Contemporary Ethical Theory Course Packet

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Contemporary Ethical Theory Course Packet Contemporary Ethical Theory PHLU 4913 Course packet Instructor: John Davenport Fall 2003 Monday - Wednesday 11:30 - 12:45 Contents of Course Packet: 1. Syllabus 2. Handouts 3. Sartre, “Existentialism is a Humanism,” from Existentialism and Humanism 4. Thomas Anderson, Sartre’s Two Ethics , chapter 4. 5. W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good , chapter 2. 6. Bernard Williams, “Critique of Utilitarianism,” in Utilitarianism: For and Against , Part II. 7. Bernard Williams, “Persons, Character, and Morality,” Moral Luck, chapter 1. 8. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice , chapter 1, chapter 2 §§10-17, and chapter 4 §40. 9. Christine Korsgaard’s “The Authority of Reflection” in The Sources of Normativity 10. Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons , chapters 1, 2, and 4. 11. Joel Feinberg, “Psychological Egoism,” from Ethics , ed. Cahn and Markie. 12. Michael Stocker, “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories,” from Virtue Ethics , ed. Crisp and Slote. 13. Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice , chapter 1 (selections). 14. Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue , 2 nd ed., chapters 14 - 15. Contemporary Ethical Theory PHLU 4913 Fall 2003 Monday - Wednesday 11:30 - 12:45 Instructor: John Davenport Phone: 212-636-7928 Email: [email protected] Office: Rm.923E Lincoln Center; Mailbox: Rm 916 Office Hours at LC : Mondays 2 - 4 PM. Thursdays I’m at RH, Tuesdays/Fridays home with kids. Précis of the Seminar: This seminar will be an intense discussion of some of the most fascinating and challenging developments in 20 th -century ethical theory (focusing largely on the analytic tradition). Because this is a seminar, active class participation and the student’s own research and written work will be crucial. We will have anywhere from 50 - 100 pages of reading per week, depending on difficulty. We will survey the 'great debate' that continues today between three broad approaches: 1. the utilitarians who focus on the results or consequences of actions, rules, and policies; 2. the neo-Kantians, who focus on the intrinsic rightness, justice, or fairness of actions and policies (i.e. do they respect each individual person as having inviolable intrinsic value?); 3. and neo-Aristotelians who want a broader approach including virtues of character and ethical ideals as guides to forming life-projects and relationships. In discussing these approaches to moral theory, we will look at some of the 20th century's most impressive writers on the theory of moral norms, including some from each of these traditions: John- Paul Sartre, Richard Hare, John Rawls, Thomas Scanlon, Christine Korsgaard, Alasdair MacIntyre, Bernard Williams, and Derek Parfit. We will focus in particular on contemporary neo-Kantian or deontological critiques of utilitarianism, arguments against moral egoism, critiques of the individualism and impartiality of utilitarian and deontological ethics, and the alternative conception of virtue ethics towards which these critiques perhaps point. However, this course does not cover three other important movements in 20 th -century ethics, which are not part of mainstream Anglo-American moral philosophy, and require their own courses: 1. new natural law ethics (Grisez, Finnis), which tries to develop a neo-Thomistic account of moral norms based on an objective conception of basic goods, rather than on a metaphysical conception of natural human functions, or our natural telos . 2. contemporary continental ethics of alterity (e.g. Levinas, Marion); 3. Discourse ethics, in particular the neo-Kantian moral theory of Jürgen Habermas, and its associated deliberative theory of democracy. In passing we will also discuss some famous problems in 'meta-ethics' including: the problem of moral relativism; the relation between ethics and pyschology; the meaning of moral terms; whether our identities are socially defined or freely chosen; and whether intrinsic value is 'real' outside or minds, or only a projection of human consciousness or society. Many of our examples will concern questions pertinent both for individuals trying to decide how to live their lives, and to people trying to envision a just government. However, although two the