means, they cannot claim full moral personhood-status. As such, we can only treat them as moral subjects for some purposes, but not for others.

B. Arguments in Favour of Corporate Moral Personhood

First, intentionality and the ability to act are often seen as important criteria for moral personhood. There are philosophers that believe that corporations are capable of intentional action, and thus, can be regarded as moral persons. These philosophers emphasize that corporate actions and intentions cannot be reduced to the persons behind the corporation (Risser, 1978, pp. 23-28; French P. A., 1979). The collective nature of the corporation is what transforms the intentions of the natural persons into a collective one of the corporation itself (Wilson, 1992, pp. 74-75). Moral responsibility, therefore, falls upon all the individual members of the corporation itself. Not just on one, as that would be unfair. This is where corporate criminal liability comes into play, as it would otherwise be impossible to identify the individual wrongdoers and to punish them. The individuals behind the corporations are

16 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 shielded from persecution, as they all had something to do with the action, but it cannot directly be retraced to the individuals themselves. In these sorts of situations, the corporation should be morally responsible for the policies and practices that provide the environment in which individual actions are likely to combine to cause harm (Werhane, 1989, pp. 821-822). Second, as a corporation can act apart from its individual constituents, it also has its own intentions, that is to say, “a deliberate disposition to do something in a certain manner or to realize a state of affairs” (Werhane, 1989). This corporate intent has to be distinguished from the individual intention of the individuals behind the corporation. It is the collective nature of the corporation’s decision-making system that turns the total individual input into one final corporate output. Peter French has argued that intentionality should be seen as the sufficient and necessary condition for moral personhood (French P. A., 1979). He posits that corporate intentionality can be traced to the corporation’s internal decision structure (CID structure). This structure has two elements: (1) an organizational flowchart outlining the different levels within the corporate hierarchy, and (2) corporate rules that are generally established in corporate policy (French P. A., 1979). If the corporation wants to act, it should first discuss what action should be undertaken, and whether this action is appropriate and feasible. The CID structure collects the individual inputs within the corporate hierarchy, contemplates upon them, and then engages in a decision-making and ratification process. “When operative and properly activated, the CID Structure accomplishes a subordination and synthesis of the intentions and acts of various biological persons into a corporate decision” (French P. A., 1979). This all enforces the CID structure and enables the corporation to act intentionally. According to French, corporations are, therefore, intentional actors capable of moral personhood and exist as “full-fledged moral persons” with all the rights, privileges, and duties that such status implies” (French P. A., 1986, p. 37). Third, an alternative approach is to see what specific qualities a natural moral person has, and then try to project these on corporations to see whether they have similar features (Hindriks, 2013, pp. 5-6). Kenneth Goodpaster and John Matthews claim that two essential traits that characterize the morally responsible person are rationality (the capacity of rational decision- making) and respect (the awareness of the effects of one’s decisions on others) (Goodpaster & Matthews Jr., 1982). As corporations are capable of assembling information regarding the impact of their actions on others, and capable of using this information to make decisions, corporations display both rationality and respect; thus, they must be seen as moral persons (Goodpaster & Matthews Jr., 1982, pp. 134-135). Some say that corporations could be even more capable of rational action than natural persons, as they do not have emotions, consciousness, or sentience that influence their decision-making processes. This relates to the idea that corporations “can and should have access to practical and theoretical knowledge which dwarfs that of individuals,” and, therefore, corporations “must have, in addition to

17 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 good intentions, superhuman intelligence” (Donaldson, 2013, p. 125). With this view in mind, corporations should be held to even higher moral standards than human beings when they fail to utilize such intelligence in morally appropriate ways.

Section 1.6 Conclusions

The fact that corporations are seen as a Real and Independent Person seems to be a bizarre outcome of the legal debate. Due to this, corporations were granted fundamental rights in the United States. It is an oxymoron; fundamental rights and corporations do not seem to go together. However, the U.S. Court sees it as a fact that moral personhood can be ascribed to corporations, as they apparently can have their own will and intention. Not only are corporations seen as real persons, they can also be seen as a citizen of a particular state, if mostly this is of use for tax purposes (Forbes, 2014). It seems that it is only a matter of time before non-natural persons become even more anthropocentric. The question remaining is how far we are willing to go in making them even more natural. In the next chapters, this topic will be discussed.

18 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Chapter 2 Philosophical Theory: Moral Personhood

After examining the legal background of corporate personhood as a form of non-natural personhood, the philosophical dimensions of moral personhood will now be explored.

Moral personhood is one of the most contested ideas in contemporary legal, moral, and political theory (Solum, 2015). This is the case because it implies a certain standard: what it means to be a person. Is there a special set of criteria that must be met in order for one to be correctly called a “person”? Are all humans persons? Or, can it be that some humans are not persons? What about non-human beings? Can something non-human be categorized as a moral person? All of these questions aim at discovering the nature of personhood and determining the kinds of entities that can properly be considered moral persons. When addressing these questions, however, the answers uncovered may vary according to the way one defines “personhood.”

Section 2.1 Three Different Accounts of Moral Personhood

This section focuses on diverse aspects of moral personhood. It will discuss three different accounts of moral personhood, which are the ontological, subjective, and objective accounts. The original idea for these three accounts is derived from Elisa Aalthola’s paper Personhood and Animals: Three Approaches (Aalthola, 2008).

Section 2.1.1 The Ontological Account

Central to the ontological account is humanity as a essential class. Humanity is described as “being a person,” and personhood described as “being human.” Humanity has an effect to human dignity; the former cannot be without the latter. The idea is that humans are persons and persons are humans. This means humanity has some definite moral effects: “Personhood can best be applied to beings who have a serious moral right to life” (Goodman, 1988, pp. 5, 8). This account implicates that only humans are moral persons, and all other persons are not moral. Once having decided that an organism is a human, we know that this makes it the kind of organism that is likely to belong to humanity.

The ontological approach accentuates personhood as an essential class, to which a being basically belongs based on some intrinsic factor. For example, Carl Cohen states, “Morality is an essential feature of human life; all humans are moral creatures, infants and the senile included (…) Rights are universally human, arise in the human realm, apply to humans

19 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 generally” (Cohen & Regan, 2001, p. 37). This involves a firm ontological postulation, as the essence of humans is distinguished categorically from the essence of non-humans. Cohen says that the argument from marginal cases is incorrect, as it does not understand that agency is “not a test to be administered to human beings one by one,” as the “critical distinction is one of kind” (Cohen & Regan, 2001, p. 53). The claim builds up to an idea of generic species- specific capacities. Even if not all humans have the active “ability” for moral agency, they all still have the inherent “capability” (Wetlesen, 1999). Being human makes us carriers of the conventional human capacities, even if we do not ourselves have them on the individual level. However, this leaves much lacunas open in this account. Most prominently, it sounds somewhat strange to say that we all have the common capacities of our species, even if some do not attain these on the individual level. This is apparent when we look at other qualities than moral agency. There are many “averages” that are characteristic of the human species, which do not belong to each individual (e.g., that human beings, in general, have visual capacities, does not mean that a blind person could argue to be able to see). How is it possible that we privilege an amount of given skill that is seen as the average of human kind, but we cannot claim to possess a skill or capacity, even if most humans do possess it? By not doing so, we do not exclude any human being that is disabled or in a vegetative state. Whether the capacities are mental or physical, the only thing that matters is what happens on the individual level, not the generic level. “Requiring individuals to be treated in accordance with the norm for their species rather than their own individual characteristics is outrageously unfair” (Hoffman, 1993, p. 9). If we humans, as species, have generic capacities that can be valuated, then we should value the human species in general. To be seen and valued as individuals, however, we need to possess the required capacities as individuals as well.

There is an interesting change of position at play here. Where it is usually non-natural persons that are understood on the basis of their group characteristics (robots, computers, animals, and even corporations), and humans that are defined through individual traits, here the claim is contrary. The outcome is that it is still vague as to why it is morally doubtful to value humans on the basis of their race, sex, gender, nationality, etc., while on the other hand, it is morally justified to value humans based on their species. This involves an essential inconsistency. In relation to non- natural persons, natural persons are described through types, not individuality; and in relation to other natural persons, natural persons are described through individuality (Cohen & Regan, 2001, pp. 43-59). Potentiality and lost capacities could also be mentioned in connection with the basis of personhood (Holland, 1984, pp. 281-291). “Humans live lives that will be, or have been, or remain essentially moral (…) what humans retain when disabled, rats never had.” In the case of the comatose or disabled, the class of humanity starts to play a role (Callahan, 1970). The well-known example is that even though

20 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 we are all potentially dead, it does not mean that we ought to be treated as such (Johnson, 1991, pp. 92-93). It is hard to see that our value is actual and plays in the “now,” as if the substance of the condition plays only in future or past. Besides, some humans will never be, and never have been, moral agents such (temporarily) comatose people or foetuses.

