Substance and Independence in Descartes

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Substance and Independence in Descartes Philosophical Review Substance and Independence in Descartes Anat Schechtman University of Wisconsin-Madison Less celebrated than Descartes’s contributions to epistemology, but no less significant, are Descartes’s ventures in metaphysics—in particular, his innovative conception of substance, which marks a decisive break between the modern period and the previous two thousand years in which hylomorphism reigned.1 It is therefore perplexing that Descartes provides not one but two characterizations of substance—which, more- over, are seemingly incompatible. On the one hand, substance is said to be the subject in which properties inhere, and that does not itself inhere in anything. On the other hand, substance is said to be an independent entity. These two characterizations have appeared to many to diverge on I would like to thank Colin Chamberlain, Michael Della Rocca, James Messina, Steven Nadler, Marleen Rozemond, and Tad Schmaltz for detailed and insightful comments on earlier versions of this essay, as well as audience members at the 2015 Oxford Seminar for early modern philosophy and the 2015 Atelier franco-ame´ricain du Se´minaire Descartes for helpful suggestions. I would also like to gratefully acknowledge support from the American Council of Learned Societies and from the Graduate School and the College of Letters and Sciences at the University of Wisconsin-Madison during the time in which this article was written. Finally, as always, I am grateful to John Bengson for everything and more. 1. Arguably, it is likewise Descartes’s conception of substance—no less than his method of doubt, the cogito, or “the way of ideas”—that helped pave the way for the next 150 years of metaphysical and epistemological (including anti-metaphysical and skeptical) developments, in Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, and Hume, among others. See Wat- son 1987 for an influential discussion of the centrality of Descartes’s metaphysical views for subsequent Cartesianism and its “breakdown.” See also Moore 2013 for a recent sche- matic portrayal of the impact of Descartes’s conception of substance on subsequent philosophy. Philosophical Review, Vol. 125, No. 2, 2016 DOI 10.1215/00318108-3453167 q 2016 by Cornell University 155 Published by Duke University Press Philosophical Review ANAT SCHECHTMAN the definition as well as the scope, or extension, of the notion of sub- stance. For it is often thought that what is the ultimate subject of inher- ence need not—and, in some cases, cannot—be independent. There is, it seems, a tension at the core of Descartes’s metaphysics, afflicting one of its fundamental notions. Readers of Descartes have tended to respond to this tension by prioritizing one of these characterizations of substance at the expense of the other. As a result, they tend to treat passages in which Descartes voices the characterization they disfavor as somehow not expressive of Des- cartes’s considered view—on such occasions, it is sometimes claimed, Descartes “speaks lightly.”2 Other interpreters simply suggest that Des- cartes’s theory of substance is confused or inconsistent. Existing inter- pretations thus tend to handle the tension by avoiding or denying rather than resolving it. My aim in this essay is to develop an interpretation of Descartes’s notions of substance and independence that reconciles his two charac- terizations. If the proposed interpretation is correct, it will allow us to move beyond the apparent tension in Descartes’s metaphysics. It may also point the way to interpretations of other central elements of that meta- physics that are linked to substance and independence, including (but not limited to) the distinction between mind and body and their union, as well as the notions of infinity and perfection, and lead to a better under- standing of the relationship between Cartesian metaphysics and sub- stance monism. The latter position is sometimes said to follow more or less directly from Descartes’s second characterization of substance, as an independent entity. While I will not have the space to examine this con- tention here, it is worth remarking that if my interpretation is correct, there is no straightforward route from the independence of substance to monism.3 What I shall say about the notions of substance and independence in Descartes might also be of interest to contemporary debates in meta- physics concerning relations of grounding and ontological dependence. Much of this debate takes certain historical data-points for granted; for example, that the targeted relation is the same as the one invoked by historical figures like Aristotle or Descartes in characterizing the relation between a substance and its properties. This assumes, of course, that we already know what relations such figures were invoking. But do we? 2. The quoted expression is from Stuart 1999, 100. 