Soundness and Completeness of the Cirquent Calculus System CL6 for Computability Logic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Soundness and Completeness of the Cirquent Calculus System CL6 for Computability Logic Soundness and completeness of the Cirquent calculus system CL6 for computability logic WENYAN XU and SANYANG LIU, Department of Mathematics, Xidian University, Xi’an, 710071, PR China. E-mail: [email protected]; [email protected] Downloaded from Abstract Computability logic is a formal theory of computability. The earlier article ‘Introduction to cirquent calculus and abstract resource semantics’ by Japaridze proved soundness and completeness for the basic fragment CL5 of computability logic. The present article extends that result to the more expressive cirquent calculus system CL6, which is a conservative extension of http://jigpal.oxfordjournals.org/ both CL5 and classical propositional logic. Keywords: Cirquent calculus, computability logic. 1 Introduction Computability logic (CoL), introduced by G. Japaridze [1, 2, 6], is a semantical and mathematical platform for redeveloping logic as a formal theory of computability. Formulas in CoL represent interactive computational problems, understood as games between a machine and its environment at CSU Fresno on July 29, 2015 (symbolically named as and ⊥, respectively); logical operators stand for operations on such problems; ‘truth’ of a problem/game means existence of an algorithmic solution, i.e. ’s effective winning strategy; and validity of a logical formula is understood as such truth under every particular interpretation of atoms. The approach induces a rich collection of (old or new) logical operators. Among those, relevant to this article are ¬ (negation), ∨ (parallel disjunction) and ∧ (parallel conjunction). Intuitively, ¬ is a role switch operator: ¬A is the game A with the roles of and ⊥ interchanged (’s legal moves and wins become those of ⊥, and vice versa). Both A∧B and A∨B are games playing which means playing the two components A and B simultaneously (in parallel). In A∧B, is the winner if it wins in both components, while in A∨B winning in just one component is sufficient. The symbols and ⊥, together with denoting the two players, are also used to denote two special (the simplest) sorts of games. Namely, is a moveless (‘elementary’) game automatically won by the player , and ⊥ is a moveless game automatically won by ⊥. Cirquent calculus is a refinement of sequent calculus. Unlike the more traditional proof theories that manipulate tree-like objects (formulas, sequents, hypersequents, etc.), cirquent calculus deals with graph-style structures termed cirquents, with its main characteristic feature thus being allowing to explicitly account for sharing subcomponents between different components. The approach was introduced by Japaridze [4] as a new deductive tool for CoL, and was further developed in [5, 7, 8]. The article [4] constructed a cirquent calculus system CL5 for the basic (¬,∧,∨)-fragment of CoL, and proved its soundness and completeness with respect to the semantics of CoL. Vol. 20 No. 1, © The Author 2011. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] doi:10.1093/jigpal/jzr043 Advance Access published 29 October 2011 [17:18 13/1/2012 jzr043.tex] Paper Size: a4 paper Job: JIGPAL Page: 317 317–330 318 Cirquent calculus system The atoms of CL5 represent computational problems in general, and are said to be general atoms. The so-called elementary atoms, representing computational problems of zero degree of interactivity (such as the earlier-mentioned games and ⊥) and studied in other pieces of literature on CoL, are not among them. Thus, CL5 only describes valid computability principles for general problems. This is a significant limitation of expressive power. For example, the formula A→A∧A is not valid in CoL when A is a general atom, but becomes valid (as any classical tautology for that matter) when A is elementary.1 So the language of CL5 naturally calls for an extension. Japaridze [4] claimed without a proof that the soundness and completeness result for CL5 could be extended to the more expressive cirquent calculus system CL6 (reproduced later), which is a conservative extension of both CL5 and classical propositional logic. This article is devoted to a soundness and completeness proof for system CL6, thus contributing to the task of extending the cirquent-calculus approach so as to accommodate incrementally expressive fragments of CoL. Downloaded from 2 Preliminaries This article primarily targets readers already familiar with Japaridze [4], and can essentially be treated as a technical appendix to the latter. However, in order to make it reasonably self-contained, http://jigpal.oxfordjournals.org/ in this section we reproduce the basic concepts from [4, 6]. An interested reader may consult (the extremely well written) [4] and [6] for additional explanations, illustrations, examples and insights. 