However, the use of personhood as some inherent factor shared by all human beings begs the question as to what this essence of man/woman is; the UNDHR and ECHR use human dignity as underlying value for humans, and the fundamental rights awarded to people are based on this factor. It is the individual value of one person that counts; or in the words of Kant, one should treat beings as an “end in themselves” (Aalthola, 2008, p. 5). However, the problem with using humanity as the basis for personhood is that it is defined rather than justified. This implies that all others, for example non-natural persons, ought to be excluded (Aalthola, 2008, p. 11). It is, therefore, some sort of quasi-empirical superiority argument: because we are humans, we have a certain essence and, therefore, we should not worry about justifying it. This means that we should just take it for granted. This is important for purposes of this discussion, because this line of thought leads to discrimination, as it implies that, unlike natural persons, all other kinds of persons and animals need to justify their claim to personhood. One could argue, however, that this is exactly what needs to be done in order to make a distinction between “us” (the natural persons) and “them” (the non-natural persons).

Section 2.1.2 The Subjective Account

Subjective approaches to personhood underline the purist capacities of personhood. Purist capacities reflect the most essential characteristics of humans. This account is called subjective, because it is about the capacities that humans experience from a first person perspective. There are two different forms: one that stresses the multiplicity of capacities, and a second one that focuses on one exclusive capacity. Personhood here, in the subjective account, implies several exclusive human capacities. Gary Francione mentions the following capacities as the basis of personhood:

…minimum intelligence, self-awareness, self-control, a sense of time, a sense of futurity, a sense of the past, the capability of relating to others, concern for others, communication, control of existence, curiosity, change and changeability, balance of rationality and feeling, idiosyncrasy, and neocortical functioning. (Francione, 1993)

DeGrazia claims that personhood entails “certain complex forms of consciousness,” such as “self-awareness over time, rationality, and sociability” (DeGrazia, 2004). Mary Anne Warren

21 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 argues that the six key markers of personhood are as follows: (1) sentience, (2) emotionality, (3) reason, (4) capacity to communicate, (5) self-awareness, and (6) moral agency (Warren, 1997, pp. 83-84). John Harris defines personhood as that “persons are beings capable of valuing their own lives” (Harris, 1990, p. 1683). Michael Tooley argues that “an organism can only possess a serious right to life if it possesses the concept of a self as a continuing subject of experiences and other mental states, and believes that it is itself such an entity” (Tooley, 1987, p. 82). Nonetheless, the danger in using these criteria is that personhood is seen as a condition that involves different “symptoms.” Personhood, therefore, turns into an indefinable state, as there is neither transparency nor consistency in the specification of these symptoms. For example, if rationality is an essential quality to be seen as a person, then all children under a certain age will fail to count as persons. Tristan Engelhardt says on this account, “If being a person is to be a responsible agent, a bearer of rights and duties, children are not persons in a strict sense” (Engelhardt, 1975). The downside of this is that personhood has become a “cluster concept” (DeGrazia, 1997, p. 35) that involves composite capacities, the required levels of which continue to be unclear. This leads to odd questions. If you have 5 out of 10 of the suggested capacities, can you then be described as a “person,” “partial person,” or “roughly a person”? Besides, how many of the qualities do you have to show? Is some self-awareness, consciousness, intentionality, rationality, etc. enough, and, if so, how much is “some”? The discussion becomes very much detailed, unclear, and unstable. Looking towards a more singular view of personhood, matters such as theoretical reason, autonomy, and moral agency have been highlighted. Possibly the most famous example is Kant, to whom personhood was chiefly comprised of autonomy; and later, Harry Frankfurt, as he based his argument on “free will.” He writes, “What philosophers have lately come to accept as analysis of the concept of a person is not actually analysis of that concept at all.” As Frankfurt would frame, “The criteria for being a person... are designed to capture those attributes which are the subject of our most humane concern with ourselves and the source of what we regard as most important and most problematical in our lives” (Frankfurt, 1971, pp. 5-7). Charles Taylor proposes a significance-based view of personhood. “What is crucial about agents is that things matter to them. We thus cannot simply identify agents by a performance criterion, nor assimilate animals to machines... [likewise] there are matters of significance for human beings which are peculiarly human, and have no analogue with animals” (Taylor, 1985, pp. 98-102). Furthermore, Peter Singer defines a “person” as being a conscious, thinking being, which knows that it is a person (self- awareness) (Singer, 1985, pp. 55-62). Daniel Dennett argues that the capacity to conceptually understand both the intentionality of oneself and another is the primary source of personhood (Dennett, 1976). Another common argument concerns moral agency. For example, Carl Cohen has claimed that in the absence of a capacity for reciprocity, the concept of personhood

22 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 cannot be applied (Cohen & Regan, 2001, p. 35). Furthermore, James Griffin’s notion of personhood is related to agency and, therefore, human rights:

What seems to me the best account of human rights is this. It is centred on the notion of agency. We human beings have the capacity to form pictures of what a good life would be and to try to realize these pictures. We value our status as agents especially highly, often more highly even than our happiness. Human rights can then be seen as protections of our agency—what one might call our personhood. (Griffin, 2001, p. 4)

Even though these theories have a certain value, they also increase the complexity of the situation. Capacities could be used in a quantitative way that implies a scale for personhood, dependent upon the level of rationality, autonomy, etc. (VanDeVeer, 1995). Additionally, the criteria used in this approach are based on generalizations. No one is “rational” in all aspects of their life—in fact, every human being fails constantly on this task. Paradoxically, the very thing that we cannot achieve is regarded as the criterion for our value. For moral agency, there is a division between “how” and “what”—we do not have to be moral in order to have moral value (Aalthola, 2008, p. 12). And, if applied consistently, an emphasis on moral agency (and other purist qualities) as a criterion for being a person would leave many human beings without personhood (Dombrowski, 1997).

Evidently, the subjective approach encounters many problems about what the criteria of personhood might actually be. But not all those suggestions are implausible, and it would be easy enough, in principle, to strike out or refine the implausible ones. However, it is noteworthy how little purists feel the need to do this. In practice, purists (or subjectivists) often seem perfectly happy to stick with what, intuitively, seems like crazily over-demanding criteria for personhood, such as Tooley’s (which excludes anyone who does not believe that he/she is a persisting self) or Engelhardt’s (which excludes children). However, the plausibility of the various suggested criteria is not the real issue. The key difficulty for purism lies in the notion that the sort of properties that it hones in on are true criteria of personhood at all, and not various made up interpretation of beings.

Concluding, the subjective account aims to define humans by specific traits. A human is a complex of such traits. It is about the capacities, in contrast with a certain type of essence, which is the core of the ontological account (Aalthola, 2008, p. 7). Intentionality, sentience, awareness, intelligence, and/or consciousness are, for example, often used as defining characteristics of a person (DeGrazia, 2004; Aalthola, 2008). So, one could say that, only if one satisfies the conditions of the list of characteristics, is one seen as fully human, and

23 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 therefore, has personhood. One could, therefore, also have moral personhood to a certain degree, for example, if one has eight out of ten traits. This, however, would lead to bizarre outcomes, as the question arises when one is seen as “fully” human or “partially” human. For example, is a comatose person, or someone asleep, also to be counted as truly human? This is the main reason that any account based on such a list is very hard to use in discussions about non-natural personhood in terms of corporations; however, for artificial intelligence and animals, there could be a basis for a claim on this account. This is the subject of the next chapter.