works we consider will be related to the foundation of political ethics, we will be looking at them more as contributions to the theory of moral norms rather than with regard to their political implications (e.g. for democratic theory). This course is primarily intended for Philosophy majors and minors, but may also be helpful for students interested in political theory and the philosophy of law. It presupposes only the core philosophy courses, although some familiarity with the history of modern philosophy would also be helpful. At the start, we will briefly review the central tenets of Kant’s and Mill’s work as an introduction to our themes, and then concentrate on key primary readings in 20 th century ethics. By the end of the course, students will have a good general knowledge of several important developments in moral philosophy in the 20th century. This will be a sufficient basis for further graduate study, or for studying closely related work in political philosophy and constitutional law. Texts : R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason (Oxford University Press, 1997): ISBN: 019881092X Raz, Value, Respect, and Attachment (Cambridge University Press, 2001): ISBN: 052100022X Alasdair MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals (Open Court, 2001): ISBN: 081269452X Smart and Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge): ISBN: 052109822X My Course packet, including all the other readings. Students pay for this with a money order. Assignments : 20% Class participation. 20%: 1 short essay (6-7 pages) with a choice between particular questions on the readings; 20% l report to the class on a given reading for the day (3-page written summary and questions) 40% Final Research Paper (14 pages +) Tentative Schedule 9/3: Introduction: Utilitarianism vs Deontology 1. Introduction to the course 2. Overview of the structure of moral theory 3. Handout on Mill’s utilitarianism. 4. Handout on Kant’s categorical imperative. 5. Discussion of the main differences between these theories . Part I: Deontological Critiques of Utilitarianism 9/8 - 9/10: Sartre and Intuitionism 1. Sartre, “Existentialism is a Humanism” (in course packet) 2. W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good , chapter 2 (course packet) 915 - 9/17: Williams’s Critique of Act-Utilitarianism 1. Bernard Williams’s critique in Utilitarianism: For and Against 2. Recommended: Williams, “Persons, Character, and Morality,” Moral Luck ch.1 (course packet) 9/22 - 9/24: Hare’s Indirect Utilitarianism 1. R. M. Hare, Freedom and Reason , chapters 2, 3 & 7. 3. Discussion of the implicit subjectivism in Hare’s principle of universalizability. 9/29 - 10/1: Rawls’s solution to the subjectivism of Hare’s principle 1. A Theory of Justice, chapter 1, chapter 2 §§10-17, and chapter 4 §40 (course packet) 2. Handouts 10/6 - 10/8: A psychological pluralist neo-Kantianism: Christine Korsgaard 1. Korsgaard, “The Authority of Reflection,” in The Sources of Normativity , ch.3 (course packet) 2. First paper due 10/13: Columbus Day (no class). Part II: Critiques of Egoism and Impartiality 10/15 : Feinberg’s critique of egoism, with developments 1. Feinberg, “Psychological Egoism” (course packet) 2. Handout on Feinberg.(course packet) 10/20 - 10/22: Parfit on Indirect Moral Egoism 3. Derek Parfit’s Reasons and Persons , chapter 1 1. Derek Parfit’s Reasons and Persons , chapters 2 and 4. 10/27 - 10/29: Stocker’s critique of utilitarian and deontological moral theories 1. Stocker, “The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories” (course packet) 11/3 - 11/5: Raz on Universalism and Particularism 1. Raz, Value, Respect, and Attachment , chapters 1 & 2. 11/10 - 11/12: Raz and Sandel on ends essential to the self 1. Raz continued. 2. Michael Sandel’s critique of Rawlsian individualism (course packet). 11/10: Recommended: The Annual Sullivan Lecture , “Versions of Political Philosophy,” by Francis Slade, 6PM, 12 th Floor Lounge. Part III: Neo-Aristotelian Virtue Ethics 11/17 - 11/19: MacIntyre on Virtues, Practices, and the Unity of a Life 1. MacIntyre, After Virtue , chapters 14 - 15 (course packet). 11/24: MacIntyre’s neo-Thomist social ethic: 1. MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals , chapters 1 & 2. 12/1 - 12/3: MacIntyre continued. 1. MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals , chapters 3 & 4. 12/8: Final Paper Due..