2.1 Games and strategies The letter ℘ is used as a variable ranging over {,⊥}, with ¬℘ meaning ℘’s adversary. A move is a finite string over the standard keyboard alphabet. A labmove is a move prefixed (‘labeled’) with or ⊥. A run is a finite or infinite sequence of labmoves, and a position is a finite run. Runs are at CSU Fresno on July 29, 2015 usually delimited by ‘’ and ‘’, with thus denoting the empty run. For any run , ¬ is the same as , with the only difference that every label ℘ is changed to ¬℘. A game2 is a pair A=(LrA,WnA), where: (i) LrA is a set of runs satisfying the condition that a finite or infinite run is in LrA iff so are all of ’s non-empty finite initial segments.3 If ∈LrA, then is said to be a legal run of A; otherwise is an illegal run of A. A move α is a legal move for a player ℘ in a position of A iff ,℘α∈LrA; otherwise α is an illegal move. When the last move of the shortest illegal initial segment of is ℘-labeled, is said to be a ℘-illegal run of A. (ii) WnA is a function that sends every run to one of the players or ⊥, satisfying the condition that if is a ℘-illegal run of A, then WnA=¬℘. When WnA=℘, is said to be a ℘-won run of A. Let A be a game. The depth of A is the smallest integer d such that the length of every legal run of A is ≤d. A is said to be elementary iff the depth of it is 0. There are exactly two elementary games, for which the same symbols and ⊥ are used as for the two players. We identify these with the two propositions of classical logic: (true) and ⊥ (false). ‘Snow is white’ is thus a moveless game automatically won by the machine, while ‘Snow is black’ is automatically lost. This is exactly what eventually makes classical propositional logic a natural fragment of CoL. 1This will be explained later. 2The concept of a game considered in CoL is more general than the one defined here, with games in the present sense called constant games. For simplicity, in this article we only consider constant games, omitting the word ‘constant’ and just saying ‘game’. 3This condition can be seen to imply that the empty run is always in LrA. [17:18 13/1/2012 jzr043.tex] Paper Size: a4 paper Job: JIGPAL Page: 318 317–330 Cirquent calculus system 319 Let be a run and α be a move. The notation α will be used to indicate the result of deleting from all moves (together with their labels) except those that look like αβ for some move β, and then further deleting the prefix ‘α’ from such moves. For instance, 1.α,⊥2.β,1.γ,⊥2.δ1. =α,γ. The game operations outlined intuitively in the preceding section are defined below, where A, A1, A2 are arbitrary games, α ranges over moves, i ∈{1,2}, is an arbitrary run, and is any legal run of the game that is being defined. (1) ¬A (negation) is defined by: Downloaded from (i) ∈Lr¬A iff ¬∈LrA. (ii) Wn¬A = iff WnA¬ =⊥. (2) A1 ∧A2 (parallel conjunction) is defined by: ∧ . (i) ∈LrA1 A2 iff every move of is i.α for some i,α and, for both i, i ∈LrAi . ∧ . (ii) WnA1 A2 = iff, for both i, WnAi i =. http://jigpal.oxfordjournals.org/ (3) A1 ∨A2 (parallel disjunction) is defined by: ∨ . (i) ∈LrA1 A2 iff every move of is i.α for some i,α and, for both i, i ∈LrAi . ∨ . (ii) WnA1 A2 = iff, for some i, WnAi i =. Intuitively, making a move i.α in A1 ∧A2 or A1 ∨A2 means making the move α in the Ai component of the game; and i. (respectively i.) is the subrun of (respectively ) that took place in that component. In what follows, we explain—formally or informally—several additional basic concepts of the CoL semantics. at CSU Fresno on July 29, 2015 (1) Static games: CoL restricts its attention to a special yet very wide subclass of games termed ‘static’. Intuitively, static games are interactive tasks where the relative speeds of the players are irrelevant, as it never hurts a player to postpone making moves. A formal definition of this concept can be found in [6], which we will not reproduce here as nothing in this article relies on it. The only relevant for us fact is that all elementary games are static, and that, as proven in [1, 6], the class of static games is closed under the operations ¬,∧,∨ (as well as any other game operations studied in CoL). (2) HPMs: CoL understands ’s effective strategies as interactive machines. Several sorts of such machines have been proposed and studied in CoL, all of them turning out to be equivalent in computing power once we exclusively consider static games. The most basic sort of such machines is called the hard-play machine (HPM). This is a kind of a Turing machine with the additional capability of making moves, and has two tapes4: the ordinary read/write work tape and the read-only run tape.