Section 2.1.3 The Objective Account

The objective account approaches personhood in terms of continuity of identity, and the ability to reflect on this. Therefore, personhood does not rest on a static quality or category, but is a project that feeds on activity, or interaction. In this account it is about the second person perspective, which are essentially the relations one has with another. “Personhood” originally was linked to “a mask,” which, in antiquity, was connected with a role in a play (Singer, 1985). This view is important in virtue ethics, which highlights the roles of persons in relation to others. Alasdair MacIntyre argues that personhood results from the capacity to respond to other beings (MacIntyre, 2001). In ethics, this is sometimes mentioned because of the relevance given to moral personhood; only if one is a moral person, can one have a role in relation to others. However, “roles” should be regarded in a wider perspective. Being someone means that one is “a subject of relations” (Cavalieri, 2001, p. 120). MacIntyre argues that these relations can be “self-relations” (such as self-consciousness), or “hetero- relations” (relations to others), and “Such a reading raises the question whether one may not in the end interpret the notion of ‘person’ in terms of the simple possibility of relating to other beings and, consequently, of the mere capacity for consciousness” (Cavalieri, 2001, pp. 120- 121).

Daniel Dennett’s intentionality criterion is important in this sense. Persons constitute each other as persons, and as agents, by treating each other as persons and as agents. But, what is relevant is not the capacity to conceptualize oneself or another as an intentional agent in the first or third person sense, but rather in the second person sense. This means that the personhood of others is experienced in direct interaction; I behave intentionally towards another, who behaves intentionally towards me. The immediate recognition of one’s own and other’s intentionality comes in the form of “feeling the subjectivity of others,” “relating to others” in “face to face interactions.”

24 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Others are not understood as persons because we infer from their behavior that they must have intentions and ideas about other people’s intentions, but because we are capable of engaging with them in specific patterns of inter-subjective interactions that include emotional and expressive behaviors… Persons are capable of representing others as ‘second persons’, i.e., as creatures capable of engaging in inter-subjective encounters. (Gomez, 1998)

This means that individuality exists through interaction. Personhood is built through a relation to the world, and especially to other individuals. “X” is a person if he/she reacts to others, whom he/she understands to be reacting towards him/herself. Finally, this view emphasises the ability to experience, which is also stressed by some authors in animal ethics. Beings that can have affective responses to the outside world and other beings can be called “persons.” Empathy has a significant role in this. Next, also identification relies on the capability to be able to see from the other being’s point of view, and thus, is fortified by interaction. The knife cuts both ways, as interaction is also strengthened by identification. We can better interact when we understand the other being’s point of view. For animals, this view would not make sense; however, corporations could have a claim.

The objective approach does involve important complications. Because of the possibility of simulation, identification would be problematic (Holton & Landon, 1999). Anthropomorphism also poses a threat, as a falsely “intentional stance” may be ascribed to non-humans such as animals, projecting human experiences onto the animal. Moreover, the model that stresses interaction could be critiqued for the circumstance that plants, animals, and AI could respond suitably to other things/beings without having an intentional mental state, and therefore, could be qualified as subjects of “interaction.” This means that the objective approach may use too wide of criteria. Several “tools” that examine experiences can override the simulation related problem. This has been named an “asymmetry view,” according to which we adopt different procedures to understand the minds of non-humans and human beings (Jamieson, 2002; Aalthola, 2008, p. 18). We understand non-human minds in a comparable way as human minds, through achieving knowledge of their backdrop, context, etc. These variances have to do with the emotive aspects of behaviour—interaction does not only depend on affective attitudes, these attitudes are also being formed in interaction. Therefore, the capacity to experience helps us to see the difference between men and women, between sharks and pigeons, and between a boat and pineapple trees. What matters in the end, is the capacity to experience and make contact with others via experiences. This is the basic root of personhood. Individuality only exists in relation to others: “I am a person in so far as I and another perceive and treat each other as persons” (Gomez, 1998).

25 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Concluding, the objective account bases personhood on a certain kind of behaviour or actions. Personhood is something that exists and is created through relations and actions in the world. Only by doing so, one creates personhood. It is something that exists and is created through interaction (Aalthola, 2008, p. 12). However, the problem that could arise is, for example, simulation, as it would be impossible to actually know whether animals or other non-natural beings really understand their experiences. Therefore, the risk of anthropomorphism is a danger, as we do not know if one is faking their experiences or not. This is something that could only be a problem with animals (Aalthola, 2008, p. 13), but perhaps with AI as well.

AI is a different and difficult topic as these are machines that are built to be the most human- like. When AI becomes more and more anthropocentric over the coming years, they will also be able to commit acts with the outside world. They will even have more human-like traits, such as a consciousness or a certain amount of intelligence, and could possible think on their own. Therefore, they could fall both under the subjective and the objective account.

Section 2.2 Conclusions

In the past century, different accounts have served as a basis for ascribing rights to non- natural persons. The philosophical definition and the legal definition of moral personhood are different. In philosophy, it means one of the three accounts as mentioned earlier, the ontological, the subjective or objective, , while in law, it means that anyone and everyone is moral once they can claim certain fundamental rights. The legal assumption is a contrario, because natural persons are conceived as moral persons, which have been granted fundamental rights, and non-natural persons who have been granted fundamental rights are also regarded as moral persons. The definitions from each field of science are therefore different and, especially in law, too strict. Each account has been used to grant moral personhood status, and each account has valid point in doing so, but they also face critique. That is the reason that none of these accounts are all encompassing or complete. Once an account has been developed, there come up cases by which the particular personhood theory does not fit. I think that we should rule out the accounts but rather take the good out of each of them and fit them in a larger composure. This is what will be shown in the next chapter.

26 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Chapter 3 A Normative Structure

In this chapter, first will the three accounts of moral personhood be discussed and the consequences of each account to (non-) natural persons and animals. Second, a fourth account of moral personhood will be introduced: the political-natural account. Third, fundamental rights distinctions will be discussed, as well as a list of fundamental rights constructed for non-natural persons and animals.

Section 3.1 The Three Accounts of Moral Personhood and their Consequences

The first chapter showed that a non-natural person has been attributed moral personhood by the U.S. Supreme Court and there were arguments given pro and contra. The second chapter introduced three accounts of moral personhood: the ontological, the subjective, and the objective account. Each account has a different perspective and different arguments for/upon declaring something or someone a moral person. The discussion will now turn to the consequences of each account of moral personhood in terms of natural persons, non-natural persons, and animals.

First, there is the ontological account that bases its view entirely on humanity or human dignity. Humanity means that one belongs to a specific class, which is based on an intrinsic factor that all humans share. This factor cannot be derived one way or another: one either has it, or does not have it. Therefore, it is a black-or-white approach. Only humans and natural persons have this intrinsic factor, and non-natural persons and animals cannot, nor ever will, share this factor. If one bases its approach of moral personhood on the ontological account, as the ECHR has done in its preamble, this means that only natural persons could be granted fundamental rights. The consequence of this account is that non-natural persons, such as corporations and animals, cannot have moral personhood and, therefore, no fundamental rights, simply because they do not belong to the human race.

Second, the subjective account will be discussed. Where the ontological account uses a class, the human race, as its defining feature, this account uses a set of characteristics to define a natural person. For example, a natural person can be defined according to intentionality, sentience, self-awareness, language, consciousness, and many more characteristics, as discussed in chapter 2. The threshold is different for each philosopher. The consequences are that this account is not suitable for corporations. When reflecting on the “Real and Independent Person” theory, as formulated by the U.S Supreme Court, the court has used the subjective account in order to attribute moral personhood to corporations. This

27 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 view leads to the belief that the corporation has a “collective consciousness, intentions, or will” (Ripken, 2000, pp. 790-799). The view of the Court is largely based upon this belief since the Santa Clara-case of 1886, and led to the attribution of a fundamental right in the Citizens United-case and in the Burwell-case. It is a mistake of the U.S. Supreme Court to base its view and their arguments on this, because how can it possibly be that a corporation has consciousness or intent? Its intent, or consciousness, comes from the natural persons behind the corporation, not from the corporation itself. However, the subjective is more suitable in the argument of attributing certain fundamental rights to non-natural persons such as AI and animals. Natural persons have a form of consciousness, intentionality, self-awareness, or language; but, can we say that a corporation has consciousness or is self-aware? It seems hard to argue for such a case, as these traits only seem to be given to natural creatures. For example, animals do possess some form of consciousness or self-awareness; at least that is what is argued in the animal personhood debate. Animals do have some of these traits and, therefore, an argument could be made in attributing some fundamental rights to them. For future non-natural persons, AI for example, the subjective account could be used to formulate an argument for moral personhood based on consciousness or intent, if these machines are capable of these characteristics.

