Philippe Mongin 1950–2020
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Dear Friends, It Is with an Immense Sadness That the French-Speaking Community of Philosophers of Economics and Historians of E
Dear friends, It is with an immense sadness that the French-speaking community of philosophers of economics and historians of economic thought learned that Philippe Mongin had passed away after a long medical fight on August 5 2020. Born in 1950, Philippe had always been an extremely brilliant student. He entered the Literature and Philosophy department of the prestigious French Ecole Normale Supérieure in 1969. In 1973 he was successful at the “agrégation” in Philosophy, and begun a Ph.D. thesis in Social Sciences at the Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales (EHESS) under Raymond Aron, on Marx’s 1857 and 1858 manuscripts - the Grundrisse: La critique de l'économie politique dans les Grundrisse de Karl Marx. Visiting scholar at King’s College, Cambridge, between 1975 and 1978, he was close to Frank Hahn and became interested in recent macro and microeconomic theory. Back to France, he worked in the 1980s on Herbert Simon’s notion of bounded rationality (see his « Simon, Stigler et les théories de la rationalité limitée », Social Science Information, 1986). In 1984, he received a new degree in Mathematics and defended a second Ph.D. thesis in Economics. In the 1990s, following Amartya Sen’s work, he focused on normative economics, more specifically on the subjects of collective preferences under uncertainty (see his « Factoring out the impossibility of logical aggregation », Journal of Economic Theory, 2008), and on John Harsanyi’s reformulation of utilitarianism. Between 1991 and 1996, he was appointed as invited professor at the University of Louvain-la-Neuve, where he co-authored some work with Claude d’Aspremont on the philosophical foundations of utility theory (see Philippe Mongin and Claude d'Aspremont, « Utility Theory and Ethics », Handbook of Utility Theory, Kluwer, 1998, ch. -
Philippe Mongin (1950-2020)
Economics & Philosophy (2020), 36, 331–333 doi:10.1017/S0266267120000309 OBITUARY Philippe Mongin (1950–2020) Daniel Hausman 15 August 2020 On 5 August, the philosophy of economics community at large and Economics and Philosophy in particular lost one of their leading figures, Philippe Mongin, who edited this journal from 1995 to 2000. Through his illness, which he bore without complaint, Philippe retained his remarkable productivity and enthusiasm for issues at the boundaries between economics and philosophy, publishing here just last November an insightful retrospective on the Allais paradox, ‘The Allais Paradox: What it Became, What it Was, What it Now Suggests to Us’.Thisisnot all: Philippe also has a paper that is just out in Philosophy of Science, and papers forthcoming at Economic Theory and Synthese. An alumnus of the Ecole normale supérieure (ENS), Philippe began his remarkable intellectual path as a PhD student of Raymond Aron at the Ecole des hautes études en sciences sociales (EHESS), completing a dissertation in 1978 on Marx’s Grundrisse, ‘La critique de l’économie politique dans les Grundrisse de Karl Marx’. (At the time, the Grundrisse attracted a great deal of attention, with the first translation into English in 1973.) Having completed his dissertation, Philippe reoriented his research from the intersection of classical political economy and philosophy to topics in economic theory, in which he became interested while visiting Cambridge in the mid to late 1970s, where he was particularly influenced by Frank Hahn. Part of what made this change in direction possible was an early career position at the CNRS (Centre national de la recherche scientifique) through which he advanced, becoming eventually Directeur de recherche de classe exceptionnelle. -
Interview of Peter J. Hammond Philippe Mongin, Mongin@Greg
Interview of Peter J. Hammond Philippe Mongin, [email protected] GREGHEC, CNRS & HEC Paris 1 rue de la Lib´eration,F-78350 Jouy-en-Josas, France 2019 January 25th, typeset from interviewSCandW+++.tex Abstract: Following an initiative of Social Choice and Welfare, this is the result of an interview conducted by email exchange during the period from July 2017 to February 2018, with minor adjustments later in 2018. Apart from some personal history, topics discussed include: (i) social choice, es- pecially with interpersonal comparisons of utility; (ii) utilitarianism, includ- ing Harsanyi's contributions; (iii) consequentialism in decision theory and in ethics; (iv) the independence axiom for decisions under risk; (v) welfare economics under uncertainty; (vi) incentive compatibility and strategy-proof mechanisms, especially in large economies; (vii) Pareto gains from trade, and from migration; (viii) cost{benefit analysis and welfare measurement; (ix) the possible future of normative economics. Acknowledgements The two of us both thank Marc Fleurbaey for his initiative, encouragement and forbearance, as well as for helpful editorial comments on an earlier draft. Philippe Mongin (PM): The important contributions you made to social choice theory, welfare economics, and social ethics are knit together by some common theoretical ideas, which I would suggest we take up successively in this discussion. I have selected in order, interpersonal comparisons of utility, utilitarianism, consequentialism, welfare economics under uncertainty, and incentive compatibility. Would you agree with this list and this order? What could come first, however, is some kind of intellectual biography. Perhaps you could explain to us how you first became interested in these topics and how they permeated your later academic life. -
The Possibility of Sociai Choice^
