Sums and Products

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sums and Products 1-27-2019 Sums and Products In this section, I’ll review the notation for sums and products. Addition and multiplication are binary operations: They operate on two numbers at a time. If you want to add or multiply more than two numbers, you need to group the numbers so that you’re only adding or multiplying two at once. Addition and multiplication are associative, so it should not matter how I group the numbers when I add or multiply. Now associativity holds for three numbers at a time; for instance, for addition, a +(b + c)=(a + b)+ c. But why does this work for (say) two ways of grouping a sum of 100 numbers? It turns out that, using induction, it’s possible to prove that any two ways of grouping a sum or product of n numbers, for n 3, give the same result. ≥ Taking this for granted, I can define the sum of a list of numbers a1,a2,...an recursively as follows. A sum of a single number is just the number: { } 1 ai = a1. i=1 X I know how to add two numbers: 2 ai = a1 + a2. i=1 X To add n numbers for n> 2, I add the first n 1 of them (which I assume I already know how to do), then add the nth: − n n−1 ai = ai + an. i=1 i=1 X X Note that this is a particular way of grouping the n summands: Make one group with the first n 1, and add it to the last term. By associativity (as noted above), this way of grouping the sum should give− the same result as any other way. Therefore, I might as well omit parentheses and write n ai = a1 + a2 + + an. ··· i=1 X The product of a list of numbers a1,a2,...an is defined recursively in a similar way. A product of a single number is just{ the number:} 1 ai = a1. i=1 Y I know how to multiply two numbers: 2 ai = a1 a2. · i=1 Y To multiply n numbers for n > 2, I multiply the first n 1 of them (which I assume I already know how to do), then multiply the nth: − n n−1 ai = ai an. · i=1 i=1 Y Y 1 Again, I can drop the parentheses and write n ai = a1 a2 an. · ····· i=1 Y Remark. Some people define the sum and product of no numbers as follows: The sum of no numbers (sometimes called the empty sum is defined to be 0, and the product of no numbers (sometimes called the empty product) is defined to be 1. These definitions are useful when you’re taking the sum or product of numbers in a set, rather than the sum or product of numbers indexed by a range of consecutive integers. For example, suppose S = 1, 4, 9, 13 . Then to use summation notation to write the sum of the squares of the elements of S, you might{ write } x2 to mean 12 + 42 + 92 + 132. x∈S X Similarly, to write the product of the reciprocals of the numbers in S, you might write 1 1 1 1 1 to mean . x 1 · 4 · 9 · 13 x∈S Y If the set containing the elements of the sum or product varies in a discussion, it might happen that the containing set is empty. Using the definitions for an empty sum or an empty product allows for this case. For instance, x2 = 0. ∈∅ Xx That is, the sum of the squares of the elements of the empty set is 0. The following properties and those for products which are given below are fairly obvious, but careful proofs require induction. Proposition. (Properties of sums) n n n (a) (ai + bi)= ai + bi. i=1 i=1 i=1 X X X n n (b) c ai = c ai. · · i=1 i=1 X X n (c) c = n c. · i=1 X 1 Proof. I’ll prove (c) as an example. I’ll use induction. For n = 1, the left side is c = c and the right i=1 side is 1 c = c. The result holds for n = 1. X Assume· that the result holds for n: n c = n c. · i=1 X Then for n + 1, I have n+1 n c = c + c i=1 i=1 X X = n c + c · =(n + 1) c · 2 The first equality used the recursive definition of a sum. The second