Last, the objective account of moral personhood will be discussed. The objective account could be characterized as that “personhood does not rest on a static quality or category, but is merely a project that feeds on an activity, which forms a point of continuation for the being” (Aalthola, 2008, p. 12). This account defines a person through the acts it performs and the relations it has with the world. The consequences of this account are that animals cannot be seen as committing intended acts. Of animals, it could not be said that it has relations with the world around it, or through its acts does it establish these relations. However, a good case could be made for corporations. Corporations do act through their relations with the world. They are, in general, seen as active contributors to society and our economies. If they do not act, they cannot do business. A similar argument was made in favour of corporate personhood, that there is something such as corporate intent, next to the intent of the individuals behind the corporation. A corporation acts with an own intent. Peter French also highlighted this. (French P. A., 1979). Because of this, the objective account could be a good starting point in arguing for corporate moral personhood.

All three accounts have their arguments pro and contra. When using a personhood account strictly on the ontological version, non-natural persons and animals will not have any rights.

28 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

The subjective and the objective accounts provide more ground for the attribution of personhood to non-natural persons and animals. In order to construct a normative framework that encompasses, natural persons, non-natural persons, and animals, three accounts are needed. It has been shown that, along with moral personhood, there come fundamental rights. Now, corporations have been granted moral personhood or Corporate Moral Personhood (nonetheless based on the wrong personhood account) and, therefore, they have been ascribed certain fundamental rights. The question is how all these conclusions will benefit to, and fit in the conceptual normative framework.

Section 3.2. A Fourth Account: the Political-Natural Account.

The three accounts can be used differently to justify moral personhood for natural persons, non-natural persons, and animals. All the arguments mentioned in section 3.1 are intertwined and related. Now, there should be placed some order. To grant non-natural persons and animals personhood-status, there should be some limits imposed. In this section, the three accounts of moral personhood will be used and attributed to each actor: natural person, non- natural person, and animals. Moral personhood implicates fundamental rights; however, not all fundamental rights should be available, or are of use, to all non-natural persons and animals. For example, the right to marry is not important for a corporation, and neither would it be for animals. This is why two interpretations of moral personhood are proposed: natural moral personhood and consequential moral personhood.

- A. Moral Interpretation: Natural Moral Personhood

This first interpretation holds that moral personhood and fundamental rights can only be ascribed to natural persons based on their intrinsic human value which is derived from the ontological account: human dignity and humanity. These underlying values only belong to human beings and, therefore, any right that is based on these critical values can only be ascribed to humans, and to nothing else.

Natural moral personhood is derived from the naturalistic account of human rights. This account was proposed by Grotius at the start of the 17th century, and followed by many more. Grotius said that the every human being has natural rights, which comes along with the status of being a human (Grotius, 1625). Moral personhood here, implicates a form of personhood that is based on the intrinsic value of being a human, which is the ontological account. Humanity is the basis for moral personhood. Human rights are what their label literally signifies, and they are grounded in human dignity, every human being’s unconditional and

29 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 inviolable worth. Not only Grotius, and many others since him, has mentioned humanity as a basis for fundamental rights, also the UDHR refers to the “individual dignity” as written down in its Preamble (Mariadakis, 1979). Although the definition of individual dignity is contested (Schachter, 1983), it has moral significance, using humanity as that to which a standard of moral equality applies. Natural persons differ in their level of rationality and agency, and some display such capacities only marginally, or not at all. The reason why humanity is chosen as the leading characteristic is that, whether one is asleep, in a coma, or anything else, none of this affects the dignity of the human; “the underlying value-dignity-is possessed by all human beings fully, equally, and uninterruptedly” (Dan-Cohen, 2013, p. 308). Basing moral personhood on humanity draws a very strong line into the attribution of fundamental rights. The reason why this is done is that some fundamental rights are more fundamental than others. The three most fundamental rights are called “the problematic trio”: the right to life, the right to vote, and the right to freedom and not to be held in slavery (Hindriks, 2013). I will later elaborate on them in the hierarch of fundamental rights. These rights all have the aim of protecting the physical and mental integrity of natural persons. A little less significant but nonetheless very important are, among others, the right to the inviolability of the human body, the right not to suffer cruel and unusual punishment, the right against slavery or involuntary servitude, the right to vote, the right to life, and the right to self-determination. In addition, one finds, for example, the right to privacy described as the right to be left alone. All the rights that are written down in the UNDR and the ECHR are moral rights, and they belong to the fundamental rights of natural persons. (Frankema, 1973; Kymlicka, 1988; Rawls, 1971).

The constitutive significance of humanity ranges over numerous levels, from concrete versions in individual lives to the bigger picture of humanity as a whole on this planet. This creates a backdrop for investigating our own traits, capacities, and vulnerabilities, as well as those of corporations, animals, artificial intelligence, and even “aliens.” It is necessary to anticipate the normative consequences of those traits, capacities, and vulnerabilities for their bearers, and for others in the near future.

- Animals

On July 1, 2015, Cecil the Lion was killed during a trophy hunting expedition in Zimbabwe. Cecil was a major attraction for the wildlife park and was followed by the University of Oxford as part of a larger study on lion conservation. The death sparked outrage over the whole world and ignited the animal rights debate again (Gordon, 2015).

30 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Animals have feelings and emotions in a way similar to natural persons. Corporations do not have feelings or emotions. As Jeremy Bentham’s account for animals reflected, “the question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?” (Bentham, 1907). Therefore, to ascribe to animals moral personhood, we should look towards the subjective account of personhood, as there are traits to be found that animals do have, such as a certain form of consciousness, intentions, and a certain capacity for decision-making. Because animals do have feelings, and perhaps also other human-like traits, they should be regarded as beings with a moral worth (McFarland & Hediger, 2009). They are not regarded as persons in any sort of sense (yet), but they have been awarded certain rights, although not similar fundamental rights to that of natural persons. This could change if one bases its view on the subjective account of personhood. In that case, there is to argue that animals should have moral personhood and, therefore, fundamental rights. Nonetheless, only those that could be justified for them, such as the right of protection against unnecessary suffering.

- Artificial Intelligence

As said before, the AI could fall under both the subjective and the objective account of moral personhood. In the 2015 movie Ex Machina, the AI manipulates the human person into believing that she (the AI) has feelings for him (the programmer), after which he frees her, but then becomes imprisoned by her at the same time. She returns to the human world, where no one notices, or will notice, that she is a robot. The AI has human-like traits in order to be manipulative and her acts reflect this manipulation. They could be moral or natural to a certain extent. The movie shows what the possible (destructive) consequences could be of AI. This simulation poses, therefore, a problem into ascribing moral personhood, and with it, certain fundamental rights. However, AI will not be taken into account for the ascription of any rights in this thesis, as it is still unclear to what extent they should be given rights (if at all).

B. Consequential Interpretation: Consequential Moral Personhood

The second interpretation of personhood is based on the instrumental value of ascribing moral personhood. It can be seen as an interpretation of the political account of human rights. The Political Conception of human rights can be traced back to John Rawls’ The Law of Peoples (Rawls, 1999). Since the publication of that work, other prominent political philosophers, including Joseph Raz and Charles Beitz, have also defended the Political Conception (Liao & Etinson, 2012).

31 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

According to the political conception of human rights, the distinctive nature of human rights is to be understood in light of its role or function in modern, international, political practice (Liao & Etinson, 2012, p. 3). In Rawls’ view, “Human rights are a class of rights that play a special role in a reasonable Law of Peoples; they restrict the justifying reasons for war and its conduct, and they specify limits to a regime’s internal autonomy” (Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 1999). Therefore, human rights are the “necessary conditions of any system of social cooperation. When they are regularly violated, we have command by force, a slave system, and no cooperation of any kind” (Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 1999). Rawls continues, “that human rights are necessary conditions of any system of social cooperation, and he believes that conditions of social cooperation can determine the limits of sovereignty” (Liao & Etinson, 2012, p. 4). Beitz argues, furthermore, “that human rights are also justifications for individuals and nongovernmental organizations to engage in reform-oriented political action” (Liao & Etinson, 2012, p. 4). Rawls’ use of the political conception is in order to construe a society of “well-ordered peoples.” In this well-ordered society, everyone binds himself or herself to a form of social contract.

