Are Children ''Intuitive Theists''?

Are Children ''Intuitive Theists''?

PSYCHOLOGICAL SCIENCE General Article Are Children ‘‘Intuitive Theists’’? Reasoning About Purpose and Design in Nature Deborah Kelemen Boston University ABSTRACT—Separate bodies of research suggest that young chil- objects and behaviors as existing for a purpose (Kelemen, 1999b, 1999c, dren have a broad tendency to reason about natural phenomena 2003; but see Keil, 1992) and are also broadly inclined to view natural in terms of purpose and an orientation toward intention-based phenomena as intentionally created, albeit by a nonhuman agent (Evans, accounts of the origins of natural entities. This article explores 2000b, 2001; Gelman & Kremer, 1991). This article explores these these results further by drawing together recent findings from findings further by drawing them together with other recent cognitive various areas of cognitive developmental research to address the developmental research to address the following question: Even if following question: Rather than being ‘‘artificialists’’ in Pia- children are not artificialists, as Piaget conceived of the term, are they getian terms, are children ‘‘intuitive theists’’—disposed to view perhaps ‘‘intuitive theists’’—predisposed to construe natural objects as natural phenomena as resulting from nonhuman design? A re- though they are nonhuman artifacts, the products of nonhuman design? view of research on children’s concepts of agency, imaginary companions, and understanding of artifacts suggests that by the time children are around 5 years of age, this description of them PROMISCUOUS TELEOLOGY AND ‘‘CREATIONISM’’ IN may have explanatory value and practical relevance. CHILDREN Contemporary research on teleological reasoning—the tendency to Piaget’s (1929) claim that children are ‘‘artificialists’’ who draw on reason about entities and events in terms of purpose—was initiated in their subjective intentional experience to conclude that all things are the context of the debate on the origins of biological understanding. made by people for a purpose has encountered substantial skepticism Consistent with the view that children’s reasoning about living things in the past few decades of cognitive developmental research. This is is constrained by teleological assumptions from a very early age, because, at core, Piaget’s proposal embodied not just the suggestion studies have found that young children attend to shared functional that children misunderstand the limits of human creative power, but a adaptation rather than shared overall appearance (or category mem- stronger claim about the profound incommensurability of children’s bership) when generalizing behaviors to novel animals (Kelemen, and adults’ conceptual systems. Specifically, Piaget believed that Widdowson, Posner, Brown, & Casler, 2003), judge whether biological young children indiscriminately generate artificialist explanations properties are heritable on the basis of their functional consequences because they are psychologically incapable of conceiving of physical rather than their origin (Springer & Keil, 1989), and explain body causes, a shortcoming that he argued rendered them insensitive to the properties by reference to their self-serving functions and not their fundamental distinction between natural kinds and artifacts. physical-mechanical cause (Keil, 1992; Kelemen, 2003). Research since Piaget has challenged these assumptions. Not only can Results like these lend support to the idea that a purpose-based tel- children reason in physical-causal terms from infancy (e.g., Baillargeon, eological stance might, therefore, be humans’ innate adaptation for bio- 1993), but they also recognize that people make artifacts, not natural logical reasoning (Atran, 1995; Keil, 1992). This conclusion has been entities (e.g., Gelman & Kremer, 1991). But although these results may complicated, however, by findings that children see not only the biological put some aspects of Piaget’s interpretation to rest, recent research has but also the nonbiological natural world in teleological terms. For ex- raised the specter of Piaget’s findings once more. Consistent with Piaget’s ample, when asked to identify unanswerable questions, American 4- and results, contemporary studies have found that, although children are not 5-year-olds differ from adults by finding the question ‘‘what’s this for?’’ entirely indiscriminate, they do indeed evidence a general bias to treat appropriate not only to artifacts and body parts, but also to whole living things like lions (‘‘to go in the zoo’’) and nonliving natural kinds like clouds (‘‘for raining’’). Additionally, when asked whether they agree that, Address correspondence to Deborah Kelemen, Department of Psy- for example, raining is really just what a cloud ‘‘does’’ rather than what it chology, Boston University, 64 Cummington