Recommended publications
  • A Confucian Defense of Shame: Morality, Self-Cultivation, and the Dangers of Shamelessness
    religions Article Article Article A ConfucianA Confucian Defense Defense of Shame: of Shame: Morality, Morality, Self-Cultivation, Self-Cultivation, A Confucian Defense of Shame: Morality, Self-Cultivation, and theand Dangers the Dangers of Shamelessness of Shamelessness and the Dangers of Shamelessness Mark BerksonMark Berkson Mark Berkson Department of Religion,Department Hamline of Religion, University, Hamline St. Paul, University, MN 55104, St. USA;Paul, [email protected] 55104, USA; [email protected] Department of Religion, Hamline University, St. Paul, MN 55104, USA; [email protected] Abstract: ManyAbstract: philosophers Many and philosophers scholars in and the scholars West have in the a negative West have view a negative of shame. view In muchof shame. In much of Abstract: Many philosophers and scholars in the West have a negative view of shame.of post-classical In much ofpost-classical Western ethical Western thought, ethical shame thought, is compared shame is negativelycompared negatively with guilt, with as shame guilt, isas shame is asso- post-classical Western ethical thought, shame is compared negatively with guilt, asassociated shame is asso- withciated the “outer”, with the how “outer”, one appears how one before appears others before (and othe thusrs is (and merely thus a is matter merely of a “face”), matter of “face”), and ciated with the “outer”, how one appears before others (and thus is merely a matterand of “face”), guilt is and associatedguilt is associated with the “inner”with the realm “inner” of therealm conscience of the conscience and soul. and Anthropologists soul. Anthropologists and and philoso- guilt is associated with the “inner” realm of the conscience and soul.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility
    Consequentialism and Moral Responsibility Draft of September 2015 Elinor Mason For Christian Seidel (ed.) Consequentialism: new directions, new problems? OUP, forthcoming. There are two different ways of thinking about the relationship between consequentialism and moral responsibility. First, we might think that consequentialism can give us an account of responsibility. I discuss this possibility briefly, and then set it aside. The other way of thinking about the relationship is the focus of this paper. The question that concerns me, is, to what extent is a normative theory, consequentialism in particular, constrained by requirements that stem from concerns about responsibility? 1. Consequentialist Accounts of Moral Responsibility J.J.C. Smart suggests that we can extend consequentialist reasoning about morality to reasoning about responsibility. One of the attractions of consequentialism is that it provides such a straightforward and attractive account of justification for our moral practices. Why do we pay our taxes, treat each other with respect, look after each other and so on? Because doing so has good consequences. However, this sort of justification, though very appealing when considering moral practice, becomes extremely counterintuitive in other sorts of case. For example, it seems obvious that justification for beliefs cannot be consequentialist. Beliefs must be justified in some way that relates to their truth, though of course there is disagreement about exactly what makes a belief justified. Similarly, so a familiar line of thought goes, whether or not someone is responsible for an act, or for anything else, cannot be determined by looking at the consequences of holding them responsible. The claim that 1 responsibility can be understood in a consequentialist way seems like a category mistake.1 Smart’s view might be correct that, insofar as praising and blaming are actions, consequentialists should take the value of the consequences of performing those acts as the relevant factor in deciding whether or not to perform them.
    [Show full text]
  • Han Feizi's Criticism of Confucianism and Its Implications for Virtue Ethics
    JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY Journal of Moral Philosophy 5 (2008) 423–453 www.brill.nl/jmp Han Feizi’s Criticism of Confucianism and its Implications for Virtue Ethics * Eric L. Hutton Department of Philosophy, University of Utah, 215 S. Central Campus Drive, CTIHB, 4th fl oor, Salt Lake City, UT 84112, USA [email protected] Abstract Several scholars have recently proposed that Confucianism should be regarded as a form of virtue ethics. Th is view off ers new approaches to understanding not only Confucian thinkers, but also their critics within the Chinese tradition. For if Confucianism is a form of virtue ethics, we can then ask to what extent Chinese criticisms of it parallel criticisms launched against contemporary virtue ethics, and what lessons for virtue ethics in general might be gleaned from the challenges to Confucianism in particular. Th is paper undertakes such an exercise in examining Han Feizi, an early critic of Confucianism. Th e essay off ers a careful interpretation of the debate between Han Feizi and the Confucians and suggests that thinking through Han Feizi’s criticisms and the possible Confucian responses to them has a broader philosophical payoff , namely by highlighting a problem for current defenders of virtue ethics that has not been widely noticed, but deserves attention. Keywords Bernard Williams, Chinese philosophy, Confucianism, Han Feizi, Rosalind Hursthouse, virtue ethics Although Confucianism is now almost synonymous with Chinese culture, over the course of history it has also attracted many critics from among the Chinese themselves. Of these critics, one of the most interesting is Han Feizi (ca.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Bernard Williams's Criticism of Aristotelian Naturalism
