The Real Projective Spaces in Homotopy Type Theory

The Real Projective Spaces in Homotopy Type Theory

The real projective spaces in homotopy type theory Ulrik Buchholtz Egbert Rijke Technische Universität Darmstadt Carnegie Mellon University Email: [email protected] Email: [email protected] Abstract—Homotopy type theory is a version of Martin- topology and homotopy theory developed in homotopy Löf type theory taking advantage of its homotopical models. type theory (homotopy groups, including the fundamen- In particular, we can use and construct objects of homotopy tal group of the circle, the Hopf fibration, the Freuden- theory and reason about them using higher inductive types. In this article, we construct the real projective spaces, key thal suspension theorem and the van Kampen theorem, players in homotopy theory, as certain higher inductive types for example). Here we give an elementary construction in homotopy type theory. The classical definition of RPn, in homotopy type theory of the real projective spaces as the quotient space identifying antipodal points of the RPn and we develop some of their basic properties. n-sphere, does not translate directly to homotopy type theory. R n In classical homotopy theory the real projective space Instead, we define P by induction on n simultaneously n with its tautological bundle of 2-element sets. As the base RP is either defined as the space of lines through the + case, we take RP−1 to be the empty type. In the inductive origin in Rn 1 or as the quotient by the antipodal action step, we take RPn+1 to be the mapping cone of the projection of the 2-element group on the sphere Sn [4]. It has a n map of the tautological bundle of RP , and we use its simple cell complex description with one cell in each universal property and the univalence axiom to define the dimension i ≤ n. Real projective spaces are frequently tautological bundle on RPn+1. By showing that the total space of the tautological bundle used as examples or as bases for computations. Each of RPn is the n-sphere Sn, we retrieve the classical descrip- RPn has as universal covering space the sphere Sn, and tion of RPn+1 as RPn with an (n + 1)-disk attached to it. The its fundamental group is Z/2Z for n > 1. R ¥ infinite dimensional real projective space P , defined as the In homotopy type theory, we would like to have access sequential colimit of RPn with the canonical inclusion maps, is equivalent to the Eilenberg-MacLane space K(Z/2Z, 1), to these spaces and their basic properties, but the above which here arises as the subtype of the universe consisting of definitions do not directly carry over to this setting. 2-element types. Indeed, the infinite dimensional projective We instead give an elementary inductive construction of space classifies the 0-sphere bundles, which one can think the spaces RPn together with their universal coverings of as synthetic line bundles. covn : RPn ! U. (We write U for the first universe These constructions in homotopy type theory further illustrate the utility of homotopy type theory, including the of types.) Indeed, the universal coverings are fibrations n interplay of type theoretic and homotopy theoretic ideas. where the fibers are 2-element sets, so the maps cov Keywords. Real projective spaces, Homotopy Type Theory, factor through the sub-type of U consisting of 2-element Univalence axiom, Higher inductive types. sets, US0 (see SectionII below). To illustrate how our approach matches traditional constructions, note that we I. INTRODUCTION get the real projective plane by attaching a 2-cell to Homotopy type theory emerged from the discovery the circle along the map of degree of 2. Geometrically, arXiv:1704.05770v1 [math.AT] 19 Apr 2017 of a homotopical interpretation of Martin-Löf’s identity this amounts to gluing a disk to Möbius strip along its types [1] and in particular from the construction of boundary, cf. Fig.1. the model in simplicial sets [6] and the proposal of In a companion article, we shall describe another con- the univalence axiom [13, 14]. We refer to the book on struction of both real and complex projective spaces as homotopy type theory for details [12]. homotopy quotients of (¥-)group actions (of the 2-element Homotopy type theory allows us to reason synthet- group O(1) and the circle group U(1), respectively). ically about the objects of algebraic topology (spaces, Our construction (like other constructions in homo- paths, homotopies, etc.) analogously to how the setting topy type theory) gives the homotopy types of real projec- of Euclidean geometry allows us to reason synthetically tive spaces, as opposed