Recommended publications
  • Giorgi Japaridze
    Giorgi Japaridze Curriculum Vitae CONTACT INFORMATION Address: Computing Sciences Department, Villanova University, 800 Lancaster Avenue, Villanova, PA 19085, USA. Email: [email protected] Telephone: (1) 610 519 7332 Fax: (1) 610 519 7889 Home page: http://www.csc.villanova.edu/~japaridz/ EDUCATION 1998 Ph.D. Computer Science, University of Pennsylvania Dissertation: The Logic of Resources and Tasks 1987 Ph.D. Logic, Moscow State University Dissertation: Modal-Logical Means of Studying Provability 1983 M.S. Philosophy, Tbilisi State University (Georgia, former USSR) Thesis: The Notion of Truth in Formalized Languages LANGUAGES: Georgian, Russian, English, Chinese (Mandarin), German. EMPLOYMENT HISTORY 2008 - present Full Professor Computing Sciences Department, Villanova University, Villanova, PA, USA 2010 - 2013 Chair Professor School of Computer Science and Technology, Shandong University, Jinan, China 2004-2008 Associate Professor Computing Sciences Department, Villanova University, Villanova, PA, USA 2007 Visiting Professor School of Information Science and Technology, Institute of Artificial Intelligence, Xiamen University, Fujian, Xiamen, China 1998 -2003 Assistant Professor Computing Sciences Department, Villanova University, Villanova, PA, USA 1995-1998 Research Assistant Dept. of Computer and Information Science, University of Pennsylvania, Philadelphia, PA, USA 1993-1994 Visiting Associate Professor Philosophy Department, University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN, USA 1992-1993 Postdoctoral Fellow Dept. of Mathematics and Computer Science, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam, The Netherlands 1987-1992 Senior Researcher Institute of Philosophy, Georgian Academy of Sciences, Tbilisi, Georgia (former USSR) Main Contributions to Science Provability and interpretability logics (1985-1998) While a student, introduced polymodal provability logic GLP, and proved its arithmetical completeness. This contained a solution of an open problem on the logic of provability raised by George Boolos a decade earlier (1985-1988).
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Computability Logic I∗
    Propositional computability logic I∗ Giorgi Japaridze† Department of Computing Sciences, Villanova University, 800 Lancaster Avenue, Villanova, PA 19085, USA. Email: [email protected] URL: http://www.csc.villanova.edu/∼ japaridz/ Abstract In the same sense as classical logic is a formal theory of truth, the recently initiated approach called computability logic is a formal theory of computability. It understands (interactive) computational prob- lems as games played by a machine against the environment, their computability as existence of a machine that always wins the game, logical operators as operations on computational problems, and validity of a logical formula as being a scheme of “always computable” problems. Computability logic has been introduced semantically, and now among its main technical goals is to axiomatize the set of valid formu- las or various natural fragments of that set. The present contribution signifies a first step towards this goal. It gives a detailed exposition of a soundness and completeness proof for the rather new type of a deductive propositional system CL1, the logical vocabulary of which contains operators for the so called parallel and choice operations, and the atoms of which represent elementary problems, i.e. predicates in the standard sense. This article is self-contained as it explains all relevant concepts. While not technically necessary, however, familiarity with the foundational paper “Introduction to computability logic” [Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 123 (2003), pp.1-99] would greatly help the reader in understanding the philosophy, underlying motivations, potential and utility of computability logic, — the context that determines the value of the present results.