3. I discuss this point in detail in Schechtman n.d. 156 Published by Duke University Press Philosophical Review Substance and Independence in Descartes It seems to me that, at least in the case of Descartes, we have yet to achieve a full understanding on this point. For example, if the continuing debate among scholars is any guide, we cannot simply assume that Descartes invokes ontological—as opposed to, say, causal—independence in char- acterizing substance. At least, we cannot do so without further debate—a debate that is undertaken here. I will spell out several problems with existing interpretations before turning to my positive proposal. Stated briefly, the proposal is that in characterizing substance, Descartes invokes a type of indepen- dence that obtains when, and only when, there is no relation to another entity that holds by the nature of the entity in question. Even though the ultimate subject of inherence is sometimes not independent in other respects (for example, modally or causally), it nevertheless satisfies this condition. Consequently, the proposal reconciles Descartes’s two charac- terizations by giving an account of the general notion of independence featured in the second characterization, and of the specific relation of inherence featured in the first characterization as its instance. The main argument on behalf of this proposal arises in response to a suite of historical, textual, and philosophical considerations. Section 1 discusses three important scholastic theses regarding substance, includ- ing the thesis that a substance is the ultimate subject of properties, and provides reasons to think that Descartes endorsed them all. Section 2 turns to the characterization of substance as an independent entity and explores a popular interpretation of it that invokes causal independence. Sections 3 and 4 discuss two other interpretations, which focus instead on absence of inherence and modal independence. Clarifying the difficul- ties confronting these three interpretations will help us to identify desid- erata for a more promising alternative, which sections 5 and 6 then seek to develop and defend.4 4. Unless otherwise noted, translations of Descartes’s works are taken from Des- cartes 1985–1992. The original texts in Latin or French may be found in Descartes 1996. References to Descartes’s work in the main text and notes cite the volume and page number in Descartes 1996 (abbreviated ‘AT’), followed (after a semicolon) by the volume and page number in Descartes 1985–1992, vols. 1 and 2 (abbreviated ‘CSM’), or by the page number in vol. 3 (abbreviated ‘CSMK’). I use the following abbreviations for specific works by Descartes: ‘Rules’ for Rules for the Direction of the Mind,‘Discourse’ for Discourse on Method,‘Meditations’ for Meditations on First Philosophy,‘Principles’ for Principles of Philosophy, ‘Passions’ for Passions of the Soul, and ‘Comments’ for Comments on a Certain Broadsheet. 157 Published by Duke University Press Philosophical Review ANAT SCHECHTMAN 1. Three Scholastic Theses It is fair to say that many central themes in Descartes’s philosophy can be better understood against the background of his scholastic predecessors, who provided him with both a source of influence and a target for criti- cism. In particular, despite obvious differences, Descartes’s notion of substance owes a significant debt to the scholastic tradition.5 This section will highlight three scholastic theses about substance and independence and provide reasons to think that Descartes adopted them as well. First, scholastic authors commonly endorse a conception of sub- stance as the ultimate subject of properties, or accidents. On this con- ception, which has two components, a substance is that to which accidents belong—or in scholastic terminology, that in which accidents exist or inhere—without belonging to (existing or inhering in) anything in turn.6 This conception originates in Aristotle’s Categories, where sub- stance is said to be “that which is neither said of a subject nor is in a subject” (Aristotle 1984, 2a11–19), and appears in later authors, such as Avicenna, who characterizes substance as “that which is not in another as in a subject,” and accident as “that which exists in a subject” (Avicenna 2005, Metaphysics 2.1). While this comment does not make the identifi- cation of substance with subject transparent, the following passage by Sua´rez does, as it explicitly invokes both components of the conception in question: There are two notions or properties indicated by the verb ‘standing under’ [substando] and the name ‘substance’: one is absolute, namely, to exist in itself and by itself [per se] ...; the other is relative, it has to do with supporting the accidents. (Metaphysical Disputations 33.1.1; quoted in Gracia 1982, 267) Others scholastic authors endorse this conception as well, characterizing substance as the subject in which accidents inhere without itself inhering 5. Of course, I do not wish to deny the heterogeneity of views among the scholastics, or to suggest that the particular theses I go on to mention were held by each and every scholastic figure. The intention is only to trace a very general and, I think, plausible line of influence.