    UNDERSTANDING BERNARD WILLIAMS’S CRITICISM OF ARISTOTELIAN NATURALISM Michael Addison A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of MPhil at the University of St Andrews 2015 Full metadata for this item is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this item: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/9315 This item is protected by original copyright Understanding Bernard Williams’s Criticism of Aristotelian Naturalism. Michael Addison This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of MPhil at the University of St Andrews 19th November 2015 Abstract: In Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (henceforth ELP) Williams claims that holding a naturalistic Aristotelian ethical theory is no longer an option for us—we cannot believe what Aristotle believed about human beings. It is the purpose of this thesis to understand what Williams means by this claim and to evaluate whether or not it constitutes a pressing argument against Aristotelian naturalism. The modern Aristotelian (represented here by Martha Nussbaum, Philippa Foot and Rosalind Hursthouse) seems to be untouched by the claim as presented—they do not have to hold Aristotle’s view of human nature. The Aristotelian approaches human nature, not from an “outside” perspective, like the scientist, but from an “inside” perspective—from the point of view of an ethically engaged agent. The method does not seek to use a theory-independent notion of human nature to vindicate the Aristotelian claim that the properly functioning human being is virtuous. Rather, the Aristotelian is engaged in a project of using the notions of virtue that we already possess, to paint a picture of the kind of lives that we can all identify with, and endorse as properly functioning.
    [Show full text]
  • RICHARD HARE 07 Hare 1226 15/11/2004 10:29 Page 117
    07 Hare 1226 15/11/2004 10:29 Page 116 RICHARD HARE 07 Hare 1226 15/11/2004 10:29 Page 117 Richard Mervyn Hare 1919–2002 RICHARD HARE left behind at his death a long essay titled ‘APhilosophical Autobiography’, which has since been published.1 Its opening is striking: I had a strange dream, or half-waking vision, not long ago. I found myself at the top of a mountain in the mist, feeling very pleased with myself, not just for having climbed the mountain, but for having achieved my life’s ambition, to find a way of answering moral questions rationally. But as I was preening myself on this achievement, the mist began to clear, and I saw that I was surrounded on the mountain top by the graves of all those other philosophers, great and small, who had had the same ambition, and thought they had achieved it. And I have come to see, reflecting on my dream, that, ever since, the hard-working philo- sophical worms had been nibbling away at their systems and showing that the achievement was an illusion. Yet his imagination could also be less modest: a gaggle of moral philoso- phers is trapped beneath the earth in a smoke-filled chamber; they talk at cross purposes, and refuse to take the way out into the open air that he alone has discovered. It was his ambition to have united elements from Aristotle, Kant, and Mill in a logically cogent way that solved the funda- mental problems of ethics (though with unfinished business); and he usu- ally believed himself to have achieved this.
    [Show full text]
  • “Human Being” a Moral Concept?
    QQ version – Oct. 26, 2010 Is “Human Being” a Moral Concept? Douglas MacLean Is “human being” a moral concept? I believe it is, which makes me a speciesist. Speciesism violates a moral principle of equality. Peter Singer defines it as “a prejudice or attitude of bias toward the interests of members of one’s own species and against those of members of other species.” He compares it to racism. My goal in this essay is to defend a speciesist attitude or outlook on morality. This defense consists in little more than sympathetically describing certain intuitions and exploring some of their implications. I have no further argument to show that this view is true or correct; in fact, I don’t know what such an argument would look like. As I see it, each side in debates about speciesism reveals different assumptions or begs different questions about the foundation of ethics. Critics of speciesism see ethics as grounded in status-conferring individual properties that generate agent-neutral reasons. The outlook I will describe is based on a conviction that ethics is inextricably tied to practices that define what it is to live a human life. The most general reasons in this conception of morality are human reasons. They are norms for creatures like us, but not necessarily for gods, intelligent aliens, or other possible agents. They are not agent-neutral. By defending a speciesist outlook on morality I do not mean to suggest that animal suffering has no moral significance. A decent human life takes seriously things like cruelty, callousness, or indifference to the natural world.
