The Positive and the Normative in Economic Thought.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Positive and the Normative in Economic Thought.Pdf The Positive and the Normative in Economic Thought Conference organized with the support of Collège International de Philosophie (CIPH) and CAPhi (University of Nantes) 16-18 December 2020, Paris The significant divergences that exist between different schools of economic thought seem to make dialogue between them very difficult. In view of the different theoretical and philosophical presuppositions of these schools, how can one imagine any form of discussion between the classical school, the Marxian school, the Austrian school, the Neoclassical school, the neo-Ricardian School, the Keynesian school, the Historical school, or Institutionalism? The present conference aims to discuss this observation on the basis of a hypothesis. Provided that these schools are studied not through the prism of their theoretical contents, but from the point of view of the way they analyze the relationship between description and prescription, between what is and what ought to be, many common points between these approaches emerge, including a shared thesis: the development of positive economics is the only way to resolve disagreements on normative issues. Indeed, if we start from the distinction between positive economics and normative economics, systematically theorized in the works of John Neville Keynes (Keynes 1890) – according to which positive economics, as distinct from normative economics, consists in dealing with what is, in contrast to normative economics, which deals with what ought to be – important similarities between different schools of economic thought and thinkers belonging to these schools can be found, for example between Milton Friedman, Ludwig von Mises and Karl Marx. All three thinkers agree that the positive representation of existing economic reality should be at the heart of economic thinking, and they all subordinate, albeit in different ways, normative economics to the analysis of the existing economic situation. For Friedman, normative economics depends on positive economics because decisions about economic policy are based on predicting the consequences of a given fact on the basis of positive economics (Friedman 1953). Only the progress of positive economics can thus resolve disagreements about which new economic policies should be implemented. For Mises, it is the positive analysis of the a priori structure of human action that can contribute to the formulation of different – mostly negative – proposals regarding what can and ought to be done in the economic field (Mises 1949). Otherwise, normative proposals to change the economic situation may be futile or have catastrophic consequences. As for Marx, he intends to develop a critical economic analysis of what he calls the capitalist mode of production that would be immanent, i.e. non-normative, in order to avoid the pitfall encountered by critical-utopian socialists and communists (Marx & Engels 1848, 72). Indeed, Marx judges the critical plans of these thinkers to rectify existing social injustices “fanatical and superstitious” (Marx and Engels 1848, 75). By establishing normative ideas in a speculative manner, without grounding them objectively, these thinkers render them purely i subjective and impotent (Hegel 1991, 302-3). Considering that only ideas whose seeds are hidden in existing reality should be taken seriously (Marx & Engels 1976, 92), Marx refuses to propose alternative normative ideas and instead studies positive reality in order to identify such seeds for overcoming this reality. By providing a forum for discussion between these schools on the relatively secondary role attributed to normative economics, this conference will attempt to debate the relevance of enhancing the value of normative approaches in economics, with particular emphasis on their philosophical and epistemological foundations. More specifically, its central issue will be to study how various attempts to reduce normative economics to positive economics can nourish a reflection on normative approaches in economics. While normative economics is concerned with creating frameworks for advancing the resolution of normative disagreements, it cannot ignore various forms of knowledge developed in positive economics. The challenge, therefore, is to identify the relationship between normative approaches in economics and positive economics, and to explore the implications of such a relationship for contemporary political philosophy and contemporary theories of justice. This conference has a twofold objective: 1) On the one hand, it aims to provide a space for dialogue between economic schools that seem to be far removed from each other, while at the same time highlighting the debates on