Recommended publications
  • Lowe's Eliminativism About Relations and the Analysis Of
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers Lowe’s eliminativism about relations and the analysis of relational inherence Markku Keinänen Tampere University, Finland markku.keinanen[a]tuni.fi https://philpeople.org/profiles/markku-keinanen .[DRAFT, please do not quote] Abstract, Contrary to widely shared opinion in analytic metaphysics, E.J. Lowe argues against the existence of relations in his posthumously published paper There are probably no relations (2016). In this article, I assess Lowe’s eliminativist strategy, which aims to show that all contingent “relational facts” have a monadic foundation in modes characterizing objects. Second, I present two difficult ontological problems supporting eliminativism about relations. Against eliminativism, metaphysicians of science have argued that relations might well be needed in the best a posteriori motivated account of the structure of reality. Finally, I argue that, by analyzing relational inherence, trope theory offers us a completely new approach to relational entities and avoids the hard problems motivating eliminativism. 1. Introduction It has been a widely shared view in analytic metaphysics that we need to postulate relations in order to provide an adequate account of reality. For instance, concrete objects are spatio-temporally related in various ways and the spatio-temporal arrangement of objects is contingent relative to their existence and monadic properties. Here the most straightforward conclusion is that there are additional entities, spatio-temporal relations, which account for objects’ being spatio-temporally related in different ways. Similarly, influential metaphysicians of science have maintained that relations figure among the fundamental constituents of reality according to reasonable interpretation of the best physical theories (Teller 1986, Butterfield 2006).
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Universals in Contemporary Philosophy∗ Scuola Normale Superiore [Pisa - July 5, 2010]
    93 Reportage 7 novembre 2010 International conference on Ontology The problem of universals in contemporary philosophy∗ Scuola Normale Superiore [Pisa - July 5, 2010] Gianmarco Brunialti Masera Overview The three-day conference opened in the afternoon of July, 5 and, after taking a quick look at the programme and the names of the important thinkers standing out on it, one could have expected to find a crowded audience room. Actually that was not quite the case. What I could afford to follow and am going to write about here is only the first day of the conference. The debate started right on time, after a short introduction given by Gabriele Galluzzo, both organizer of the conference and member of the scientific board. I would ac- tually like to underline the word debate: each speech (about 40 minutes) was immediately followed by a short discussion of the issues introduced by the proponent. Unfortunately, de- spite of the accurate and punctual speeches, the little time dedicated to each is what most penalized the conference, in my opinion: this inevitably obliged both the speakers and the audience to be plunged in medias res, without standing too much on ceremonies. I take this to be ‘penalizing’, considering the debate on universals is a very wide one and composed by an incredibly great number of positions which can sometimes start from oppo- site sides and some other times depart at some specific middle point of one single theory of properties and relations. Moreover, most (if not all) of them entail a certain number of other metaphysical themes from which the specific problematics of universals cannot be cut off.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Philosophy.Pdf
    I N T R O D U C T I O N What Is Philosophy? CHAPTER 1 The Task of Philosophy CHAPTER OBJECTIVES Reflection—thinking things over—. [is] the beginning of philosophy.1 In this chapter we will address the following questions: N What Does “Philosophy” Mean? N Why Do We Need Philosophy? N What Are the Traditional Branches of Philosophy? N Is There a Basic Method of Philo- sophical Thinking? N How May Philosophy Be Used? N Is Philosophy of Education Useful? N What Is Happening in Philosophy Today? The Meanings Each of us has a philos- “having” and “doing”—cannot be treated en- ophy, even though we tirely independent of each other, for if we did of Philosophy may not be aware of not have a philosophy in the formal, personal it. We all have some sense, then we could not do a philosophy in the ideas concerning physical objects, our fellow critical, reflective sense. persons, the meaning of life, death, God, right Having a philosophy, however, is not suffi- and wrong, beauty and ugliness, and the like. Of cient for doing philosophy. A genuine philo- course, these ideas are acquired in a variety sophical attitude is searching and critical; it is of ways, and they may be vague and confused. open-minded and tolerant—willing to look at all We are continuously engaged, especially during sides of an issue without prejudice. To philoso- the early years of our lives, in acquiring views phize is not merely to read and know philoso- and attitudes from our family, from friends, and phy; there are skills of argumentation to be mas- from various other individuals and groups.