    [Show full text]
  • Contribution of Warsaw Logicians to Computational Logic
    axioms Article Contribution of Warsaw Logicians to Computational Logic Damian Niwi ´nski Institute of Informatics, University of Warsaw, 02-097 Warsaw, Poland; [email protected]; Tel.: +48-22-554-4460 Academic Editor: Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska Received: 22 April 2016; Accepted: 31 May 2016; Published: 3 June 2016 Abstract: The newly emerging branch of research of Computer Science received encouragement from the successors of the Warsaw mathematical school: Kuratowski, Mazur, Mostowski, Grzegorczyk, and Rasiowa. Rasiowa realized very early that the spectrum of computer programs should be incorporated into the realm of mathematical logic in order to make a rigorous treatment of program correctness. This gave rise to the concept of algorithmic logic developed since the 1970s by Rasiowa, Salwicki, Mirkowska, and their followers. Together with Pratt’s dynamic logic, algorithmic logic evolved into a mainstream branch of research: logic of programs. In the late 1980s, Warsaw logicians Tiuryn and Urzyczyn categorized various logics of programs, depending on the class of programs involved. Quite unexpectedly, they discovered that some persistent open questions about the expressive power of logics are equivalent to famous open problems in complexity theory. This, along with parallel discoveries by Harel, Immerman and Vardi, contributed to the creation of an important area of theoretical computer science: descriptive complexity. By that time, the modal m-calculus was recognized as a sort of a universal logic of programs. The mid 1990s saw a landmark result by Walukiewicz, who showed completeness of a natural axiomatization for the m-calculus proposed by Kozen. The difficult proof of this result, based on automata theory, opened a path to further investigations.
    [Show full text]
  • Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 8 Games, Game Theory and Game Semantics Article 5 2013 Ptarithmetic Giorgi Japaridze School of Computer Science and Technology, Shandong University; Department of Computing Sciences, Villanova University Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc Part of the Theory and Algorithms Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Japaridze, Giorgi (2013) "Ptarithmetic," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 8. https://doi.org/10.4148/1944-3676.1074 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Ptarithmetic 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of and developed (Japaridze 2011, unpublished, forth.). In retrospect, Cognition, Logic and Communication however, the author finds that “Ptarithmetic” contained a number of potentially useful ideas that have not been subsequently adopted by November 2013 Volume 8: Games, Game Theory the “clarithmetics” line of research (at least not yet), and that, for this and Game Semantics reason, it would be a pity to let this material remain unpublished. pages 1-186 DOI: 10.4148/1944-3676.1074 Probably the most important of such ideas is the “Polynomial Time Induction” (PTI) rule of Ptarithmetic, with no close or distant relatives elsewhere in the literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Games and Logic
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 8 Games, Game Theory and Game Semantics Article 8 2013 Games and Logic Gabriel Sandu University of Helsinki Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc Part of the Logic and Foundations Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Sandu, Gabriel (2013) "Games and Logic," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 8. https://doi.org/10.4148/1944-3676.1072 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Games and Logic 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of x”. Their scopal dependencies and independencies in a first-order sen- Cognition, Logic and Communication tence are recast in terms of the strategic interaction of two players in a game of perfect information. For instance, the first-order sentence November 2013 Volume 8: Games, Game Theory ∀x∃yB(x, y) is analyzed in terms of a game between the universal and Game Semantics player (Abelard) and the existential player (Eloise). They choose indi- pages 1-30 DOI: 10.4148/1944-3676.1072 viduals from the underlying universe of discourse to be the values of the variables x and y, respectively. The order of the choices and the information sets of the players are indicated by the syntax of the sen- GABRIEL SANDU tence.