equality follows from the induction hypothesis. The final equality is just basic algebra. Properties (a) and (b) can also be proved using induction. Example. Compute the following sums: 4 (a) i2. i=1 X 6 (b) i bi. · i=2 X 50 (c) 4. j=1 X n (d) (ai + c), where c is a constant. i=1 X (a) 4 i2 = 12 + 22 + 32 + 42 = 30. i=1 X (b) 6 i bi = 2b2 + 3b3 + 4b4 + 5b5 + 6b6. · i=2 X Note that sums need not start indexing at 1. (c) 50 4 = 50 4 = 200. · k=1 X Note that the summation variable can be anything that you want. (d) n n n n (ai + c)= ai + c = ai + n c. · i=1 i=1 i=1 i=1 X X X X 50 √n + 2 √n + 1 Example. Compute the exact value of − . √ 2 n=1 n + 3n + 2 X Note that √n + 2 √n + 1 √n + 2 √n + 1 1 1 − = − = . √n2 + 3n + 2 (n + 1)(n + 2) √n + 1 − √n + 2 So p 50 50 √n + 2 √n + 1 1 1 − = . √ 2 √n − √n n=1 n + 3n + 2 n=1 + 1 + 2 X X 3 I’ll write out a few of the terms: 1 1 + √2 − √3 1 1 + √3 − √4 1 1 + √4 − √5 . 1 1 + √50 − √51 1 1 √51 − √52 Most of the terms cancel in pairs, with the negative term in one expression cancelling with the positive term in the next expression. Only the first term and the last term are left, and they give the value of the sum: 50 √n + 2 √n + 1 1 1 − = . √ 2 √ − √ n=1 n + 3n + 2 2 52 X This is an example of a telescoping sum. Proposition. (Properties of products) n n n (a) aibi = ai bi . i=1 i=1 ! i=1 ! Y Y Y n n k k (b) ai = ai . i=1 i=1 ! Y Y n (c) c = cn. i=1 Y Proof. I’ll prove (a) by way of example. The proof will use induction on n. 1 1 1 For n = 1, the left side is aibi = a1b1. The right side is ai bi = a1b1. The result holds i=1 i=1 ! i=1 ! for n = 1. Y Y Y Assume that the result holds for n: n n n aibi = ai bi . i=1 i=1 ! i=1 ! Y Y Y 4 Then for n + 1, I have n+1 n aibi = aibi an+1bn+1 · i=1 i=1 Y Yn n = ai bi an+1bn+1 i=1 ! i=1 ! Yn Y n = ai an+1 bi bn+1 i=1 ! i=1 ! Y Y n+1 n+1 = ai bi i=1 ! i=1 ! Y Y The first equality follows from the recursive definition of a product. The second equality uses the induction hypothesis. The third equality comes from commutativity of multiplication. And the fourth equality is a result of the recursive definition of a product again. Properties (b) and (c) can also be proved by induction. Example. Compute the following products: 4 (a) en. n=1 Y n 2 (b) (cai) , where c is a constant. i=1 Y 20 (c) 5. k=1 Y (a) 4 en = e e2 e3 e4 = e10. · · · n=1 Y (b) n n n n n 2 2 2 2 2 2 2n (cai) = c ai = c ai = c ai . i=1 i=1 i=1 ! i=1 ! i=1 ! Y Y Y Y Y (c) 20 5 = 520. k=1 Y 50 4 4 Example. Compute the exact value of 1+ + . n n2 n=1 Y Note that 4 4 n2 + 4n + 4 (n + 2)2 1+ + = = . n n2 n2 n2 So 50 50 4 4 (n + 2)2 1+ + = . n n2 n2 n=1 n=1 Y Y 5 I’ll write out a few of the terms: 32 42 52 62 502 512 522 12 · 22 · 32 · 42 ····· 482 · 492 · 502 Most of the terms in the numerators cancel with the terms in the denominators “two fractions ahead”. Only the first two denominators and the last two numerators don’t cancel, and they give the value of the product: 50 4 4 512 522 1+ + = · = 1758276. n n2 12 22 n=1 Y · This is an example of a telescoping product. If n is a positive integer, n! (read n-factorial) is the product of the integers from 1 to n: n n!= k = 1 2 n. · ····· k=1 Y For example, 5! = 1 2 3 4 5 = 120. · · · · By convention, 0! is defined to be 1. This definition agrees with the extension of factorials using the Gamma function, described below. It also is the appropriate definition when factorials come up in binomial coefficients. Note that n! = 1 2 (n 1) n =(n 1)! n. · ····· − · − · There is a way of extending the definition of factorials to positive real numbers (so that, for instance, 1 ! is defined). The Gamma function is defined by 2 ∞ Γ(x)= e−ttx−1 dt for x> 0.