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Research Commons@Waikato Philosophical Papers Vol. 30, No. 2 (July 2001): 117-143 Predication and the Problem of Universals Catherine Legg Abstract: This paper contrasts the scholastic realists of David Armstrong and Charles Peirce. It is argued that the so-called 'problem of universals' is not a problem in pure ontology (concerning whether universals exist) as Armstrong construes it to be. Rather, it extends to issues concerning which predicates should be applied where, issues which Armstrong sets aside under the label of 'semantics', and which from a Peircean perspective encompass even the fundamentals of scientific methodology. It is argued that Peir ce's scholastic realism not only presents a more nuanced ontology (distinguishing the existent front the real) but also provides more of a sense of why realism should be a position worth fighting for. ... a realist is simply one who knows no more recondite reality than that which is represented in a true representation. C.S. Peirce Like many other philosophical problems, the grandly-named 'Problem of Universals' is difficult to define without begging the question that it raises. Laurence Goldstein, however, provides a helpful hands-off denotation of the problem by noting that it proceeds from what he calls The Trivial Obseruation:2 The observation is the seemingly incontrovertible claim that, 'sometimes some things have something in common'. The 1 Philosophical Writings of Peirce, ed. Justus Buehler (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), 248. 2 Laurence Goldstein, 'Scientific Scotism – The Emperor's New Trousers or Has Armstrong Made Some Real Strides?', Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol 61, No.
    [Show full text]
  • “Bare Particulars”∗ Theodore Sider Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006), 387–97
    “Bare Particulars”∗ Theodore Sider Philosophical Perspectives 20 (2006), 387–97 One often hears a complaint about “bare particulars”. This complaint has bugged me for years. I know it bugs others too, but no one seems to have vented in print, so that is what I propose to do. (I hope also to say a few constructive things along the way.) The complaint is aimed at the substratum theory, which says that partic- ulars are, in a certain sense, separate from their universals. If universals and particulars are separate, connected to each other only by a relation of instanti- ation, then, it is said, the nature of these particulars becomes mysterious. In themselves, they do not have any properties at all. They are nothing but a pincushion into which universals may be poked. They are Locke’s “I know not what” (1689, II, xxiii, §2); they are Plato’s receptacles (Timaeus 48c–53c); they are “bare particulars”.1 Against substratum theory there is the bundle theory, according to which particulars are just bundles of universals. The substratum and bundle theories agree on much. They agree that both universals and particulars exist. And they agree that a particular in some sense has universals. (I use phrases like ‘particular P has universal U ’ and ‘particular P’s universals’ neutrally as between the substratum and bundle theories.) But the bundle theory says that a particular is exhaustively composed of (i.e., is a mereological fusion of) its universals. The substratum theory, on the other hand, denies this. Take a particular, and mereologically subtract away its universals.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics: a Contemporary Introduction: Third Edition
    Metaphysics Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction is for students who have already done an introductory philosophy course. Michael J. Loux provides a fresh look at the central topics in metaphysics, making this essential reading for any student of the subject. This third edition is revised and updated and includes two new chapters on Time and Causation. Topics addressed include: • the problem of universals • the nature of abstract entities • the problem of individuation • the nature of modality • identity through time • the nature of time • the Realism/anti-Realism debate Wherever possible, Michael J. Loux relates contemporary views to their classical sources in the history of philosophy. As an experienced teacher of philosophy and an important contributor to recent debates, Loux is