1 Elementary Set Theory

1 Elementary Set Theory

1 Elementary Set Theory Notation: fg enclose a set. f1; 2; 3g = f3; 2; 2; 1; 3g because a set is not defined by order or multiplicity. f0; 2; 4;:::g = fxjx is an even natural numberg because two ways of writing a set are equivalent. ; is the empty set. x 2 A denotes x is an element of A. N = f0; 1; 2;:::g are the natural numbers. Z = f:::; −2; −1; 0; 1; 2;:::g are the integers. m Q = f n jm; n 2 Z and n 6= 0g are the rational numbers. R are the real numbers. Axiom 1.1. Axiom of Extensionality Let A; B be sets. If (8x)x 2 A iff x 2 B then A = B. Definition 1.1 (Subset). Let A; B be sets. Then A is a subset of B, written A ⊆ B iff (8x) if x 2 A then x 2 B. Theorem 1.1. If A ⊆ B and B ⊆ A then A = B. Proof. Let x be arbitrary. Because A ⊆ B if x 2 A then x 2 B Because B ⊆ A if x 2 B then x 2 A Hence, x 2 A iff x 2 B, thus A = B. Definition 1.2 (Union). Let A; B be sets. The Union A [ B of A and B is defined by x 2 A [ B if x 2 A or x 2 B. Theorem 1.2. A [ (B [ C) = (A [ B) [ C Proof. Let x be arbitrary. x 2 A [ (B [ C) iff x 2 A or x 2 B [ C iff x 2 A or (x 2 B or x 2 C) iff x 2 A or x 2 B or x 2 C iff (x 2 A or x 2 B) or x 2 C iff x 2 A [ B or x 2 C iff x 2 (A [ B) [ C Definition 1.3 (Intersection). Let A; B be sets. The intersection A \ B of A and B is defined by a 2 A \ B iff x 2 A and x 2 B Theorem 1.3. A \ (B [ C) = (A \ B) [ (A \ C) Proof. Let x be arbitrary. Then x 2 A \ (B [ C) iff x 2 A and x 2 B \ C iff x 2 A and (x 2 B or x 2 C) iff (x 2 A and x 2 B) or (x 2 A and x 2 C) iff x 2 A \ B or x 2 A \ C iff x 2 (A \ B) [ (A \ C) 1 Definition 1.4 (Set Theoretic Difference). Let A; B be sets. The set theoretic difference A n B is defined by x 2 A n B iff x 2 A and x 62 B. Theorem 1.4. A n (B [ C) = (A n B) \ (A n C) Proof. Let x be arbitrary. Then x 2 A n (B [ C) iff x 2 A and x 62 B [ C iff x 2 A and not (x 2 B or x 2 C) iff x 2 A and (x 62 B and x 6 inC) iff x 2 A and x 62 B and x 6 inC iff x 2 A and x 62 B and x 2 A and x 6 inC iff x 2 (A n B) and x 2 (A n C) iff x 2 (A n B) \ (A n C) Provisional definition of function: Let A; B be sets. Then f is a function from A to B written f : A ! B if f assigns a unique element b 2 B to each a 2 A. But what is the meaning of "assign"? Basic idea is to consider f : R ! R defined by f(x) = x2. We shall identify f with its graph. To generalize this to arbitrary sets A and B we first need the concept of an ordered pair. IE, a mathematical object ha; bi satisfying ha; bi = hc; di iff a = c and b = d. In particular, h1; 2i= 6 f1; 2g. Definition 1.5 (Cartesian Product). If A; B are sets, then their Cartesian Product A × B = fha; bi ja 2 A; b 2 Bg Definition 1.6 (Function). f is a function from A to B iff f ⊆ A × B and for each a 2 A, there exists a unique b 2 B such that ha; bi 2 f. In this case, the unique value b is called the value of f at a, and we write f(a) = b. It only remains to define ha; bi in terms of set theory. Definition 1.7 (Ordered Pair). ha; bi = ffag; fa; bgg Theorem 1.5. ha; bi = hc; di iff a = c and b = d. Proof. Clearly if a = c and b = d then ha; bi = ffag; fa; bgg = ffcg; fc; dgg = hc; di 1. Suppose a = b. Then ffag; fa; bgg = ffag; fa; agg = ffag; fagg = ffagg Since ffagg = ffcg; fc; dgg we must have fag = fcg and fag = fc; dg. So a = c = d, in particular, a = c and b = d. 2. Suppose c = d. Then similarly a = b = c so a = c and b = d. 3. Suppose a 6= b and c 6= d. Since ffag; fa; bgg = ffcg; fc; dgg we must have fag = fcg or fag = fc; dg. The latter is clearly impossible, so a = c. Similarly, fa; bg = fc; dg or fa; bg = fcg. The latter is clearly impossible, and as a = c, then b = d. 2 NB (Note Bene) - It is almost never necessary in a mathematical proof to remember that a function is literally a set of ordered pairs. Definition 1.8 (Injection). The function f : A ! B is an injection iff (8a; a0 2 A) if a 6= a0 then f(a) 6= f(a0) Definition 1.9 (Surjection). The function f : A ! B is a surjection iff (8b 2 B)(9a 2 A) such that f(a) = b Definition 1.10 (Composition). If f : A ! B and g : B ! C are functions, then their composition g ◦ f : A ! C is dined by (g ◦ f)(x) = g(f(x)) Theorem 1.6. If f : A ! B and g : B ! C are surjections, then g ◦f : A ! C is also a surjection. Proof. Let c 2 C be arbitrary. Since g is surjective, 9b 2 B such that g(b) = c. Since f is surjective, 9a 2 A such that g(a) = b. Then, (g ◦ f)(a) = g(f(a)) = c, hence g ◦ f is a surjection. Definition 1.11 (Bijection). A function f : A ! B is a bijection if f is an injection and a surjection. Theorem 1.7. If f : A ! B and g : B ! C are bijections, then g ◦ f : A ! C is a bijection. Proof. Composition of surjections is a surjection, and compositions of injections are injections. Definition 1.12 (Inverse Function). If f : A ! B is a bijection, then its inverse, f −1 : B ! A is defined by f −1(b) = the unique a 2 A such that f(a) = b. Remarks - If f : A ! B is a bijection, it is easily checked that f −1 : B ! A is a bijection. In terms of ordered pairs, f −1 = fhb; ai : ha; bi 2 fg Definition 1.13 (Equinumerous). Two sets, A and B, are equinumerous, writ- ten A ∼ B iff there exists a bijection f : A ! B. Theorem 1.8 (Galileo). Let E = f0; 2; 4;:::g be the even natural numbers. Then, N ∼ E Proof. We can define a bijection f : N ! E by f(n) = 2n Remark 1.1. If is often extremely difficult to explicitly define a bijection f : N ! A. However, suppose that f : N ! A is a bijection. For each n 2 N let an be f(n). Then, a0; a1;::: is a list of the elements of A such that every element occurs exactly once, and conversely, if such a list exists, then we can define a bijection f : N ! A by f(n) = an 3 Theorem 1.9. N ∼ Z Proof. We can list the elements of Z: 0; 1; −1; 2; −2;::: Theorem 1.10. N ∼ Q Proof. We proceed in two steps. First, we prove that N ∼ Q+ = fq 2 Q : q > 0g and consider the following 1 2 3 1 ! 1 1 ! 2 2 3 infinite matrix 1 . 2 % 2 . 1 2 3 # 3 % 3 . 3 Proceed through the matrix along the indicated route adding rational num- bers to your list if they have not already occurred. Second, we declare that N ∼ Q. In the first part, we showed that there exists a bijection f : N ! Q+ hence we can list Q by 0; f(1); −f(1);:::. Definition 1.14 (Power Set). If A is any set, then its power set is P(A) = fB : B ⊆ Ag, so P(f1; 2; : : : ; ng)is of size 2n. Theorem 1.11 (Cantor). N 6∼ P(N) Proof. This method of proof is called the diagonal argument. We must show that there does not exist a bijection f : N ! P(N). Let f : N ! P(N) be any function. So, we shall prove that f is not a surjection. Hence, we must find a set S ⊆ N such that 8n 2 N f(n) 6= S. We do this via a "time and motion study" For each n 2 N we must make the nth decision. That is, if n 2 S. We perform the nth task, that is, ensure f(n) 6= S. We make the nth decision so that it accomplishes the nth task, ie, n 2 S iff n 62 f(n).

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    40 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us