to more refined structure such about points, lines, circles, etc. (as opposed to analyti- as that of smooth manifolds or real algebraic varieties. cally in terms of elements and subsets of the Cartesian A benefit of having a construction in homotopy type plane R2). Already in [12] we find a portion of algebraic theory is that it applies in any model thereof, and not constructors inl : A ! A +C B inr : B ! A +C B and a path constructor glue : ∏(c:C) inl( f (c)) = inr(g(c)). Figure 1. Möbius strip. The real projective plane is obtained by gluing The elimination principle of A +C B provides a way of on a disk along the boundary. (TikZ code adapted from [5].) defining sections of type families P : A +C B ! Type (not necessarily small). If we have p : ∏ P(inl(a)) just in the standard one of infinity groupoids, ¥Gpd. A (a:A) For example, it is conjectured (and proved in many pB : ∏(b:B) P(inr(b)) cases) that Grothendieck ¥-toposes provide models. As as well as paths the real projective spaces are just certain colimits built P from the unit type, they sit in the discrete part of any pC : ∏(c:C) pA( f (c)) =glue(c) pB(g(c)), Grothendieck ¥-topos, i.e., in the inverse image of the f P(x) then we get a section : ∏(x:A+C B) . More- geometric morphism to ¥Gpd. In the settings of real- over, the section f we obtain this way satisfies the or smooth-cohesive homotopy type theory, they should computation rules f (inl(a)) ≡ pA(a) : P(inl(a)) and be the shapes of the incarnations of the real projective f (inr(b)) ≡ pB(b) : P(inr(b)). We also have a wit- spaces as topological or smooth manifolds, respectively, ness for propositional equality for map on paths, w : cf. the similar situation for the circle discussed in [10]. ∏(c:C) apd f (glue(c)) = pC(c) (we refer to the homotopy It is also expected that homotopy type theory can be P type theory book for details on dependent paths a =p b modeled in elementary ¥-toposes [11], which do not in and the map on paths operations ap f and apd f ). general admit a geometric morphism to ¥Gpd, and From pushouts, it is easy to derive also homotopy hence something like our construction would be needed coequalizers of parallel maps f , g : A ⇒ B for A, B : U. to access the homotopy types of the real projective spaces From these we get sequential colimits of diagrams in such models. f0 f1 f2 In the remainder of this introduction we describe in A0 A1 A2 ··· more detail the precise setting of homotopy type theory A N ! U f A ! A we are working in as well as the techniques we use. consisting of : and : ∏(n:N) n n+1. We also get the suspension ΣA of a type A as the We work in an intensional dependent type theory with pushout a univalent universe U containing the type of natural A 1 numbers, the unit type and the empty type, and we assume that U is closed under homotopy pushouts. S Furthermore, to use the universal property of pushouts 1 ΣA. N to map into arbitrary types regardless of their size, we n assume function extensionality for all dependent types. The spheres S are defined by recursion on n : N−1, (This is automatic if every type belongs to a univalent by iteratively suspending the (−1)-sphere, which is the universe, but we do not assume more than one universe.) empty type. Thus, for each n : N−1, the (n + 1)-sphere The types A : U are called small types. has a north pole and a south pole, and there is a n Let us briefly recall how homotopy pushouts are homotopy glue : S ! (N = S) which suspends the obtained as higher inductive types: if we are given n-sphere between the poles. In particular, the 0-sphere 0 A, B, C : U and f : C ! A and g : C ! B, then we S is a 2-element type. form the pushout of f and g The pushout of the product projections A × B ! A and A × B ! B gives the join A ∗ B. Lemma 8.5.10 in [12] Σ ' S0 ∗ Sn+1 ' g establishes that A A, so it follows that C B S0 ∗ Sn. f inr With pushouts, it is also possible to define for any type A : U its propositional truncation kAk, which is the A A + B inl C reflection of A into the type of mere propositions. This means we have a function j−j : A ! kAk, precompo- as the higher inductive type A +C B : U with point sition with which gives an equivalence (kAk ! B) ' 2 (A ! B) for any mere proposition B. There are several and let PX : X ! U and PY : Y ! U be type families that are constructions of the propositional truncation in terms of compatible in the sense that there is a fiberwise equivalence pushouts and colimits due to Van Doorn [3], Kraus [7], e : ∏(a:A) PX( f (a)) ' PY(g(a)).

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    8 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us