He aims to establish a law of peoples, that is, a set of principles and norms including human rights, to which “well-ordered peoples” from different religious, philosophical, and moral background can freely agree as the basis for governing their behavior towards one another, thereby establishing a mutually respectful peace. (Liao & Etinson, 2012, p. 6)

Regarding the political conception of human rights, the role or function in society is based on the consequential interpretation. The only reason for the attribution of moral personhood and, thus, certain fundamental rights—or human rights as Rawls calls them—is in light of their function or role. The difference between Rawls and this thesis is that Rawls argues from a legal perspective and this thesis from a philosophical perspective. Nonetheless, central is the aim, the telos, of ascribing fundamental rights to non-natural persons. It is the value to society at large (Nagel, 1970; Williams, 1972; Sheffler, 1988; Liao & Etinson, 2012, p. 329). It is about achieving a distant goal, for example truth-finding, free- market economy, protection of other fundamental rights, furtherance of the rule of law, rights of others, modern life, and democratic society (Scolnicov, 2013, pp. 5-6). To give a practical example, a newspaper should have the right to freedom of expression in order to be able to vent its thoughts on certain topics. It is for the well-order of society, in the Rawlsian sense, that newspapers share their critical thoughts and ideas. A corporation could claim the right of freedom of speech if sued, when it has publicized its thoughts on a particular matter. The justification is found in society’s need for the existence of non-natural persons. Without

32 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 corporations, the economy would no longer be able to properly function. Corporations need personhood in order to strike deals, form contracts, and act in society. The consequential interpretation is, in this sense, nothing less than the objective account of moral personhood. The attribution of moral personhood stands with the acts it does.

In Figure 1, there is an overview of the accounts as they are positioned now.

Natural Moral Non-Natural Natural Moral Animal Consequential Personhood Personhood Moral Personhood

Non-Natural Animals Natural Persons Persons

Fundamental Fundamental Fundamental rights Rights rights

Based on a Based on a Based on a moral moral subjective moral objective ontological interpretation interpretation interpretation

Figure 1

The natural moral personhood account is meant only for natural persons, and finds its basis in the ontological account. Therefore, it can have fundamental rights to the fullest extent. The natural moral animal personhood also grants animals moral standing. It finds its basis in the subjective account, as animals can feel, suffer, and experience/possess other human-like traits. The fundamental rights are limited, for example, to the extent of non-suffering. The non-natural moral consequential personhood ascribes moral personhood to corporations through the objective account of moral personhood. It can have certain fundamental rights, but only if they are consequential or to the benefit of society. The specific fundamental rights that fall under each pillar will be discussed in the next sections.

33 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Section 3.3 The Consequences of the Moral Personhood Accounts and Fundamental Rights

In the previous section, the different versions of moral personhood in the political-natural account of moral personhood were mentioned. In terms of fundamental rights, this means that natural persons have all fundamental rights that are available, and that are stated, in the ECHR. Corporations can claim a specific set of fundamental rights, but only those that are beneficial to the better working of society. Animals can also only claim a specific set of fundamental rights, for example, only those that prevent their suffering. In the Figure 2, all three versions have been put together, and it can be seen that the natural, moral, fundamental rights encompass all of the fundamental rights that are available. Each different account can only be ascribed a limited set, depending on the needs of each subject.

Non-Natural Consequential Moral Fundamental Rights Natural Moral Fundamental Rights

Natural Moral Animal Fundamental Rights

Figure 2

Section 3.4 Fundamental Rights Distinctions

Having determined the various accounts of moral personhood, and shown how these accounts fall under the scope of fundamental rights, the next question requires examination. “Which fundamental rights should be ascribed to which kind of person?” In order to answer this question, it is first necessary to define the various kinds of fundamental rights, derived from the distinction made between three generations of rights by

34 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 the Czech jurist Karel Vasak (Vasak, 1979). The rights, summarized below, are fundamental rights as accrued over the history of humanity, and originate from natural rights as posited by Aristotle, Aquinas, Locke, Grotius, and Kant to the contemporary, fundamental rights as reflected in documents such as the UDHR and ECHR.

First-generation, “civil-political” rights (or legalité rights) are about liberty and involvement in political life. These are very human-centred and negatively fashioned to defend the individual from any intrusion by the government. This first generation of rights considers human rights more in a negative formulation (i.e., freedoms from) rather than in a positive formulation (i.e., rights to). It favours the abstinence of interference by the government in the pursuit of human dignity. Rights included in this first generation are rights such as those put forward in Articles 2–21 of the UDHR. These include the right to life, liberty, and security of the person; freedom from discrimination in terms of gender and race and comparable forms of discrimination; freedom of thought, conscience, and religion; freedom of opinion and expression; freedom from torture and from cruel, inhumane, or degrading treatment or punishment; freedom from arbitrary arrest, detention, or exile; freedom from slavery or involuntary servitude; the right to a fair and public trial; freedom from interference in privacy and correspondence; freedom of movement and residence; the right to protection from persecution; freedom of peaceful assembly and association; and the right to participate in government, directly or through free elections. Also included are the right to own property and the right not to be deprived of it arbitrarily.

Second-generation, “socio-economic” (or egalité) rights assure equal circumstances and treatment. These rights are not directly owned by humans but establish positive obligations to the state to respect and realize them. Socio-economic rights are expressed in Articles 22 to 27 of the 1948 UDHR, like the right to social security; the right to a standard of living adequate for the health and well-being of self and family; the right to rest and leisure, including periodic holidays with pay; the right to work and to protection against unemployment; the right to education; and the right to the protection of one’s scientific, literary, and artistic production.

Third-generation, “collective-developmental” (or fraternité) rights are based on the last principle of “fraternity.” They form an extensive group of rights that have found resonance in multiple international agreements and accords, but are more challenged than the previous categories. These include the right to economic and social development; the right to political, economic, social, and cultural self-determination; the right to peace; the right to a clean and healthy milieu; the right to humanitarian disaster relief; and the right to participate in and

35 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 benefit from “the common heritage of mankind.”

These are the fundamental rights that have developed over the years. The following question should be posited now. “How can we make up a hierarchical structure that embodies the above rights, which in first instance are intended to be applicable to natural only, and make them suitable to be used for non-natural persons and animals as well? Let us start with defining a hierarchy of rights for natural, non-natural persons and animals.

Section 3.5 A Hierarchy of Fundamental Rights

When one has moral personhood, this directly implies that one also has the rights that come with this status. See below the hierarchy of fundamental rights, followed by its explanation.

Natural Fundamental Rights: The problematic Trio (Non-Derivable)

All Fundamental Rights

Freedom of opinion and expression; the right to a fair Freedom from and public trial; freedom torture and from from interference in privacy andRIghts correspondence; freedom cruel, inhuman, of movement and residence; or degrading the right to protection from persecution; freedom of treatment or peaceful assembly and punishment; association; the right to own property and the right not to freedom from be deprived of it arbitrarily; slavery or the right to the protection of one’s scientific, literary, and servitude. artistic production; the right

to peace.

Consequential Fundamental Consequential

Animal Rights Animal Fundamental Natural Fundamental Rights Fundamental Natural

36 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

In the previous section, the traditional hierarchy of fundamental rights was mentioned in Vasak’s account. The traditional approach cannot properly be applied here because of the various fundamental rights that are being ascribed to The hierarchy proposal in this these uses all three generations, and cuts rights through it. The upper level (the pyramid) consists of the most fundamental rights to natural persons. These are called the “problematic trio”: the right to life, the right to vote, and the right to freedom and not to be held in slavery. These are rights that can and will never be granted to non-natural persons and are the highest rights of this pyramid (Hindriks, 2013). According to Hindriks these rights are problematic:

…as they are particularly apt for illustrating problems concerning corporate rights. Do these rights extend to organizations? If so, bankruptcies and takeovers might be in conflict with the rights that corporate agents are entitled to. The underlying idea would be that a bankruptcy terminates the existence of a moral person (“corporate death”), and that a takeover results in the target becoming the slave of the acquirer (“corporate slavery”). This is rather counterintuitive, to say the least. This reflects how strange it would be to accept that organizations should be regarded as full- fledged citizens with all the concomitant rights and obligations. (Hindriks, 2013, p. 23)

Next to these three most fundamental rights, the box below the pyramid contains all fundamental rights that are available to humans. Inside the box, there are two pillars: one for non-natural persons and one for animals. In this box all fundamental rights that are available this means: all fundamental rights as enshrined in the UDHR and ECHR.They encompass all three generations of fundamental rights. Subsequently, the two pillars are combinations of first, second, and third-generation rights and encompassed within natural fundamental rights. It differs for each and every person, whether non-natural or animal, to be granted. For non-natural persons this can only be based on consequential grounds. For example, the right of freedom of expression is essential for a publishing corporation but is not directly necessary for a clothing corporation. Similarly, the right of religious freedom could be very well argued for in cases of certain types of religious (non-profit) corporations such as churches. Also, when a corporation is going to trial, they should have the right to a fair and public trial. As one can see the applicability of fundamental rights rests on the telos or aim of the non-natural person, such as the aim of a corporation as stated in its statutes. Rights that could be ascribed to non-natural persons are as follows: Freedom of opinion and expression; the right to a fair and public trial; freedom from

37 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 interference in privacy and correspondence; freedom of movement and residence; the right to protection from persecution; freedom of peaceful assembly and association; the right to own property and the right not to be deprived of it arbitrarily; the right to the protection of one’s scientific, literary, and artistic production; the right to peace.