uniquely qualified to write this book. The third edition retains the student-friendly features of previous editions: • chapter overviews summarizing the main topics of study • examples to clarify difficult concepts • annotated further reading at the end of each chapter • endnotes and a full bibliography Michael J. Loux is Shuster Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. He is also editor of Metaphysics: Contemporary Readings, designed to accompany this textbook and also published by Routledge. His book Substance and Attribute (1978) is one of the major metaphysics books of recent years. Routledge Contemporary Introductions to Philosophy Series editor: Paul K. Moser Loyola University of Chicago This innovative, well-structured series is for students who have already done an introductory course in philosophy. Each book introduces a core general subject in contemporary philosophy and offers students an access- ible but substantial transition from introductory to higher-level college work in that subject.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysical and Semantic Implications of the Doctrine of Transubstantiation
    Substance Made Manifest: Metaphysical and Semantic Implications of the Doctrine of Transubstantiation Joshua P. Hochschild Mount St. Mary’s University This paper responds to Bruce Marshall’s use of logic to clarify the metaphysical issues at stake in the doctrine of transubstantiation. While appreciating and agreeing with the general approach of finding connections between logic and metaphysics, on the one hand, and the communal and ecumenical significance of Eucharistic doctrine, on the other, this paper criticizes Marshall’s particular analysis as beholden to a distinctively modern approach to logic, and displaying a typically modern neglect of the notion of substance. The conclusion suggests that distinctively Catholic teaching on transubstantiation is significant today not only for proclaiming a mystery of Christian faith, but also for calling attention to classical categories of reality, categories once considered more natural and common but subsequently obscured by modern philosophical and theological developments. Verbum caro, panem verum verbo carnem efficit: fitque sanguis Christi merum, et si sensus deficit, ad firmandum cor sincerum sola fides sufficit. —St. Thomas Aquinas Pange Lingua Gloriosi Corporis Mysterium 1. The Power of Language As the symposium’s designated philosopher, invited to talk about metaphysics, I confess that I will allow myself to be drawn into technical discussions in terminology Aquinas adopted from the Aristotelian philosophical tradition.1 With that in mind, I wish to make clear that I recognize that Aquinas was a theologian, and perhaps more importantly that he was a poet—a metaphysical poet, in the words of Sertillanges.2 The great literary critic Hugh Kenner, reflecting on the Pange Linga, describes Thomas’s poetic virtuosity as taking language to the very limits of 1 A version of this paper was originally given at the Metaphysics Colloquium of the Institute for Saint Anselm Studies at Saint Anselm College, June 5-6, 2013.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Inference? Penalty
    WHAT IS INFERENCE? OR THE FORCE OF REASONING by Ulf Hlobil Dipl.-Psych., University of Trier, 2008 Magister Artium in Philosophy, University of Trier, 2009 M.A. in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2012 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2016 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH KENNETH P. DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Ulf Hlobil It was defended on May 31, 2016 and approved by Robert Brandom, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy John McDowell, Distinguished University Professor of Philosophy Kieran Setiya, Professor of Philosophy James Shaw, Associate Professor of Philosophy Dissertation Director: Robert Brandom, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright © by Ulf Hlobil 2016 iii WHAT IS INFERENCE? OR THE FORCE OF REASONING Ulf Hlobil, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2016 What are we doing when we make inferences? I argue that to make an inference is to attach inferential force to an argument. Inferential force must be understood in analogy to assertoric force, and an argument is a structure of contents. I call this the “Force Account of inference.” I develop this account by first establishing two criteria of adequacy for accounts of inference. First, such accounts must explain why it is absurd to make an inference one believes to be bad. The upshot is that if someone makes an inference, she must take her inference to be good. Second, accounts of inference must explain why we cannot take our inferences to be good—in the sense that matters for inference—by merely accepting testimony to the effect that they are good.