Recommended publications
  • Finite Sum – Product Logic
    Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 8, No. 5, pp. 63–99. FINITE SUM – PRODUCT LOGIC J.R.B. COCKETT1 AND R.A.G. SEELY2 ABSTRACT. In this paper we describe a deductive system for categories with finite products and coproducts, prove decidability of equality of morphisms via cut elimina- tion, and prove a “Whitman theorem” for the free such categories over arbitrary base categories. This result provides a nice illustration of some basic techniques in categorical proof theory, and also seems to have slipped past unproved in previous work in this field. Furthermore, it suggests a type-theoretic approach to 2–player input–output games. Introduction In the late 1960’s Lambekintroduced the notion of a “deductive system”, by which he meant the presentation of a sequent calculus for a logic as a category, whose objects were formulas of the logic, and whose arrows were (equivalence classes of) sequent deriva- tions. He noticed that “doctrines” of categories corresponded under this construction to certain logics. The classic example of this was cartesian closed categories, which could then be regarded as the “proof theory” for the ∧ – ⇒ fragment of intuitionistic propo- sitional logic. (An excellent account of this may be found in the classic monograph [Lambek–Scott 1986].) Since his original work, many categorical doctrines have been given similar analyses, but it seems one simple case has been overlooked, viz. the doctrine of categories with finite products and coproducts (without any closed structure and with- out any extra assumptions concerning distributivity of the one over the other). We began looking at this case with the thought that it would provide a nice simple introduction to some techniques in categorical proof theory, particularly the idea of rewriting systems modulo equations, which we have found useful in investigating categorical structures with two tensor products (“linearly distributive categories” [Blute et al.
    [Show full text]
  • LINEAR ALGEBRA METHODS in COMBINATORICS László Babai
    LINEAR ALGEBRA METHODS IN COMBINATORICS L´aszl´oBabai and P´eterFrankl Version 2.1∗ March 2020 ||||| ∗ Slight update of Version 2, 1992. ||||||||||||||||||||||| 1 c L´aszl´oBabai and P´eterFrankl. 1988, 1992, 2020. Preface Due perhaps to a recognition of the wide applicability of their elementary concepts and techniques, both combinatorics and linear algebra have gained increased representation in college mathematics curricula in recent decades. The combinatorial nature of the determinant expansion (and the related difficulty in teaching it) may hint at the plausibility of some link between the two areas. A more profound connection, the use of determinants in combinatorial enumeration goes back at least to the work of Kirchhoff in the middle of the 19th century on counting spanning trees in an electrical network. It is much less known, however, that quite apart from the theory of determinants, the elements of the theory of linear spaces has found striking applications to the theory of families of finite sets. With a mere knowledge of the concept of linear independence, unexpected connections can be made between algebra and combinatorics, thus greatly enhancing the impact of each subject on the student's perception of beauty and sense of coherence in mathematics. If these adjectives seem inflated, the reader is kindly invited to open the first chapter of the book, read the first page to the point where the first result is stated (\No more than 32 clubs can be formed in Oddtown"), and try to prove it before reading on. (The effect would, of course, be magnified if the title of this volume did not give away where to look for clues.) What we have said so far may suggest that the best place to present this material is a mathematics enhancement program for motivated high school students.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 of Concrete Abstractions: an Introduction to Computer
    Out of print; full text available for free at http://www.gustavus.edu/+max/concrete-abstractions.html CHAPTER TWO Recursion and Induction 2.1 Recursion We have used Scheme to write procedures that describe how certain computational processes can be carried out. All the procedures we've discussed so far generate processes of a ®xed size. For example, the process generated by the procedure square always does exactly one multiplication no matter how big or how small the number we're squaring is. Similarly, the procedure pinwheel generates a process that will do exactly the same number of stack and turn operations when we use it on a basic block as it will when we use it on a huge quilt that's 128 basic blocks long and 128 basic blocks wide. Furthermore, the size of the procedure (that is, the size of the procedure's text) is a good indicator of the size of the processes it generates: Small procedures generate small processes and large procedures generate large processes. On the other hand, there are procedures of a ®xed size that generate computa- tional processes of varying sizes, depending on the values of their parameters, using a technique called recursion. To illustrate this, the following is a small, ®xed-size procedure for making paper chains that can still make chains of arbitrary lengthÐ it has a parameter n for the desired length. You'll need a bunch of long, thin strips of paper and some way of joining the ends of a strip to make a loop. You can use tape, a stapler, or if you use slitted strips of cardstock that look like this , you can just slip the slits together.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1811.04966V3 [Math.NT]