    [Show full text]
  • Bernard Williams on Ethical Theory
    Bernard Williams on Ethical Theory A Study of Bernard Williams' Critique of Ethical Theory and its Implications for doing Moral Philosophy Ivo R. Kreft A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Queen's University Kingston, Ontario, Canada January 1998 copyright 8 Ivo R. Kreft, 1998 National Library Bibliothey nationale d Canada du Cana a Acquisitions and Acquisitions et Bibliographie Services services bibliographiques 395 Wellkqton Street 395, rue Wellington ûttawaûN K1AOiU4 Onawa ON KIA ON4 Canada Canada The author has granted a non- L'auteur a accordé une licence non exclusive licence dowing the exclusive permettant a la National Library of Canada to Bibliothèque nationale du Canada de reproduce, loan, distriiute or seLi reproduire, prêter, distribuer ou copies of this thesis in microform, vendre des copies de cette thèse sous paper or electronic formats. la forme de microfiche/fïlm, de reproduction sur papier ou sur format électronique. The author retains ownership of the L'auteur conserve la propriété du copyright in this thesis. Neither the droit d'auteur qui protège cette thése. thesis nor substantial extracts fkom it Ni la thèse ni des extraits substantiels may be printed or otherwise de celle-ci ne doivent être imprimés reproduced without the author's ou autrement reproduits sans son permission. autorisation. Abstract This thesis will evaluate the effect Bernard Williams' critique of ethical theory has on moral philosophy, and defend the view that although Williams has shown the inadequacies of theory, moral philosophy cm still enquire into the nature of ethics and produce substantive results.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics, Final Paper
    Ethics 24.231 Paper Topics – Final Paper – DUE December 9th by the BEGINNING of class. Please write a 2000-2500 word paper in response to one of the following topics OR in response to any of the paper topics from earlier in the term on which you have not yet written. (Of course, if you choose to respond to an earlier topic, you paper should still be 2000-2500 words long.) As before, you may choose to answer only some parts of a question, but you must be clear about what parts you are addressing. 1. Explain and evaluate Bernard Williams’ argument on pages 239-241 of “The Idea of Equality” for the conclusion that medical care should be distributed on the basis of medical need. Do you think Williams’ argument is sound? Does a parallel argument entail that haircuts should be distributed on the basis of haircutting need? 2. In “Famine, Affluence, and Morality”, Peter Singer develops an argument for the conclusion that we ought to provide much, much more assistance than we do to needy strangers. His argument appeals to the following principle: If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it. Carefully set out Singer’s argument. Do you think the principle to which Singer appeals is true? If not, why not? In evaluating Singer’s argument, you may want to consider whether a decision not to give to famine relief differs in morally significant ways from a decision not to save a child drowning in a pond, because doing so would ruin your shoes.
    [Show full text]
  • Oedipus's Responsibility: the Problem of Moral Luck Bernard Williams and Thomas Nagel
    2021-4218-AJHA – 28 APR 2021 1 Oedipus’s Responsibility: The Problem of Moral Luck 2 Bernard Williams and Thomas Nagel 3 4 In mythology, Oedipus is determined by destiny or fate to a set of actions. If 5 he is not responsible for his fate or luck, will he be responsible for his crimes? 6 Can moral judgments be independent of luck, chance or fortune? Following 7 an example proposed by Nagel: two agents (with the same intention, desire, 8 belief, etc.) shoot someone. The first agent hits his target. The second agent 9 does not hit, because, luckily, a bird crossed the path of the bullet fired. Both 10 agents wanted to hit the target, but by chance or luck interference only one 11 hits. Do we judge both agents in the same moral way? The moral 12 responsibility of an agent over his actions seems inseparable from a principle 13 of control of the agent over his actions. However, when we analyse the object 14 of the moral judgment (agent, actions) the evaluation over it varies 15 according to elements of luck (constitutive, circumstantial, resulting, causal 16 fortune). Does luck introduce a paradox into the core of moral judgments 17 (Nagel's thesis), which limits any conception of morality (as Williams 18 argues)? In this paper we defend the need to consider morally agents and 19 actions, regardless of whether they are or are not subject to luck. 20 21 Keywords: Bernard Williams, luck, moral, Thomas Nagel. 22 23 24 Introduction: The Tension between Morality and Luck 25 26 Can moral judgments be independent of luck? The moral responsibility of 27 an agent for his actions seems inseparable from a principle of control of the agent 28 over his actions.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism and Commitment