For animals, the range of fundamental rights is smaller. For example, the right to freedom of speech does not make sense and, therefore, could not be ascribed to them. However, for animals, the right to non-suffering makes sense, but for a corporation this does not. For animals, it also depends on how far one goes in ideology, for example, there are animal activist that believe that animals should be fully equal to natural persons and should not even be eaten. Others, carnivores for example, would obviously disagree. The line is, therefore, very thin. Rights that, at the very least, can be included are freedom from torture and from cruel, inhumane, or degrading treatment or punishment, and freedom from slavery or servitude. However, this discussion is also very fragile: some animals’ advocates would also want to ascribe the right to life to animals and want total equality. It there is a totally different discussion that cannot be taken into account here but can only be briefly mentioned.

Section 3. 7 Conclusions

The limits of which non-natural persons can operate are seen within the boundaries of the natural moral personhood and moral consequential personhood. Both kinds of personhoods encompass the three accounts of moral personhood (ontological, subjective and objective), and together they form a fourth account, the political-natural account. Each account, next to the moral natural account, has a specific set of fundamental rights, based on a specific form of moral personhood. The natural moral account is based upon humanity and the fundamental rights, the problematic trio, that are held in this account to be non-derivable; they can never be ascribed to anything or anyone other than natural persons. For animals, moral personhood could be argued, and with this comes a limited amount of rights. The moral consequential account assures that non-natural persons could be ascribed certain fundamental rights, but only if it is for the benefit of society.

Looking towards the future, AI and robots are on their way and many, such as Tesla’s Elon Musk and Microsoft’s Bill Gates think that it is the largest threat to mankind (Edicicco, 2015). Another thing to keep in mind is the development of the corporation, as it has corporate personhood right now; the next step might be corporate nationhood. This means that corporations be treated similar to nations. Especially since the Trans-Pacific Partnership

38 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

(TPP) proposed last year, worries about the rise of this legal status for corporations have grown.

The government of El Salvador was so concerned that its water was so fouled by mining companies that it passed a moratorium on new mines in 2008. Oceana Gold, an Australian corporation, didn’t like the law, so it sued El Salvador for $301 million, the amount the company said the policy cost it in lost profits. The case was not heard in a Salvadoran court, but rather by a special, secretive corporate tribunal based in the United States and overseen by a panel of three judges, all corporate lawyers. If the tribunal rules in favor of the mining company, El Salvador has no right to appeal. The Trans-Pacific Partnership creates special rights for corporations and threatens standards that protect our families and communities. There are 29 chapters in the proposed treaty; just five of them deal with traditional trade issues. The other two dozen chapters convey a vast array of new political and economic rights to corporations, including the type of “corporate nationhood” that allowed the Australian mining company to sue El Salvador. Individual people have no such rights. (Klinger, 2015)

Countries run by private corporations—it is an interesting and dangerous thought. However, the political-natural personhood account could apply to this issue as well. Although personhood has to be substituted by nationhood, in essence it boils down to the same: non- natural persons that want to be treated equally to natural persons. But, again, this can only happen if it is in the benefit of society, democracy, or rule of law. It is only for consequential reasons. The future looks challenging, and it will be very interesting to see the changes coming, both in the legal as well in the philosophical, playing field. With the political-legal account, the world would find itself prepared.

39 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Chapter IV Conclusions

In this thesis, corporate personhood was used as a leading example to show to what extent non-natural persons have been ascribed fundamental rights. With this in mind, there has been looked beyond the corporation towards animal and to the future. We do not want to let the attribution of fundamental rights get out of hand. That is why, in this thesis, a normative personhood structure is proposed, to deal with the situation as best as possible.

The main question of this thesis is: In what respect should non-natural persons be equal to natural persons? The sub questions are: 1) What is a person, and how did non-natural persons gain personhood-status? 2) What are the leading accounts of personhood? 3) Could we construct a conceptual normative structure to analyse personhood? 4) What are the implications of this conceptual normative structure for the hierarchy of fundamental rights?

1) A person can be defined in three ways: moral, natural, and legal. The corporation has developed over time from a legal person that exists as a legal vehicle to govern wealth and property to a corporate moral person, which is capable of having certain fundamental rights. Arguments pro and contra corporate personhood have been given to provide a good overview of the situation.

2) The leading theories on moral personhood have been summarised in three accounts: the subjective account, which defines a moral person in terms of certain criteria; the objective account, which defines a moral person through its actions; and the ontological account, which defines a moral person through an inherent factor such as human dignity or humanity. When looking to the accounts of moral personhood, it has been difficult to believe that corporate personhood is based on the subjective account. The U.S. Supreme Court has anthropomorphized corporations based on this subjective account. But, I believe this is not the right personhood account to base corporate personhood upon. Rather, the objective account could better be used, as it would make more sense and be more justified for corporate personhood.

3) and 4) The first two questions introduced non-natural persons and the way they are understood in philosophy and law. The following questions are, then, can we construct a normative personhood structure? And if so, what are the implications of this normative structure for the hierarchy of fundamental rights? There has been made a difference in forms of legal, natural, and moral personhood. When one has moral personhood, this implicates that one has fundamental rights too. The basis for the normative structure proposed here is divided

40 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907 into three accounts: moral personhood for natural persons, non-natural persons, and animals. These three subjects can be granted moral personhood based on the three different accounts of moral personhood: the ontological, the subjective and the objective account. Based on these accounts, specific sets of fundamental rights have been distinguished out of three generations of fundamental rights, for natural persons, non-natural, persons and animals. For fundamental rights, there are two justifications: the moral and the consequential. The moral justification includes the most essential fundamental rights, such as the right to life, the right to vote, and the right to be protected from inhumane treatment; these are only for natural persons. Moral consequential personhood and consequential fundamental rights are fundamental rights for non-natural persons, such as corporations. These rights are granted in order to capacitate corporations as best as possible. Animals have not been forgotten either in this account of personhood. Animals are moral beings, as they can experience pain and have a certain form of intent and consciousness similar to the human being; therefore, based on the objective account, there could be made a case in ascribing them certain fundamental rights. The combination of all three accounts of moral personhood is encompassed within a normative structure: the political-natural account.

Now, in what respect should non-natural persons and animals be equal to natural persons? Non-natural persons are created for the benefit of natural persons, either as legal vehicles to govern wealth and property or to help natural persons in a specific pursuit. Therefore, non- natural persons should only be equal to natural persons to the extent that it is to the benefit of natural persons, nothing more or nothing less. This is similar to the attribution of certain sets of fundamental right to other non-natural persons or animals. Non-natural persons will only be equal to the respect that the attribution of such fundamental rights is for the benefit of society: only for consequential reasons and in the best capacitation of the non-natural person. For animals, the threshold is slightly lower but also clearer: animals will never be equal to natural persons but as they are natural animals they should automatically be ascribed a certain basic fundamental right such as the right against unnecessary suffering.

This thesis has aimed to formulate a conceptual normative structure of personhood to encompass natural persons, non-natural persons and animals. Its aim was not to be all encompassing but merely to sketch the lines upon which this structure could be build. Nonetheless, there is still much left open that demands more investigation such as the topic of AI or the conflict of fundamental rights among the various accounts. Maybe, some place in the future I will elaborate on it again.