the relationship between positive and normative in each of these schools. With regard to the Marxian school, it can thus be noted that the epistemological approach of some thinkers belonging to the so-called “analytical” current of Marxism (notably Roemer (Roemer 1982), Elster (Elster 1985), and Buchanan (Buchanan 1982)) cannot be reduced to that of Marx. Moreover, the inflection of Marxian thought among certain critical theorists (Adorno, Horkheimer) leads to the development of a form of normativity linked to the reworking of the concept of justice (Horkheimer, 1937/1970), which articulates the normative approach with a positive interdisciplinary approach within the Institute for Social Research (Horkheimer, 1932 and 1937) and with a reflection on the motif of utopia (Adorno and Bloch, 1964; Adorno, 1966; Abensour 2000 & 2009). The question of the normative foundations of critique thus tends to gain momentum in this critical theory of society (Habermas, 1981; Honneth, 1992 & 2000). Within the Chicago School, Friedman’s epistemological positions are markedly different from the epistemological approach of one of the founders of the Chicago School, Frank Hyneman Knight, as well as that of James Buchanan. Finally, in the Austrian school, the apriorist approach of Mises differs considerably from that defended by Hayek in his Law, Legislation and Liberty, as well as from those of Menger and Böhm-Bawerk. 2) On the other hand, this conference intends to open a discussion on different ways of establishing a relationship between positive economics and normative economics, without reducing one to the other or diminishing the importance of one to the benefit of the other. It aims to develop, through this perspective, a field of discussion between various schools of economic thought that are believed to be radically heterogeneous, and to establish a dialogue with contemporary theories of justice and contemporary political philosophy. ii The conference will be organized around five main research axes: 1. The various ways in which the relationship between positive economics and normative economics has been theorized within economic thinking, both in the past and today. 2. Approaches that have given more weight to normative economics and have had an influence on contemporary political philosophy (e.g. welfare economics, public economics, normative constitutional economics, the capability approach, social choice theory, various theories of justice etc.). 3. The way in which the weight given to the positive approach in Marx, Mises and Friedman has been debated by the very heirs of these approaches (in Marxism for example with the Frankfurt School, in the Austrian School for example with Hayek, and in the Chicago School for example with James Buchanan). 4. The various approaches and theories, such as those of Foucault and Putnam, which have tried to question the very possibility of distinguishing between facts and values, between the study of positivity and the study of normativity. The impact of this type of critique on normative economics, and the need to create a theoretical framework that can help us resolve disagreements about what needs to be done will be discussed 5. The impact of various ways of theorizing the relationship between positive and normative economics on the question of expertise in economics, and on the role that economics, as an academic discipline, should play in political decision-making. The conference will be held over four half-days (one afternoon, one full day, and one morning), with presentations in French and English. Researchers who have already confirmed their participation are: 1. Étienne Balibar (Kingston University) 2. Antoinette Baujard (Université Jean Monnet & GATE Lyon Saint-Etienne). 3. Gilles Campagnolo (CNRS and the Aix-Marseille School of Economics) 4. Muriel Gilardone (Université de Caen) 5. Uskali Mäki (University of Helsinki) 6. Magdalena Malecka (University of Helsinki & IAS, Princeton) 7. Philippe Mongin (CNRS & HEC Paris) 8. Emmanuel Picavet (Université Panthéon-Sorbonne) 9. Jesús Zamora Bonilla (Universidad Nacional de Educación a Distancia) iii References • ABENSOUR, M., Pour une philosophie politique critique, Paris, Sens & Tonka, 2000. • BAUJARD, A., “Welfare Economics”, in: Handbook on the History of Economic Analysis, Volume III (edited by Faccarello, G., & Kurz, H. D.), Cheltenham, Edward Elgar Publishing Limited, 2016, pp. 611-623. • BRENNAN, G., & BUCHANAN, J. M., The Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1986. • BUCHANAN, A. E., Marx and Justice: The Radical Critique of Liberalism, Totowa, New Jersey, Rowman and Littlefield, 1982. • BUCHANAN, A. E., “Marx, Morality, and History: An Assessment of Recent Analytical Work on Marx”, Ethics 98, 1987, N. 1, pp. 104-136. • CAMPAGNOLO, G., & GHARBI, J. S., Philosophie économique.