    Descartes’ rule of signs, Newton polygons, and polynomials over hyperfields Matthew Baker and Oliver Lorscheid Abstract. In this note, we develop a theory of multiplicities of roots for polynomials over hyperfields and use this to provide a unified and conceptual proof of both Descartes’ rule of signs and Newton’s “polygon rule”. Introduction Given a real polynomial p ∈ R[T ], Descartes’ rule of signs provides an upper bound for the number of positive (resp. negative) real roots of p in terms of the signs of the coeffi- cients of p. Specifically, the number of positive real roots of p (counting multiplicities) is bounded above by the number of sign changes in the coefficients of p(T ), and the number of negative roots is bounded above by the number of sign changes in the coefficients of p(−T ). Another classical “rule”, which is less well known to mathematicians in general but is used quite often in number theory, is Newton’s polygon rule. This rule concerns polynomi- als over fields equipped with a valuation, which is a function v : K → R ∪{∞} satisfying • v(a) = ∞ if and only if a = 0 • v(ab) = v(a) + v(b) • v(a + b) > min{v(a),v(b)}, with equality if v(a) 6= v(b) for all a,b ∈ K. An example is the p-adic valuation vp on Q, where p is a prime number, given by the formula vp(s/t) = ordp(s) − ordp(t), where ordp(n) is the maximum power of p dividing a nonzero integer n. Another example is the T -adic valuation v on k(T), for any field k, given by v ( f /g) = arXiv:1811.04966v3 [math.NT] 26 May 2020 T T ordT ( f )−ordT (g), where ordT ( f ) is the maximum power of T dividing a nonzero polyno- mial f ∈ k[T].
    [Show full text]
  • Diagrammatics in Categorification and Compositionality
    Diagrammatics in Categorification and Compositionality by Dmitry Vagner Department of Mathematics Duke University Date: Approved: Ezra Miller, Supervisor Lenhard Ng Sayan Mukherjee Paul Bendich Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Mathematics in the Graduate School of Duke University 2019 ABSTRACT Diagrammatics in Categorification and Compositionality by Dmitry Vagner Department of Mathematics Duke University Date: Approved: Ezra Miller, Supervisor Lenhard Ng Sayan Mukherjee Paul Bendich An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Mathematics in the Graduate School of Duke University 2019 Copyright c 2019 by Dmitry Vagner All rights reserved Abstract In the present work, I explore the theme of diagrammatics and their capacity to shed insight on two trends|categorification and compositionality|in and around contemporary category theory. The work begins with an introduction of these meta- phenomena in the context of elementary sets and maps. Towards generalizing their study to more complicated domains, we provide a self-contained treatment|from a pedagogically novel perspective that introduces almost all concepts via diagrammatic language|of the categorical machinery with which we may express the broader no- tions found in the sequel. The work then branches into two seemingly unrelated disciplines: dynamical systems and knot theory. In particular, the former research defines what it means to compose dynamical systems in a manner analogous to how one composes simple maps. The latter work concerns the categorification of the slN link invariant. In particular, we use a virtual filtration to give a more diagrammatic reconstruction of Khovanov-Rozansky homology via a smooth TQFT.
    [Show full text]
  • Discussion Problems 2
    CS103 Handout 11 Fall 2014 October 6, 2014 Discussion Problems 2 Problem One: Product Parities Suppose that you have n integers x₁, x₂, …, xₙ. Prove that the product x₁ · x₂ · … · xₙ is odd if and only if each number xᵢ is odd. You might want to use the following facts: the product of zero numbers is called the empty product and is, by definition, equal to 1, and any two true state- ments imply one another. Problem Two: Prime Numbers A natural number p ≥ 2 is called prime if it has no positive divisors except 1 and itself. A natural number is called composite if it is the product of two natural numbers m and n, where both m and n are greater than one. Every natural number greater than or equal to two is either prime or composite. Prove, by strong induction, that every natural number greater than or equal to two can be written as a product of prime numbers. Problem Three: Factorials! Multiplied together! The number n! is defined as 1 × 2 × … × n. We choose to define 0! = 1. Prove by induction that for any m, n ∈ ℕ, we have m!n! ≤ (m + n)!. Can you explain intuitively why this is true? Problem Four: Picking Coins Consider the following game for two players. Begin with a pile of n coins for some n ≥ 0. The first player then takes between one and ten coins out of the pile, then the second player takes between one and ten coins out of the pile. This process repeats until some player has no coins to take; at this point, that player loses the game.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Categories As Tools for Building Theories
    Logic and Categories As Tools For Building Theories Samson Abramsky Oxford University Computing Laboratory 1 Introduction My aim in this short article is to provide an impression of some of the ideas emerging at the interface of logic and computer science, in a form which I hope will be accessible to philosophers. Why is this even a good idea? Because there has been a huge interaction of logic and computer science over the past half-century which has not only played an important r^olein shaping Computer Science, but has also greatly broadened the scope and enriched the content of logic itself.1 This huge effect of Computer Science on Logic over the past five decades has several aspects: new ways of using logic, new attitudes to logic, new questions and methods. These lead to new perspectives on the question: What logic is | and should be! Our main concern is with method and attitude rather than matter; nevertheless, we shall base the general points we wish to make on a case study: Category theory. Many other examples could have been used to illustrate our theme, but this will serve to illustrate some of the points we wish to make. 2 Category Theory Category theory is a vast subject. It has enormous potential for any serious version of `formal philosophy' | and yet this has hardly been realized. We shall begin with introduction to some basic elements of category theory, focussing on the fascinating conceptual issues which arise even at the most elementary level of the subject, and then discuss some its consequences and philosophical ramifications.