41 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Bibliography

Lawless v. Ireland (Preliminary Objections), Series A, No. 1 (ECHR 1979). Aalthola, E. (2008). Personhood and animals: three different approaches. Environmental Ethics , 30 (2), 175-193. Albors-Lorens. (2000). The European Court of Justice: more than a teleological court. Cambridge Yearbook of European Legal Studies . Arizona Free Enterprise Club v. Bennett , 10-238, 10-239 (US Supreme Court 2011). Beardsmore, R. W. (1996). If a Lion Could Talk. In K. S. Johannessen, & T. Nordenstam, Wittgenstein and the Philosophy of Culture. Verlag. Beitz, C. (2004). Human Rights and the Law of Peoples. In D. K. Chatterjee, The Ethics of Assistance, morality and the distant needy. Cambridge: CUP. Bentham, J. (1907). An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Opgeroepen op July 8, 2015, van Library of Economics and Liberty: http://www.econlib.org/library/Bentham/bnthPML18.html Berle Jr., A., & Means, G. (1932). The Modern Corporation and Private Property. Bernstein, M. H. (1998). On Moral Considerability: An Essay on Who Morally Matters . Oxford: Oxford University Press. Blackstone, W. (1756). Commentaries on the Laws of England. Blumberg, P. I. (1990). The Corporate Entity in an Era of Multinational Corporations. Delaware Journal of Corporate Law , 15. Boxer, C. R. (1974). The Anglo-Dutch Wars of the 17th Century. Bratton Jr., W. (1989). The “Nexus of Contracts” Corporation: A Critical Appraisal. Cornell Law Review . Bratton Jr., W. (1989). The New Economic Theory of the Firm: Critical Perspectives from History. Standford Law Review . Brown, J. W. (1905). The Personality of the Corporation and the State. Law Quarterly Review Bruns, R. (1986). A More Perfect Union: The Creation of the United States Constitution. Washington, D.C. Buckley vs. Valeo, 424 U.S. 1 (US Supreme Court 1976). Burwell vs. Hobby Lobby, 573 US (US Supreme Court 2014). Calarco, M., & Atterton, P. (2004). Animal Philosophy: Ethics and Identity. London: Continuum. Callahan, D. (1970). Abortion: Law, Choice and Morality. New York: MacMillan. Calverley, D. J. (2006). Android science and animal right, does an analogy exist? Connection Science , 403-417.

42 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Cavalieri, T. A. (2001). Ethical issues at the end of life. Journal of American Osteopathy Association (101), 616-622. Citizens United v. Federal Elections Commission , 08-205, 558 U.S. 31 (US Supreme Court January 21, 2010). Cline, J. S. (2010, March 27). When Persons Aren't People: The Legal Personhood of Animals, Androids, Aliens, and Acme, Inc. Senior Thesis presented as a Requirement for POL49, Dr. Shak Hanish . California. Cohen. (2001). Cohen, C., & Regan, T. (2001). The Animal Rights Debate . New York: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers. Cressey, D. R. (1989). The Poverty of Theory in Corporate Research. Advances in Criminological Advances . Dan-Cohen, M. (2013). Epilogue on Corporate Personhood and Humanity. New Criminal Law Review , 16 (300). Davidson, D. (1980). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Clarendon. Davis, R. (2015). Slavery in America: Historical Overview. Opgeroepen op May 29, 2015, van http://www.slaveryinamerica.org/history/hs_es_overview.htm DeGrazia, D. (1997). Great Apes, Dolphins, and the Concept of Personhood. Southern Journal of Philosophy . DeGrazia, D. (2004). On the Questions of Personhood Beyond Homo Sapiens. In P. Singer, In Defense of Animals (2nd ed.). London: Blackwell. Dennett, D. (1976). Conditions of Personhood. In A. Rorty, The Identities of Persons. Berkeley: University of California Press. Dombrowski, D. (1997). Babies and Beasts: The Argument from Marginal Cases. University of Illinois. Donaldson, T. (2013). Personalizing Corporate Ontology: The French Way. In M. Boylan, Business Ethics (2nd Edition ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. Edicicco, L. (2015, January 28). Bill Gates: Elon Musk Is Right, We Should All Be Scared Of Artificial Intelligence Wiping Out Humanity . Opgeroepen op July 24, 2015, van Business Insider: : http://uk.businessinsider.com/bill-gates-artificial-intelligence-2015- 1?r=US&IR=T#ixzz3go7rstru Engelhardt, T. (1975). Ethical Issues in Aiding the Death of Young Children. In R. M. Baird, & S. E. Rosenbaum, Euthanasia: the Moral Issues. Buffalo, New York: Promotheus. Ferguson, N. (2008). The Ascent of Money: A Financial History of the World . The Penguin Press HC. First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765 (US Supreme Court 1978).

43 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Forbes. (2014). America's 100 Best Corporate Citizens in 2014. Opgeroepen op July 10, 2015, van Forbes: http://www.forbes.com/sites/susanadams/2014/04/24/americas-100-best- corporate-citizens-in-2014/ Francione, G. L. (1993). Personhood, Property, and Legal Competence. In P. S. Paola Cavalieri, The Great Ape Project (pp. 248-257). New York. Frankema, W. (1973). Ethics (2nd ed.). Prentice Hall. Frankfurt, H. G. (1971). Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person. The Journal of Philosophy , 68 (1). French, P. A. (1986). Principles of Responsibility, Shame, and the Corporation. Shame, Responsibility and The Corporations . French, P. A. (1979). The Corporation As A Moral Person. American Philosophical Quarterly , 16 (3), 207-215. French, P. (1984). Collective And Corporate Responsibility. The University of Chicago Press. Friedman, L. M. (1985). A History of American Law (2nd ed.). Garettt, J. E. (1989). Unredistributable Corporate Moral Responsibility. Journal of Business Ethics . Geldart, W. M. (1911). Legal Personality. Law Quarterly Review . Gomez, J. C. (1998). Are Apes Persons? The Case for Primate Intersubjectivity. Ethica and Animali . Goodman, M. F. (1988). What is a Person? Contemporary Issues in Biomedicine, Ethics and Society . Humana Press. Goodpaster, K. E., & Matthews Jr., J. B. (1982, Jan/Feb.). Can a Corporation Have a Conscience? Harvard Busuness Review . Gordon, B. (2015, July 31). Cecil the lion's killing tells us a lot about the wrongs of animal rights activists. The Telegraph . Gray, J. C. (1921). The Nature and Sources of the Law . (R. Gray, Red.) MacMillan. Griffin, J. (2001). Discrepancies between the Best Philosophical Account of Human Rights and the International Law of Human Rights. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society . Grotius, H. (1625). De Iure Belli Ac Pacis. Paris. Haberkorn, J., & Gerstein, J. (2014, June 30). Supreme Court sides with Hobby Lobby on contraception mandate. Politico . Hager, R., & Leas, J. M. (2012, January 17). The Problem With Citizens United Is Not Corporate Personhood. Opgeroepen op June 15, 2015, van Truthout: http://www.truth- out.org/news/item/6095:the-problem-with-citizens-united-is-not-corporate-personhood Hainsworth, D. R. (1998). The Anglo-Dutch Naval Wars 1652-1674.