Recommended publications
  • The Capability Approach an Interdisciplinary Introduction
    The Capability Approach An Interdisciplinary Introduction Ingrid Robeyns Version August 14th, 2017 Draft Book Manuscript Not for further circulation, please. Revising will start on September 22nd, 2017. Comments welcome, E: [email protected] 1 Table of Contents 1 Introduction ................................................................................................................ 5 1.1 Why the capability approach? ................................................................................. 5 1.2 The worries of the sceptics ....................................................................................... 7 1.3 A yardstick for the evaluation of prosperity and progress ........................... 9 1.4 Scope and development of the capability approach ...................................... 13 1.5 A guide to the reader ................................................................................................ 16 2 Core ideas and the framework .......................................................................... 18 2.1 Introduction ................................................................................................................ 18 2.2 A preliminary definition of the capability approach ..................................... 20 2.3 The capability approach versus capability theories ...................................... 24 2.4 The many modes of capability analysis ............................................................. 26 2.5 The modular view of the capability approach ................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Welfare Economy
    Welfare Economy Chapter 1 Welfare, an individual and collective concept We present what is welfare for economists, we elaborate the bedrock of normative economics Winter 2019 Université de Tours - A. Chassagnon Welfare Economics Welfare economics aims to define and to measure social welfare, and to provide evaluations of public policies. A typical question : between different economic situations, more precisely, between different resource allocations, which is the best ? It follows that a deep critical analysis of the instruments is required in that field. Individual and collective welfare First, the welfare should be defined at the individual level. There are many measures It could be a declarative measure : how do you feel your welfare is ? It could be the utility of consumption : What bundle do you prefer ? Second, the welfare should be defined at the collective level There are many measures From a qualitative point of vue, definition of the Pareto optimal allocations From a quantitative point of vue, consider weighted average of the utilities Vocabulary All of those words should be reviewed (in textbooks or in wikipedia) • declarative measure • Bundle (of goods) • weighted average • qualitative measure • quantitative measure • Welfare • Utility function • Allocation (of resources) Map of the talk 1) Individual welfare Declarative welfare, Happiness, Utility functions Time and Inter-country comparisons 2) Collective welfare Pareto optimal (or efficient) allocations Social Welfare Functions and utilities 1a. Individual welfare Declarative welfare, Happiness, Happiness Given its very nature, reported happiness is subjective. It is difficult to compare one person’s happiness with another’s It can be especially difficult to compare happiness across cultures One concern has always been the accuracy and reliability of people’s responses to happiness surveys.
    [Show full text]
  • The Capability Approach and the Right to Education for Persons with Disabilities
    Social Inclusion (ISSN: 2183–2803) 2018, Volume 6, Issue 1, Pages 29–39 DOI: 10.17645/si.v6i1.1193 Article Equality of What? The Capability Approach and the Right to Education for Persons with Disabilities Andrea Broderick Department of International and European Law, Maastricht University, 6211 LH Maastricht, The Netherlands; E-Mail: [email protected] Submitted: 29 September 2017 | Accepted: 27 December 2017 | Published: 26 March 2018 Abstract The right to education is indispensable in unlocking other substantive human rights and in ensuring full and equal partici- pation of persons with disabilities in mainstream society. The cornerstone of Article 24 of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities seeks to ensure access to inclusive education for persons with disabilities on an equal basis with others as well as the full development of human potential. Since the adoption of the Convention, there has been much theorising about inclusive education; however, there has been little focus on the meaning of equal- ity in the context of the right to education for persons with disabilities. The capability approach, developed by Amartya Sen and further refined by Martha Nussbaum, focuses on ensuring equality and developing human potential. It is of- ten viewed as a tool that can be used to overcome the limitations of traditional equality assessments in the educational sphere, which only measure resources and outcomes. This article explores whether the capability approach can offer new insights into the vision of educational equality contained in the Convention and how that vision can be implemented at the national level.
    [Show full text]
  • How Far Is Vienna from Chicago? an Essay on the Methodology of Two Schools of Dogmatic Liberalism
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Paqué, Karl-Heinz Working Paper — Digitized Version How far is Vienna from Chicago? An essay on the methodology of two schools of dogmatic liberalism Kiel Working Paper, No. 209 Provided in Cooperation with: Kiel Institute for the World Economy (IfW) Suggested Citation: Paqué, Karl-Heinz (1984) : How far is Vienna from Chicago? An essay on the methodology of two schools of dogmatic liberalism, Kiel Working Paper, No. 209, Kiel Institute of World Economics (IfW), Kiel This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/46781 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu Kieler Arbeitspapiere Kiel Working Papers Working Paper No.