    [Show full text]
  • Indexed Collections Let I Be a Set (Finite of Infinite). If for Each Element
    Indexed Collections Let I be a set (finite of infinite). If for each element i of I there is an associated object xi (exactly one for each i) then we say the collection xi,i∈ I is indexed by I. Each element i ∈ I is called and index and I is called the index set for this collection. The definition is quite general. Usually the set I is the set of natural numbers or positive integers, and the objects xi are numbers or sets. It is important to remember that there is no requirement for the objects associated with different elements of I to be distinct. That is, it is possible to have xi = xj when i = j. It is also important to remember that there is exactly one object associated with each index. Technically, the above corresponds to having a set X of objects and a function i : I → X. Instead of writing i(x) for element of x associated with i, instead we write xi (just different notation). Examples of indexed collections. 1. With each natural number n, associate a real number an. Then the indexed collection a0,a1,a2,... is what we usually think of as a sequence of real numbers. 2. For each positive integer i, let Ai be a set. Then we have the indexed collection of sets A1,A2,.... n Sigma notation. Let a0,a1,a2,... be a sequence of numbers. The notation i=k ai stands for the sum ak + ak+1 + ak+2 + ···an. n If k>n, then i=k ai contains no terms.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:Math/0509655V2 [Math.CT] 26 May 2006 Nt Rdcs Aigacategory a Having Products
    ON HOMOTOPY VARIETIES J. ROSICKY´ ∗ Abstract. Given an algebraic theory T , a homotopy T -algebra is a simplicial set where all equations from T hold up to homotopy. All homotopy T -algebras form a homotopy variety. We will give a characterization of homotopy varieties analogous to the character- ization of varieties. 1. Introduction Algebraic theories were introduced by F. W. Lawvere (see [31] and also [32]) in order to provide a convenient approach to study algebras in general categories. An algebraic theory is a small category T with finite products. Having a category K with finite products, a T -algebra in K is a finite product preserving functor T →K. Algebras in the category Set of sets are usual many-sorted algebras. Algebras in the category SSet of simplicial sets are called simplicial algebras and they can be also viewed as simplicial objects in the category of algebras in Set. In homotopy theory, one often needs to consider algebras up to homotopy – a homotopy T -algebra is a functor A : T → SSet such that the canonical morphism A(X1 ×···× Xn) → A(X1) ×···× A(Xn) is a weak equivalence for each finite product X1 ×···× Xn in T . These homotopy algebras have been considered in recent papers [6], [7] and [9] but the subject is much older (see, e.g., [16], [8], [35] or [38]). arXiv:math/0509655v2 [math.CT] 26 May 2006 A category is called a variety if it is equivalent to the category Alg(T ) of all T -algebras in Set for some algebraic theory T . There is a char- acterization of varieties proved by F.