St., Boston, MA 02215; is ‘‘made for,’’ preschoolers demur, endorsing the view that natural entities e-mail: [email protected]. are ‘‘made for something’’ and that is why they are here (Kelemen, 1999b). Volume 15—Number 5 Copyright r 2004 American Psychological Society 295 Intuitive Theists? These kinds of promiscuous teleological intuitions persist into changed from a different kind of animal that used to live on earth, or elementary school, particularly in relation to object properties. For (d) it appeared (Evans, 2001). This preference was also found in 5- to instance, when asked to conduct a ‘‘science’’ task and decide whether 7-year-old children’s agreement ratings for animate and inanimate prehistoric rocks were pointy because of a physical process (e.g., ‘‘bits entities. Indeed, it was only among 11- to 13-year-old non- of stuff piled up for a long period of time’’) or because they performed fundamentalist children that divergence from the theist position a function, American 7- and 8-year-olds, unlike adults, preferred emerged. Evans’s results do not stand in isolation. Gelman and teleological explanations whether they invoked ‘‘self-survival’’ func- Kremer (1991) found that although American preschoolers recognize tions (e.g., ‘‘so that animals wouldn’t sit on them and smash them’’) or that artifacts rather than natural entities are human made, they favor ‘‘artifact’’ functions (e.g., ‘‘so that animals could scratch on them when God as the explanation of the origin of remote natural items (e.g., they got itchy’’; Kelemen, 1999c; but see Keil, 1992). This bias in oceans). Petrovich (1997) found similar results with British pre- favor of teleological explanation for properties of both living and schoolers (although see Mead, 1932, on Manus children’s disin- nonliving natural objects occurs even when children are told that clination to use supernatural explanation).1 adults apply physical kinds of explanation to nonliving natural entities Considered together, current data on children’s promiscuous tele- (Kelemen, 2003). In American children, the bias begins to moderate ology and explanations of origins might therefore suggest an obvious around 9 to 10 years of age, and this pattern now has been found also affirmative answer to the question of whether children are intuitive with British children for both object properties and, slightly less theists: Children view natural phenomena as intentionally designed by markedly, natural object wholes. These British findings are relevant a god. Not coincidentally, they therefore view natural objects as ex- because they weigh against interpretations that promiscuous tele- isting for a purpose. But before embracing, or even entertaining, this ological intuitions are a simple reflection of the relatively pronounced conclusion, we must look first at whether it is actually defensible. cultural religiosity, or religious exceptionalism (in postindustrial, in- What evidence is there that children possess any of the conceptual ternational context), of the United States (see Kelemen, 2003, for prerequisites that intuitive theism might entail? What evidence is discussion of religiosity differences). there that their intuitions display any coherence at all? So, if ambient cultural religiosity is not the obvious explanation, what does cause this promiscuous teleology? A study of responses CONCEPTUAL PREREQUISITES TO INTUITIVE THEISM young children receive when asking questions about nature indicates parents generally favor causal rather than teleological explanation, so Piaget (1929) found that when asked how natural objects originated, current evidence suggests the answer does not lie there, at least, not in children frequently identified ‘‘God’’ as the cause. Piaget argued that any straightforward sense (Kelemen, Callanan, Casler, & Pe´rez- these statements were simply further cases of artificialism: Unable to Granados, 2002). Another hypothesis being explored in my lab is, entertain an abstraction such as God, and egocentrically focused, therefore, as follows (e.g., Kelemen, 1999b, 1999c). Perhaps chil- children used ‘‘God’’ to refer to a person who was fundamentally sim- dren’s generalized attributions of purpose are, essentially, side effects ilar to the dominant authority in children’s own lives—their parent. of a socially intelligent mind that is naturally inclined to privilege Once again, however, Piaget’s assumptions about the concreteness intentional explanation and is, therefore, oriented toward explanations of children’s concepts have been challenged. Research now suggests characterizing nature as an intentionally designed artifact—an ori- that rather than being anthropomorphic, children’s earliest concept of entation given further support by the artifact-saturated

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    7 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us