The Possibility of Sociai Choice^ By AMARTYA SEN* "A camel," it has been said, "is a horse de- predicaments of the different individuals within signed by a committee." This might sound like the society? How can we find any rational basis a telling example of the terrible deficiencies of for making such aggregative judgements as "the committee decisions, but it is really much too society prefers this to that," or "the society mild an indictment. A camel may not have the should choose this over that," or "this is socially speed of a horse, but it is a very useful and right"? Is reasonable social choice at all possi- harmonious animal—well coordinated to travel ble, especially since, as Horace noted a long long distances without food and water. A com- time ago, there may be "as many preferences as mittee that tries to reflect the diverse wishes of there are people"? its different members in designing a horse could very easily end up with something far less I. Social Choice Theory congruous: perhaps a centaur of Greek myth- ology, half a horse and half something else—a In this lecture, I shall try to discuss some mercurial creation combining savagery with challenges and foundational problems faced by confusion. social choice theory as a discipline.' The imme- The difficulty that a small committee experi- diate occasion for this lecture is, of course, an ences may be only greater when it comes to award, and I am aware that I am expected to decisions of a sizable society, reflecting the discuss, in one form or another, my own work choices "of the people, by the people, for the associated with this event (however immodest people." That, broadly speaking, is the subject that attempt might otherwise have been). -
Philippe Mongin (1950–2020)
Economics & Philosophy (2020), 36, 331–333 doi:10.1017/S0266267120000309 OBITUARY Philippe Mongin (1950–2020) Daniel Hausman 15 August 2020 On 5 August, the philosophy of economics community at large and Economics and Philosophy in particular lost one of their leading figures, Philippe Mongin, who edited this journal from 1995 to 2000. Through his illness, which he bore without complaint, Philippe retained his remarkable productivity and enthusiasm for issues at the boundaries between economics and philosophy, publishing here just last November an insightful retrospective on the Allais paradox, ‘The Allais Paradox: What it Became, What it Was, What it Now Suggests to Us’.Thisisnot all: Philippe also has a paper that is just out in Philosophy of Science, and papers forthcoming at Economic Theory and Synthese. An alumnus of the Ecole normale supérieure (ENS), Philippe began his remarkable intellectual path as a PhD student of Raymond Aron at the Ecole des hautes études en sciences sociales (EHESS), completing a dissertation in 1978 on Marx’s Grundrisse, ‘La critique de l’économie politique dans les Grundrisse de Karl Marx’. (At the time, the Grundrisse attracted a great deal of attention, with the first translation into English in 1973.) Having completed his dissertation, Philippe reoriented his research from the intersection of classical political economy and philosophy to topics in economic theory, in which he became interested while visiting Cambridge in the mid to late 1970s, where he was particularly influenced by Frank Hahn. Part of what made this change in direction possible was an early career position at the CNRS (Centre national de la recherche scientifique) through which he advanced, becoming eventually Directeur de recherche de classe exceptionnelle. -
The Positive and the Normative in Economic Thought.Pdf
The Positive and the Normative in Economic Thought Conference organized with the support of Collège International de Philosophie (CIPH) and CAPhi (University of Nantes) 16-18 December 2020, Paris The significant divergences that exist between different schools of economic thought seem to make dialogue between them very difficult. In view of the different theoretical and philosophical presuppositions of these schools, how can one imagine any form of discussion between the classical school, the Marxian school, the Austrian school, the Neoclassical school, the neo-Ricardian School, the Keynesian school, the Historical school, or Institutionalism? The present conference aims to discuss this observation on the basis of a hypothesis. Provided that these schools are studied not through the prism of their theoretical contents, but from the point of view of the way they analyze the relationship between description and prescription, between what is and what ought to be, many common points between these approaches emerge, including a shared thesis: the development of positive economics is the only way to resolve disagreements on normative issues. Indeed, if we start from the distinction between positive economics and normative economics, systematically theorized in the works of John Neville Keynes (Keynes 1890) – according to which positive economics, as distinct from normative economics, consists in dealing with what is, in contrast to normative economics, which deals with what ought to be – important similarities between different schools of economic thought and thinkers belonging to these schools can be found, for example between Milton Friedman, Ludwig von Mises and Karl Marx. All three thinkers agree that the positive representation of existing economic reality should be at the heart of economic thinking, and they all subordinate, albeit in different ways, normative economics to the analysis of the existing economic situation. -
LE PARADOXE D'allais Document Téléchargé Depuis - Lazar Seth 150.203.229.102 24/06/2015 08H07
LE PARADOXE D'ALLAIS Document téléchargé depuis www.cairn.info - Lazar Seth 150.203.229.102 24/06/2015 08h07. © Presses de Sciences Po (P.F.N.S.P.) Comment lui rendre sa signification perdue ? Philippe Mongin Presses de Sciences Po (P.F.N.S.P.) | « Revue économique » 2014/5 Vol. 65 | pages 743 à 779 ISSN 0035-2764 ISBN 9782724633665 Article disponible en ligne à l'adresse : -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- http://www.cairn.info/revue-economique-2014-5-page-743.htm -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Pour citer cet article : -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Philippe Mongin, « Le paradoxe d'Allais. Comment lui rendre sa signification perdue ? », Revue économique 2014/5 (Vol. 65), p. 743-779. DOI 10.3917/reco.655.0743 -------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Distribution électronique Cairn.info pour Presses de Sciences Po (P.F.N.S.P.). © Presses de Sciences Po (P.F.N.S.P.). Tous droits réservés pour tous pays. La reproduction ou représentation de cet article, notamment par photocopie, n'est autorisée que dans les limites des conditions générales d'utilisation du site ou, le cas échéant, des conditions générales de la licence souscrite par votre établissement. Toute autre reproduction ou représentation, en tout ou partie,