    [Show full text]
  • On Least Squares Exponential Sum Approximation with Positive Coefficients*
    MATHEMATICS OF COMPUTATION, VOLUME 34, NUMBER 149 JANUARY 1980, PAGES 203-211 On Least Squares Exponential Sum Approximation With Positive Coefficients* By John W. Evans, William B. Gragg and Randall J. LeVeque Abstract. An algorithm is given for finding optimal least squares exponential sum approximations to sampled data subject to the constraint that the coefficients appear- ing in the exponential sum are positive. The algorithm employs the divided differences of exponentials to overcome certain problems of ill-conditioning and is suitable for data sampled at noninteger times. 1. Introduction. In this paper the following least squares approximation is con- sidered: Let y0, ...,yN be N + I real data points sampled at times 0 < t0 < • • • < tN, and let w0, ..., wN > 0 be a set of weights. For a compact subset S of the real num- bers minimize N I/ r Z ai exPi-ait„) subject only to ax, ...,ar>0 and ax, ..., ar E S and with no limitation on the number of terms r. An algorithm is given which extends that of [3], [10] so that noninteger times are acceptable. The algorithm uses the exponential [7], [9] of a certain triangular matrix [8] to obtain divided differences of the exponential function. For other work on this topic the reader is referred to [1], [2], [5] and to the references in [10]. We begin by giving some definitions and results from [3] in Section 2 and then present in Section 3 a modification of the numerical procedure of that paper which applies to approximation by positive sums of exponentials. The role of divided dif- ferences in a linear least squares step of the numerical procedure is considered in Sec- tion 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Remarkable Infinite Product Identities Involving Fibonacci
    Some remarkable infinite product identities involving Fibonacci and Lucas numbers∗ Kunle Adegoke † Department of Physics and Engineering Physics, Obafemi Awolowo University, Ile-Ife, Nigeria Abstract By applying the classic telescoping summation formula and its vari- ants to identities involving inverse hyperbolic tangent functions hav- ing inverse powers of the golden ratio as arguments and employing subtle properties of the Fibonacci and Lucas numbers, we derive interesting general infinite product identities involving these num- bers. 1 Introduction The following striking (in Frontczak’s description [1]) infinite product iden- tity involving Fibonacci numbers, ∞ F +1 2k+2 =3 , F2k+2 1 Yk=1 − originally obtained by Melham and Shannon [2], is an n =1= q case of a more general identity (to be derived in this present paper): arXiv:1702.08321v2 [math.NT] 29 Apr 2017 ∞ F + F q F L (2n−1)(2k+2q) 2q(2n−1) = (2n−1)(2k−1) (2n−1)2k . F(2n−1)(2k+2q) F2q(2n−1) L(2n−1)(2k−1)F(2n−1)2k Yk=1 − Yk=1 ∗AMS Classification Numbers : 11B39, 11Y60 †[email protected], [email protected] 1 + The above identity is valid for q N0, n Z , where we use N0 to denote the set of natural numbers including∈ zero.∈ Here the Fibonacci numbers, Fn, and Lucas numbers, Ln, are defined, for n N , as usual, through the recurrence relations F = F + F , with ∈ 0 n n−1 n−2 F0 =0, F1 =1 and Ln = Ln−1 + Ln−2, with L0 =2, L1 =1. Our goal in this paper is to derive several general infinite product identi- ties, including the one given above.
    [Show full text]
  • Dismal Arithmetic
    1 2 Journal of Integer Sequences, Vol. 14 (2011), 3 Article 11.9.8 47 6 23 11 Dismal Arithmetic David Applegate AT&T Shannon Labs 180 Park Avenue Florham Park, NJ 07932-0971 USA [email protected] Marc LeBrun Fixpoint Inc. 448 Ignacio Blvd., #239 Novato, CA 94949 USA [email protected] N. J. A. Sloane1 AT&T Shannon Labs 180 Park Avenue Florham Park, NJ 07932-0971 USA [email protected] To the memory of Martin Gardner (October 21, 1914 – May 22, 2010). Abstract Dismal arithmetic is just like the arithmetic you learned in school, only simpler: there are no carries, when you add digits you just take the largest, and when you multiply digits you take the smallest. This paper studies basic number theory in this world, including analogues of the primes, number of divisors, sum of divisors, and the partition function. 1Corresponding author. 1 1 Introduction To remedy the dismal state of arithmetic skills possessed by today’s children, we propose a “dismal arithmetic” that will be easier to learn than the usual version. It is easier because there are no carry digits and there is no need to add or multiply digits, or to do anything harder than comparing. In dismal arithmetic, for each pair of digits, to Add, take the lArger, but to Multiply, take the sMaller. That’s it! For example: 2 5 = 5, 2 5 = 2. Addition or multiplication of larger numbers uses the same rules, always with the proviso that there are no carries. For example, the dismal sum of 169 and 248 is 269 and their dismal product is 12468 (Figure 1).
    [Show full text]