    [Show full text]
  • The Capability Approach: Its Development, Critiques and Recent Advances
    An ESRC Research Group The Capability Approach: Its Development, Critiques and Recent Advances GPRG-WPS-032 David A. Clark Global Poverty Research Group Website: http://www.gprg.org/ The support of the Economic and Social Research Council (ESRC) is gratefully acknowledged. The work was part of the programme of the ESRC Global Poverty Research Group. 1 The Capability Approach: Its Development, Critiques and Recent Advances By David A. Clark* Over the last decade Amartya Sen’s Capability Approach (CA) has emerged as the leading alternative to standard economic frameworks for thinking about poverty, inequality and human development generally. In countless articles and several books that tackle a range of economic, social and ethical questions (beginning with the Tanner Lecture ‘Equality of What?’ delivered at Stanford University in 1979), Professor Sen has developed, refined and defended a framework that is directly concerned with human capability and freedom (e.g. Sen, 1980; 1984; 1985; 1987; 1992; 1999). From the outset Sen acknowledged strong connections with Adam Smith’s (1776) analysis of ‘necessities’ and living conditions and Karl Marx’s (1844) concern with human freedom and emancipation. Later Sen (1993, p.46) recognised that ‘the most powerful conceptual connections’ (which he initially failed to appreciate) relate to Aristotle’s theory of ‘political distribution’ and his analysis of eudaimonia – ‘human flourishing’ (see Nussbaum, 1988; 1990). While the roots of the CA can be traced back to Aristotle, Classical Political Economy and Marx, it is possible to identify more recent links. For example, Sen often notes that Rawls’s Theory of Justice (1971) and his emphasis on ‘self-respect’ and access to primary goods has ‘deeply influenced’ the CA (Sen, 1992, p.8).
    [Show full text]
  • Public Choice, Constitutional Political Economy and Law and Economics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Papers in Economics 0610 PUBLIC CHOICE, CONSTITUTIONAL POLITICAL ECONOMY AND LAW AND ECONOMICS Ludwig Van den Hauwe Brussels, Belgium © Copyright 1999 Ludwig Van den Hauwe Abstract The various subdisciplines within the emerging ‘new institutionalism’ in economics all draw special attention to the legal-political constraints within which economic and political agents choose and therefore represent a return of economics to its appropriate legal foundations. By changing the name of his research programme to constitutional political economy Buchanan distanced himself from those parts of the public choice literature that remained too close to the traditional welfare economics approach. This chapter draws lessons for law and economics from recent developments in the re-emerging field of constitutional political economy. CPE compares alternative sets of institutional arrangements, in markets and the polity, and their outcomes, using ‘democratic consent’ as an internal standard of comparison. The chapter discusses the methodological foundation of the CPE approach, presents Buchanan’s reconstruction of the Coase theorem along subjectivist-contractarian lines and gives an overview of recent contributions to the literature. JEL classification: B41, D70, H10 Keywords: Constitutional Economics, Constitutional Political Economy, Public Choice, James M. Buchanan, Methodological Foundation A. The Manifold Legacy of Adam Smith 1. Introduction As the title of this chapter suggests, the new law and economics movement on the one hand and the now rapidly emerging field of constitutional political economy - as well as the somewhat older public choice branch of economics from which it emerged - on the other hand, are research traditi- ons that are in some respects genuinely related.