    [Show full text]
  • Realism and Theories of Truth
    Realism and Theories of Truth Jamin Asay University of Hong Kong [email protected] Forthcoming in The Routledge Handbook of Scientific Realism, ed. Juha Saatsi 1. Introduction The notion of truth has never been far from the ongoing conversation about scientific realism. Scientific realism (and its opposition) is often defined explicitly in terms of truth, and sometimes it is argued that scientific realism (and its opposition) requires a commitment to particular conceptions about the nature of truth. It’s not difficult to appreciate why. The realist perspective maintains that science succeeds (or aims at succeeding) in correctly capturing the nature of reality, and to correctly describe reality just is to give a true theory about it. While it is fairly indisputable that there is some connection between truth and realism, it remains to be seen just how deep the relationship goes. In this essay, I explore some of the prominent ways that scientific realism and the theory of truth have intersected, and evaluate the arguments that have been offered concerning their relationship. Two basic positions can be articulated when it comes to the relationship between the theory of truth and scientific realism. Those who favor neutrality believe that one’s position on the theory of truth is neutral with respect to one’s position on scientific realism, and vice versa. Even though realism might be defined in terms of truth, it’s a further (and false) claim that realism (or its opposition) must be defined in terms of particular theories of truth. Those who favor a partisan view believe that varieties of scientific realism and anti-realism are tied up in the nature of truth, such that the former are committed to particular perspectives on truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Contemporary Approaches to the Individuation of Concrete Particulars: Why a Substance Theory Is a Stronger Account Nicholas Paul Spitzer University of Missouri-St
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Theses Graduate Works 7-14-2006 Two Contemporary Approaches To The Individuation Of Concrete Particulars: Why A Substance Theory Is A Stronger Account Nicholas Paul Spitzer University of Missouri-St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://irl.umsl.edu/thesis Recommended Citation Spitzer, Nicholas Paul, "Two Contemporary Approaches To The ndI ividuation Of Concrete Particulars: Why A Substance Theory Is A Stronger Account" (2006). Theses. 264. https://irl.umsl.edu/thesis/264 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Works at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TWO CONTEMPORARY APPROACHES TO THE INDIVIDUATION OF CONCRETE PARTICULARS: WHY A SUBSTANCE THEORY IS A STRONGER ACCOUNT by NICHOLAS PAUL SPITZER B.A., Behavioral Studies, Lael College and Graduate School, St. Louis, MO, 1999 A THESIS Submitted to the Graduate School of the UNIVERSITY OF MISSOURI – ST. LOUIS In partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree MASTER OF ARTS in PHILOSOPHY August 2006 Advisory Committee Jon D. McGinnis, Ph.D. Committee Chair Berit Brogaard, Ph.D. Andrew Black, Ph.D. © Copyright 2006 by Nicholas P. Spitzer All Rights Reserved Spitzer, Nicholas (2006), UMSL, page 2 Introduction As we interact with and observe our environment, we confront a world filled with many different entities.1 Some of these entities are things like houses, cars, commercial airplanes, oak trees, spiders, dogs, cats and people. Our initial intuitions seem to be that the world comes carved up with things like these concrete particulars.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Primary Substance
    24.200: Ancient Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 1, 2004 Aristotle on Primary Substance I. Substance in the Categories In the Categories, Aristotle takes primary substances to be ordinary individuals like Socrates. We noted in connection with this view that a primary substance must be what is both ontologically and epistemically basic, i.e., they must be those things on which the existence of everything else depends, and on which our systematic knowledge depends. Aristotle's view in the Categories that primary substances are ordinary concrete individuals depended on his acceptance of what we called the subject criterion. I.e., primary substances are the primary logical subjects, i.e., they are that in which properties (qualities, quantities, etc.) inhere, and which are themselves the members of kinds (species). "A substance --that which is called a substance most strictly, primarily, and most of all-- is that which is neither said of a subject nor in a subject." (Cat. 2a11) Primary substances are also the subjects of change: "It seems most distinctive of substance that what is numerically one and the same is able to receive contraries [i.e., contrary properties]." (Cat. 4a10) (E.g., a single individual may become hot, having been cold, or may change from being 5' tall to being 5'2" tall.) In his discussion of change in Physics I: 7-9, Aristotle feels the need to accommodate both the demand that in any change something remain through that change, and the demand that there be something "new" as a product of the change. To handle these demands, he distinguishes three "elements" in any change: the matter, the form, the lack.
    [Show full text]