    [Show full text]
  • ON the SYSTEM CL12 of COMPUTABILITY LOGIC Contents
    Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 11(3:1)2015, pp. 1–71 Submitted Jan. 13, 2013 www.lmcs-online.org Published Jul. 28, 2015 ON THE SYSTEM CL12 OF COMPUTABILITY LOGIC GIORGI JAPARIDZE Department of Computing Sciences, Villanova University, 800 Lancaster Avenue, Villanova, PA 19085, USA URL: http://www.csc.villanova.edu/∼japaridz/ e-mail address: [email protected] Abstract. Computability logic (CoL) is a long-term project for redeveloping logic on the basis of a constructive game semantics, with games seen as abstract models of interactive computational problems. Among the fragments of CoL successfully axiomatized so far is CL12 — a conservative extension of classical first-order logic, whose language augments that of classical logic with the so called choice (“constructive”) sorts of quantifiers and connectives. This system has already found fruitful applications as a logical basis for constructive and complexity-bound versions of Peano arithmetic, such as arithmetics for polynomial time computability, polynomial space computability, and beyond. The present paper introduces a third, indispensable complexity measure for interactive computations termed amplitude complexity, and establishes the adequacy (soundness/completeness) of CL12 and the associated Logical Consequence mechanism with respect to (simultaneously) A amplitude, S space and T time computability under certain minimal conditions on the triples (A,S,T ) of function classes. This result very substantially broadens the potential application areas of CL12, even when time and/or space complexity is the only concern. It would be sufficient to point out that, for instance, now CL12 can be reliably used as a logical basis of systems for logarithmic space or exponential time computabilities — something that the earlier-known crude adequacy results for CL12 were too weak to allow us to do.
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Projects in Discrete Mathematics and Computer Science
    Historical Projects in Discrete Mathematics and Computer Science Janet Barnett, Guram Bezhanishvili, Hing Leung, Jerry Lodder, David Pengelley, Desh Ranjan 1 Introduction A course in discrete mathematics is a relatively recent addition, within the last 30 or 40 years, to the modern American undergraduate curriculum, born out of a need to instruct computer science ma- jors in algorithmic thought. The roots of discrete mathematics, however, are as old as mathematics itself, with the notion of counting a discrete operation, usually cited as the first mathematical devel- opment in ancient cultures [38]. By contrast, a course in finite mathematics is sometimes presented as a fast-paced news reel of facts and formulae, often memorized by the students, with the text offering only passing mention of the motivating problems and original work that eventually found resolution in the modern concepts of induction, recursion and algorithm. This chapter focuses on the pedagogy of historical projects, which offer excerpts from original sources, place the material in context, and provide direction to the subject matter. Each historical project is centered around a publication of mathematical significance, such as Blaise Pascal’s “Treatise on the Arithmetical Triangle” [53, vol. 30] from the 1650s or Alan Turing’s 1936 paper “On Computable Numbers with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem” [66]. The projects are designed to introduce or provide supplementary material for topics in the curriculum, such as induction in a discrete mathematics course, or compilers and computability for a computer science course. Each project provides a discussion of the historical exigency of the piece, a few biographical comments about the author, excerpts from the original work, and a sequence of questions to help the student appreciate the source.