    [Show full text]
  • A New Normative Economics for the Formation of Shared Social Values
    1 1 A new normative economics for the formation of shared social values 2 Neil Ravenscroft 3 School of Environment & Technology, University of Brighton, Lewes Road, Brighton BN2 4 4GJ, UK 5 6 [email protected] 7 Introduction 8 9 It is widely accepted that transition towards a more sustainable society is in part dependent 10 upon an ability to link scientific knowledges - generated in fields such as sustainability 11 science - with socio-political actions that foster sustainable outcomes. For Miller, et al (2014: 12 p.239), this is about strengthening ‘… the role of values in science and decision-making for 13 sustainability,’ while for Rodriguez-Morales and Rawluk (this issue), it is primarily about the 14 deployment of political power in sustainability decision-making processes. In their work, 15 Westberg and Polk (2016) argue that this is about catalysing knowledge exchange between 16 sustainability science and society in such a way that new composite, socially constructed, 17 knowledges are generated that can inform the development of sustainability policy. As 18 Rawluk, et al (this issue) argue, this revolves around complex social-ecological 19 conceptualisations of values that inform the resource trade-offs that society is prepared to 20 accept in pursuit of sustainability, with the fundamental question being one of how choices 21 are made about these trade-offs (see also Anderson, et al, 2015, 2016). 22 23 Conventionally, in neoclassical economics, the social welfare questions raised by the pursuit 24 of sustainability have been addressed by reference to the aggregation of individual 25 preferences – often expressed and captured through market mechanisms (Bartkowski and 26 Lienhoop, 2018).
    [Show full text]
  • Values in Welfare Economics Antoinette Baujard
    Values in Welfare economics Antoinette Baujard To cite this version: Antoinette Baujard. Values in Welfare economics. 2021. halshs-03244909 HAL Id: halshs-03244909 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-03244909 Preprint submitted on 1 Jun 2021 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. WP 2112 – June 2021 Values in Welfare economics Antoinette Baujard Abstract: This chapter focuses on the inner rationale and consequences of four different archetypal positions regarding how ethical and political values are tackled in welfare economics. Welfare economics is standardly associated with the welfarist framework, for which social welfare is based on individual utility only. Beyond this, we distinguish the value-neutrality claim – for which ethical values should be and are out of the scope of welfare economics –, the value confinement ideal – for which ethical values are acceptable if they are minimal and consensual–, the transparency requirement – for which any ethical values may be acceptable in the welfare economics framework if explicit and formalized –, and the entanglement claim – which challenges the very possibility of demarcation between facts and values. Keywords: Welfare economics, facts and values, value judgement, welfarism, transparency, demarcation, normative and positive, neutrality JEL codes: B41, D60, D63 Values in Welfare economics1 By Antoinette Baujard2 Abstract.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoliberal Reason and Its Forms: Depoliticization Through Economization∗
    Neoliberal reason and its forms: Depoliticization through economization∗ Yahya M. Madra Department of Economics Boğaziçi University Bebek, 34342, Istanbul, Turkey [email protected] Yahya M. Madra studied economics in Istanbul and Amherst, Massachusetts. He has taught at the universities of Massachusetts and Boğaziçi, and at Skidmore and Gettysburg Colleges. He currently conducts research in history of modern economics at Boğaziçi University with the support of TÜBITAK-BIDEB Scholarship. His work appeared in Journal of Economic Issues, Rethinking Marxism, The European Journal of History of Economic Thought, Psychoanalysis, Society, Culture and Subjectivity as well as edited volumes. His current research is on the role of subjectivity in political economy of capitalism and post-capitalism. and Fikret Adaman Department of Economics, Boğaziçi University Bebek, 34342, Istanbul, Turkey [email protected] Fikret Adaman studied economics in Istanbul and Manchester. He has been lecturing at Boğaziçi University on political economy, ecological economics and history of economics. His work appeared in Journal of Economic Issues, New Left Review, Cambridge Journal of Economics, Economy and Society, Ecological Economics, The European Journal of History of Economic Thought, Energy Policy and Review of Political Economy as well as edited volumes. His current research is on the political ecology of Turkey. DRAFT: Istanbul, October 3, 2012 ∗ Earlier versions of this paper have been presented in departmental and faculty seminars at Gettysburg College, Uludağ University, Boğaziçi University, İstanbul University, University of Athens, and New School University. The authors would like to thank the participants of those seminars as well as to Jack Amariglio, Michel Callon, Pat Devine, Harald Hagemann, Stavros Ioannides, Ayşe Mumcu, Ceren Özselçuk, Maliha Safri, Euclid Tsakalatos, Yannis Varoufakis, Charles Weise, and Ünal Zenginobuz for their thoughtful comments and suggestions on the various versions of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • 73 on Feminist Economics J
    Indira mva/ Art No. ppl_fr_9400065 1^17 73 j on feminist economics Wilfred Dolfsma and Hella Hoppe abstract Feminist economics rightfully draws increasing attention from professional, mainstream economists. In this paper, we argue that one of the reasons for this is its increasingly coherent perspective on economic phenomena, challenging what is often perceived to be the staid mainstream of economic thought. We discuss methodological issues, some theoretical developments – notably on the household – and issues of economic policy. Feminist economics is argued to make important contributions, not least in the potential to provide suggestions for policy. We point to parallels between feminist economics and institutional economics, and argue that these relations might be strengthened to the benefit of both. keywords feminist economics; review; institutional economics; methodology; economic policy; economics of the household; institutions of the labour market feminist review 73 2003 1 (00–00) c 2003 Feminist Review. 0141-7789/03 $15 www.feminist-review.com introduction Over one and a half centuries ago, Charles Fourier ventured the view that the position of women in a society is an indicator of the general quality of its social system (Fourier, 1846: 132). He seems to have been somebody with insight, or at least foresight. Over the last few decades, according to Fourier’s index, many Western societies have progressed substantially. The progress has not been uni- directional, however. In more recent times, however, some deterioration can perhaps be observed. This article looks at the recent development of feminist economic thought and the extent to which government policy seems to have paid heed.