44 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Hall, P. (2000). Moving Targets: Evangelicalism and the Transformation of Economic life, 1870-1920. In L. Eskridge, & M. A. Noll, More Money, More Ministery: Money and Evangelicals in Recent North American History (p. Ch. 5). Eerdmans. Hammond, B. (1991). Banks and Politics in America from the Revolution to the Civil War. Princeton University Press . Harris, J. (1990). The Value of Life. London: Routledge. Hessen, R. (1979). In Defense of the Corporation. Hindriks, F. (2013). How Autonomous Are Collective Agents? Corporate Rights and Normative Individualism. Erkenntnis . Hoffman, T. (1993). Animals, Mental Defectives, and the Social Contrac. Between the Species . Holland, A. (1984). On behalf of a Moderate Speciesism. Journal of Applied Philosophy , 1 (2). Holton, R. &. (1999). Empathy and Animal Ethics. In D. Jamieson, Singer and His Critics . Blackwell. Holton, R., & Landon, R. (1999). Empathy and Animal Ethics. In D. Jamieson, Singer and His Critics. Blackwell. Investopedia. (sd). Closely Held Corporation. Opgeroepen op August 7, 2015, van Investopedia: http://www.investopedia.com/terms/c/closely-held-corporation.asp Jamieson, D. (2002). Science, Knowledge, and Animal Minds. In Morality's Progress: Essays on Humans, Other Animals, and the Rest of Nature. Johnson, L. (1991). A Morally Deep World: An Essay on Moral Significance and Environmental Ethics . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant, I. (1785/1948). Groundwork Of The Metaphysic Of Morals. Klinger, S. (2015, April 20). If You Thought Corporate Personhood Was Bad, Wait Until You See Corporate Nationhood in the New Trade Treaty. Opgeroepen op July 24, 2015, van Center for Effective Government: http://www.foreffectivegov.org/blog/if-you-thought- corporate-personhood-was-bad-wait-until-you-see-corporate-nationhood-new-trade-t Krannich, J. M. (2005). The Corporate “Person”: A New Analytical Approach to a Flawed Method of Constitutional Interpretation. Loyola University Chicago Law Review . Kymlicka, W. (1988). Rawls on Teleology and Deontology. Philosophy & Public Affairs , 173. Ladd, J. (1970). Morality and the Ideal of Rationality in Formal Organizations. Monist . Levinas, E. (2004). The Name of a Fog, or Natural Rights. In Calarco, & Atterton, Animal Philosophy: Ethics and Identity. London: Continuum. Liao, S. M., & Etinson, A. (2012). Political and Naturalistic Conceptions of Human Rights: A False Polemic. Journal of Moral Philosophy , 9 (3).

45 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

London, C. o. (2015, June 18). History of the government of the City of London. Opgeroepen op July 13, 2015, van City of London: http://www.cityoflondon.gov.uk/about-the-city/about- us/Pages/history-of-the-government-of-the-city-of-london.aspx MacIntyre, A. (2001). Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues . Open Court Publishing Company. May, L. (1983). Vicarious Agency and Corporate Responsibility. Philosophical Studies . Mayer, C. J. (1990). Personalizing the Impersonal: Corporations and the Bill of Rights. Hastings Law Journal , 41 (3). McFarland, S. E., & Hediger, R. (2009). Animals and Agency: An Interdisciplinary Exploration. Brill. Midgley, M. (2003). Is a Dolphin a Person? In S. Armstrong, & R. Botzler, The Animal Ethics Reader. London: Routledge. Mill, J. S. (1978). On Liberty. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing. Millon, D. (2001). The Ambiguous Significance of Corporate Personhood. Stanford Agora: An Online Journal of Legal Perspectives , 1. Monk, L. (2003). The Words We Live By: Your Annotated Guide to the Consitution. Opgeroepen op May 29, 2015, van National Constitution Center: http://constitutioncenter.org/constitution/the-amendments/amendment-14-citizenship-rights Nagel, T. (1970). The Possibility of Altruism. Nelson, W. E. (1988). The Fourteenth Amendment: From Political Principle to Judicial Doctrine. Harvard University Press. Nesteruk, J. (1990). Persons, Property, and the Corporation: A Proposal for a New Paradigm. DePaul Law Review (133). Nesteruk, J., & Risser, D. (1993). Conceptions of the Corporation and Ethical Decision Making in Business. Business & Professional Ethics Journal . Paul vs. Virginia, 75 US 168 (United States Supreme Court 1868). Pfeiffer, R. S. (1988). The Meaning and Justification of Collective Moral Responsibility. Public Affairs Quarterly . Pico Della Mirandola, G. (1486/1956). Oration On The Dignity Of Man . (R. Caponigri, Vert.) Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: HUP. Rawls, J. (1999). The Law of Peoples. Boston: HUP. Raz, J. (2010). Human Rights Without Foundations. The Philosphy of International Law. Regan, T. (1983). The Case for Animal Rights . Berkeley: University of California Press. Ripken, S. K. (2000). Characteristics of Soulless Persons: The Applicability of the Character Evidence Rule to Corporations, . University of Illinois Law Review .

46 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Ripken, S. K. (2010). Corporations are People Too: A Multi-Dimensional Approach to the Corporate Personhood Puzzle. Fordham Journal of Corporate & Financial Law , 15, 97. Ripken, S. K. (2010). Corporations are People Too: A Multi-Dimensional Approach to the Corporate Personhood Puzzle. . Fordham Journal of Corporate & Financial Law , 15. Risk Encyclopedia. (sd). The History of Corporations. Opgeroepen op August 7, 2015, van Risk Encyclopedia: http://www.riskencyclopedia.com/articles/corporation/ Risser, D. T. (1978). Power and Collective Responsibility. Kinesis . Robinson, G. H. (1936, April). Tort Jurisdiction in American Admiralty. University of Pennsylvania Law Review , 716-756. Ryder, R. D. (2010). Speciesism Again: The Original Leaflet. Critical Society (2). Santa Clara County v. Southern Pacific Railroad (US Supreme Court 1886). Schachter, O. (1983). Human Dignity as a Normative Concept. Schall, J. V. (2006). The Corporation: What Is It?, . Ave MAria Law Review . Scolnicov, A. (2013). Lifelike and lifeless in law: Do corporations have human rights? . University of Cambridge Faculty of Law Research Paper , 12. Shakespeare, W. (1600). Hamlet. Sheffler, S. (1988). Consequentialism and its critics. Oxford University Press. Singer, P. (1985). Persons and non-persons. In In Defense of Animals. Basil Blackwell. Solum, L. B. (2015, January 11). Legal Theory Lexicon 027: Persons and Personhood. Opgeroepen op July 9, 2015, van Legal Theory Lexicon: http://lsolum.typepad.com/legal_theory_lexicon/2004/03/legal_theory_le_2.html Spicker, S. F. (1970). The Philosophy Of The Body: Rejections Of Cartesian Dualism. Taylor, C. (1985). The Concept of a Person. Philosophical Papers , 1. The Economist. (2015, May 9). The Economist. Opgeroepen op July 24, 2015, van Artificial intelligence scares people—excessively so: http://www.economist.com/news/briefing/21650526-artificial-intelligence-scares- peopleexcessively-so-rise-machines The National Archives. (2012). The Constitution: Amendments 11-27. The National Constitution Center. (sd). The 10th Amendment. Opgeroepen op May 29, 2015, van . http://constitutioncenter.org/constitution/the-amendments/amendment-10-powers-of- the-states-and-people The White House. (sd). The Constitution. Opgeroepen op May 29, 2015, van www.whitehouse.gov/1600/constitution Tooley, M. (1987). Abortion and Infanticide. In P. Singer, Applied Ethics. Oxford: OUP. Trustees of Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 17 U.S. 518 (US Supreme Court 1819).

47 MA Thesis Philosophy – Christiaan van der Does de Willebois - 10579907

Turner, K., Giacopassi, D., & Vandiver, M. (2006). Ignoring the Past: Coverage of Slavery and Slave Patrols in Criminal Justice Texts. Journal of Criminal Justice Education , 17 (1), 181-195. Uzgalis, W. (2015, Summer). John Locke. (E. N. Zalta, Red.) Opgeroepen op July 7, 2015, van The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke/supplement.html VanDeVeer, D. (1995). Interspecies Justice and Intrinsic Value. The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy , 3. Vasak, K. (1979). Pour Une Troisième Génération Des Droits De L’homme. (C. Swinarsk, Red.) Studies and Essays On International Humanitarian Law And Red Cross Principles . Warren, M. A. (1997). On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion. In H. Lafolette, Ethics in Practice. Oxford: Blackwell. Werhane, P. W. (1989). Corporate and Individual Moral Responsibility: A Reply to Jan Garrett. Journal of Business Ethics . Wetlesen, J. (1999). The Moral Status of Beings who are not Persons. Environmental Values , 8 (3). Williams, B. (1972). Morality. Cambridge University Press. Wilson, P. E. (1992). Barring Corporations from the Moral Community—The Concept and the Cost. Journal of Social Philosophy . Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Philosophical Investigations . Oxford: Basil Blackwell Ltd. Wolgast, E. (1992). Ethics Of An Artificial Person: Lost Responsibility. Professions And Organizations . Young, E. H. (1912/2014). Foreign Companies and Other Corporations. Cambridge University Press.

48