    CONSEQUENTIALISM AND COMMITMENT BY ALASTAIR NORCROSS Abstract: It is sometimes claimed that a consequentialist theory such as utilitarianism has problems accommodating the importance of personal commitments to other people. However, by emphasizing the distinction between criteria of rightness and decision procedures, a consequentialist can allow for non-consequentialist decision procedures, such as acting directly on the promptings of natural affection. Furthermore, such non- consequentialist motivational structures can co-exist happily with a commitment to consequentialism. It is possible to be a self-reflective consequentialist who has genuine commitments to individuals and to moral principles, without engaging in self-deception. Personal commitments, to people and, to a lesser extent, to principles, are a very important part of most people’s lives. They give shape and meaning to our lives, and help to constitute our identity. To say that I am Diana’s husband and David’s father is to give more than mere relational information about me. It says something fundamental about my motivational structure. There are things I would do for Diana and David, risks I would take, sacrifices I would endure, that I wouldn’t even consider for a perfect stranger, or even a fairly close friend. For most of us, it is hard to imagine what a life devoid of such commitments would be like. And yet, certain moral theories seem to require that we abandon them, or at least be prepared to abandon them whenever they conflict with the demands of impersonal morality. Both consequentialist theories and Kantian versions of deontology have been accused of being inimical to commitments.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Bernard Williams' Criticism of the City-Soul Analogy in Plato's Republic
    The 3rd BESETO Conference of Philosophy Session 14 Rethinking Bernard Williams’ Criticism of the City-Soul Analogy in Plato’s Republic (draft) WU Tianyue Peking University Abstract This essay takes a close look at Bernard Williams’ criticism of the city-soul analogy in Plato’s Republic, which “has dominated the discussion of its subject ever since.” (Myles Burnyeat). I start with reviving Williams’ arguments to elucidate the genuine challenge to Plato’s theory of justice by introducing city-soul analogy. The second part of this essay aims to show that Williams’ critics, such as Jonathan Lear, G.R.F. Ferrari, and Nobert Blössner have not successfully solved the problems Williams brought forth in his article. Finally, I call attention to a neglected aspect of the city-soul analogy, i.e. the predominance of reason in Plato’s theory of justice. By carefully analyzing Plato’s account of justice and briefly addressing the discussion about philosopher-kings in Book V–VII, I argue that Plato actually defines justice as the rule of the reasoning part. With this new definition of justice, the city-soul analogy will be shown philo- sophically accountable within the whole argumentative structure of Republic. It is well known that Republic is not an accurate translation of the ancient Greek word πολιτεία, whose meanings range from “condition and rights of a citizen” to “constitution of a state”1. The Chinese translation Li Xiang Guo, which literally means the ideal state, even goes further to iden- tify Plato’s magnum opus as a utopian writing. However, Plato’s or Socrates’ mythical narrative2 of the ideal city (καλλιπόλις) and its constitution starts rather late in the middle of Book II of Republic.
    [Show full text]
  • Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy
    Res Cogitans Volume 8 Issue 1 Article 9 2017 Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy Kexin Yu University of Rochester, [email protected] Recommended Citation Yu, Kexin (2017) "Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy," Res Cogitans: Vol. 8: Iss. 1, Article 9. https://doi.org/ 10.7710/2155-4838.1169 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by CommonKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Res Cogitans by an authorized editor of CommonKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Res Cogitans (2017) 8:1 2155-4838 | commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Unpacking the City-Soul Analogy Kexin Yu University of Rochester Published online: September 7 2017 © Kexin Yu 2017 Abstract In the Republic, the city-soul analogy made by Plato paves the way for the entire dialogue. The main interlocutors use the analogy to show the nature of justice and aim to prove that just people live better and are happier than unjust people, by establishing a city to which justice, as defined by them, is applied. Scholars have recently been debating the validity of this analogy. Some critics assert that there are several significant structural inconsistencies and logical misconceptions, thus making the analogy fallacious; at the same time, there are proponents who write extensively in favor of this analogy and defend it against the objections raised. In this paper, I will re-examine passages in the Republic where the analogy first occurs, evaluate the critique made by Bernard Williams, and present arguments defending Plato’ strategy. Ultimately, I will show that Plato’ city-soul analogy is not as far-fetched as Williams argues and this analogy – as a crucial strategy of Plato’s – is efficient and powerful enough in showing the similarities between the city and the soul, for the interlocutors to justifiably and reasonably reach the conclusion that the justice of the individual is the same as that of the city.
    [Show full text]