    [Show full text]
  • Capitalism and Morality ______
    Capitalism and Morality _________________________ Carl Menger and Milton Friedman: Two Men Two Methods Two Schools Two Paths to Free Markets Brandon W. Holmes Wheeling Jesuit University Graduate 2006 History of Economic Thought Class, Dr. Younkins, April 19, 2006 Of the economists who defend the free market, there are two schools. One is the Austrian school and the other is the Chicago school. The two schools together rightly recognize the superiority of free market economy in both conforming to man’s nature and promoting his well-being. While scholars in the two schools agree on the superiority of the free market they differ, sometimes greatly, on their choice of method and argument that they use to discern, promote and defend its principles. These similarities and differences show themselves in the works of two scholars, Carl Menger and Milton Friedman, whose works comprise two paths to liberty; each path having its strengths and weaknesses. In addition to the significance of these paths to those interested in defending the free market, an understanding of them is also important to anyone seriously interested in political economy. Carl Menger: Solid Foundations of the Theoretical Austrian The Austrian school began with the works of economic philosopher Carl Menger in Vienna in the late Nineteenth century. His Principles of Economics broke new ground and laid the foundation for one of the most influential schools of economics ever founded when published in 1871. According to Younkins, Menger “destroyed the existing structure of economic science and, including both its theory and methodology, and put it on totally new foundations” (Younkins 2005, 17).
    [Show full text]
  • A Theorem on the Methodology of Positive Economics Eduardo Pol University of Wollongong, [email protected]
    University of Wollongong Research Online Faculty of Business - Papers Faculty of Business 2015 A theorem on the methodology of positive economics Eduardo Pol University of Wollongong, [email protected] Publication Details Pol, E. (2015). A theorem on the methodology of positive economics. Cogent Economics & Finance, 3 (1), 1054142-1-1054142-13. Research Online is the open access institutional repository for the University of Wollongong. For further information contact the UOW Library: [email protected] A theorem on the methodology of positive economics Abstract It has long been recognized that the Milton Friedman's 1953 essay on economic methodology (or F53, for short) displays open-ended unclarities. For example, the notion of "unrealistic assumption" plays a role of absolutely fundamental importance in his methodological framework, but the term itself was never unambiguously defined in any of the Friedman's contributions to the economics discipline. As a result, F53 is appealing and liberating because the choice of premises in economic theorizing is not subject to any constraints concerning the degree of realisticness (or unrealisticness) of the assumptions. The question: "Does the methodology of positive economics prevent the overlapping between economics and science fiction?" comes very naturally, indeed. In this paper, we show the following theorem: the Friedman's methodology of positive economics does not exclude science fiction. This theorem is a positive statement, and consequently, it does not involve value judgements. However, it throws a wrench on the formulation of economic policy based on surreal models. Keywords theorem, economics, methodology, positive Disciplines Business Publication Details Pol, E. (2015). A theorem on the methodology of positive economics.
    [Show full text]