    [Show full text]
  • Semantics of Information As Interactive Computation
    Semantics of Information as Interactive Computation Gordana Dodig-Crnkovic Department of Computer Science and Electronics, Mälardalen University. Sweden [email protected] http://www.idt.mdh.se/personal/gdc Abstract. Computers today are not only the calculation tools - they are directly (inter)acting in the physical world which itself may be conceived of as the universal computer (Zuse, Fredkin, Wolfram, Chaitin, Lloyd). In expanding its domains from abstract logical symbol manipulation to physical embedded and networked devices, computing goes beyond Church-Turing limit (Copeland, Siegelman, Burgin, Schachter). Computational processes are distributed, reactive, interactive, agent-based and concurrent. The main criterion of success of computation is not its termination, but the adequacy of its response, its speed, generality and flexibility; adaptability, and tolerance to noise, error, faults, and damage. Interactive computing is a generalization of Turing computing, and it calls for new conceptualizations (Goldin, Wegner). In the info-computationalist framework, with computation seen as information processing, natural computation appears as the most suitable paradigm of computation and information semantics requires logical pluralism. Keywords: Semantic Information, Computationalism, Philosophy of Computing, Hypercomputating, Philosophy of Information 1 Introduction Every epoch and culture has a different conception of the universe. For some (numerous ancient myths, Thales, Spinoza) universe was a living organism. For Ptolemy, Descartes, and Newton it was a huge machine. Our current understanding of information and computing has led to a conception of the universe as a computer. On such a pancomputational and paninformational view (Zuse, Fredkin, Wolfram, Chaitin, Lloyd) we can consider information as a result of (natural) computation, and the universe as a network of computing processes that are defined by the information they manipulate and produce.
    [Show full text]
  • Computability Logic გამოთვლადობის ლოგიკა Логика Вычислимости 可计算性逻辑 (Col)
    12/14/2016 Giorgi Japaridze A Survey of Computability Logic გამოთვლადობის ლოგიკა Логика вычислимости 可计算性逻辑 (col) Computability is one of the most interesting and fundamental concepts in mathematics and computer science, and it is natural to ask what logic it induces. This is where Computability Logic (CoL) comes in. It is a formal theory of computability in the same sense as classical logic is a formal theory of truth. In a broader and more proper sense, CoL is not just a particular theory but an ambitious and challenging program for redeveloping logic following the scheme “from truth to computability”. Under the approach of CoL, logical operators stand for operations on computational problems, formulas represent such problems, and their “truth” is seen as algorithmic solvability. In turn, computational problems ­­­ understood in their most general, interactive sense ­­­ are defined as games played by a machine against its environment, with “algorithmic solvability” meaning existence of a machine which wins the game against any possible behavior of the environment. With this semantics, CoL provides a systematic answer to the question “what can be computed?”, just like classical logic is a systematic tool for telling what is true. Furthermore, as it happens, in positive cases “what can be computed” always allows itself to be replaced by “how can be computed”, which makes CoL of potential interest in not only theoretical computer science, but many applied areas as well, including constructive applied theories, interactive knowledge base systems, resource oriented systems for planning and action, or declarative programming languages. Currently CoL is still at an early stage of development, with open problems prevailing over answered questions.
    [Show full text]
  • Association for Symbolic Logic Business Office: ASL, Dept
    Association for Symbolic Logic Business Office: ASL, Dept. of Mathematics, Univ. of Connecticut 341 Mansfield Road, U-1009, Storrs, CT 06269-1009, USA Phone: 1-860-486-3989; Fax: 1-860-486-4238; email: [email protected] Web: http://www.aslonline.org ASL NEWSLETTER January 2021 • The 2020 ASL Election. In the 2020 election, the members of the ASL elected Juliet Floyd (Boston Univer- sity) and Dima Sinapova (University of Illinois-Chicago) to the Executive Committee; and Sebastiaan Terwijn (Radboud University, Nijmegen) and Wei Li (Chinese Academy of Sciences) to the ASL Council. All terms are for three years beginning January 1, 2021. Many thanks to all those who voted. • Special 25th Anniversary BSL Prize. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic was founded 25 years ago. Over the past 25 years, the BSL has published many expository papers of outstanding quality, on a variety of topics, and from a variety of perspectives within logic. These papers have helped students to get started, they have allowed researchers to see connections between different areas, and they have let all of us see some of the history of our subject. To celebrate, and to advertise the BSL, the ASL is giving a special BSL 25th Anniversary Prize. Here is the list of winning papers from the first 25 years of the BSL. • Jeremy Avigad, \Forcing in proof theory," 10(3):305-333, 2004. • Akihiro Kanamori, \The mathematical development of set theory from Cantor to Cohen," 2(1):1-71, 1996. • Colin McLarty, \What does it take to prove Fermat's Last Theorem?" 16(3):359-377, 2010.
    [Show full text]
  • Build Your Own Clarithmetic I: Setup and Completeness
    Logical Methods in Computer Science Vol. 12(3:8)2016, pp. 1–59 Submitted Oct. 30, 2015 www.lmcs-online.org Published Sep. 6, 2016 BUILD YOUR OWN CLARITHMETIC I: SETUP AND COMPLETENESS GIORGI JAPARIDZE Department of Computing Sciences, Villanova University, 800 Lancaster Avenue, Villanova, PA 19085, USA URL: http://www.csc.villanova.edu/∼japaridz/ e-mail address: [email protected] Abstract. Clarithmetics are number theories based on computability logic. Formulas of these theories represent interactive computational problems, and their “truth” is under- stood as existence of an algorithmic solution. Various complexity constraints on such solutions induce various versions of clarithmetic. The present paper introduces a param- P1,P2,P3 CLA11 P1, P2, P3 eterized/schematic version P4 . By tuning the three parameters in an essentially mechanical manner, one automatically obtains sound and complete theories with respect to a wide range of target tricomplexity classes, i.e., combinations of time (set by P3), space (set by P2) and so called amplitude (set by P1) complexities. Sound in the sense that every theorem T of the system represents an interactive number-theoretic computational problem with a solution from the given tricomplexity class and, further- more, such a solution can be automatically extracted from a proof of T . And complete in the sense that every interactive number-theoretic problem with a solution from the given tricomplexity class is represented by some theorem of the system. Furthermore, through tuning the 4th parameter P4, at the cost of sacrificing recursive axiomatizability but not simplicity or elegance, the above extensional completeness can be strengthened to intensional completeness, according to which every formula representing a problem with a solution from the given tricomplexity class is a theorem of the system.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitæ JOHN PATTON BURGESS
    Curriculum Vitæ JOHN PATTON BURGESS PERSONAL DATA Date of Birth 5 June, 1948 Place of Birth Berea, Ohio, USA Citizenship USA Office Address Department of Philosophy Princeton University Princeton, NJ 08544-1006 USA Office Telephone/ Voice Mail (609)-258-4310 e-mail address [email protected] website www.princeton.edu/~jburgess ACADEMIC EMPLOYMENT PRINCETON UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY 2009- John N. Woodhull Professor of Philosophy 1986-2009 Professor 1981-1986 Associate Professor 1975-1981 Assistant Professor UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN AT MADISON DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS 1974-75 Post-Doctoral Instructor HIGHER EDUCATION 1970-1974 UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA AT BERKELEY 1974 PH.D. IN LOGIC & METHODOLOGY Dissertation: Infinitary Languages & Descriptive Set Theory Supervisor: Jack H. Silver 1969-1970 THE OHIO STATE UNIVERSITY 1970 M. S. IN MATHEMATICS Thesis: Obstacles to Embedding 4-Manifolds Supervisor: Henry H. Glover 1966-1969 PRINCETON UNIVERSITY 1969 A.B. IN MATHEMATICS (summa cum laude, FBK) Thesis: Probability Logic Advisor: Simon B. Kochen EDITORIAL AND RELATED ACTIVITIES F.O.M. [Foundations of Mathematics Moderated Electronic Discussion Board] 2010- Member, Editorial Board TEMPLETON FOUNDATION 2008 Juror, Gödel Centenary Research Prize Fellowships 2007 Juror, Exploring the Infinite, Phase I: Mathematics and Mathematical Logic PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES 2006- Consulting Editor MACMILLAN ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, 2ND ED. 2004-06 Consulting Editor for Logic ASSOCIATION FOR SYMBOLIC LOGIC 2008- Member of Editorial Board for Reviews,
    [Show full text]