Paul Gustafson Texas A&M University - Math 482 Instructor: Dr. David Larson Math 482 Final Paper: Cantor Spaces in R This paper describes some basic properties of Cantor subspaces of the real line. It also includes an application of these Cantor subspaces to a characterization of the countability of closed subsets of R in terms of some simple exterior measures. Recall that a perfect set is a set for which every point is a limit point. A set S is called totally disconnected if for every x; y 2 S, there exist disjoint open sets U; V ⊂ S such that x 2 U, y 2 V , and U [ V = S. Definition 1. A Cantor space is a non-empty, totally disconnected, perfect, compact metric space. Example 1. Let C0 := [0; 1], C1 := [0; 1=3] [ [2=3; 1], and C2 = [0; 1=9] [ [2=9; 1=3] [ [2=3; 7=9] [ [8=9; 1]. Similarly, for i > 2, let Ci be the closed set given by removing the open middle third of each interval of Ci−1. The ternary Cantor set 1 \ ∆ := Ci i=0 is a Cantor space. Proof. Since 0 2 Ci for all i, ∆ is non-empty. Since each interval in Ci is of length 3−i, ∆ is totally disconnected. It is closed and bounded, so compact by the Heine-Borel theorem. To see that ∆ is perfect, first note that the endpoints of any interval in any Ci remain endpoints of intervals in Ci+1, and Ci+1 ⊂ Ci. Hence, every point that is an endpoint of an interval in some Ci is in ∆. Now, fix x 2 ∆. Given > 0, there exists a Ci whose intervals are of length less than . Hence, both endpoints of the interval in Ci containing x are within of x, and are members of ∆. Thus, x is a limit point, so ∆ is perfect. Theorem 1. Let K be a Cantor space. If A ⊂ K is nonempty and clopen, then A is Cantor. Proof. A is compact since it is closed in K, and totally disconnected since it is open. To see that A is perfect, let x 2 A. Since K is perfect, there exists a sequence (xn) ⊂ K such that xn ! x. Since A is open, all but a finite number of xn lie in A. Theorem 2. If A ⊂ R is a Cantor space, then there is a order-preserving homeomorphism f : A ! f0; 1gN, where f0; 1gN is ordered lexicographically and Pn −n equipped with the product metric d(x; y) = i=1 jx(i) − y(i)j2 . 1 Proof. Step 1. Let a := inf(A), and d := sup(A) − a = diam(A). Since A is d 3d totally disconnected, there exists c 2 [a + 4 ; a + 4 ] n A. Then M0 := (−∞; c) \ A and M1 := (c; 1) \ A are clopen relative to A, hence Cantor spaces by 3 Theorem 1. Moreover, diam(Mi) ≤ 4 diam(A) for i = 0; 1. n−1 Step 2. For n > 1, apply Step 1 to Mt for each t 2 f0; 1g to get clopen 3 Cantor spaces Mt;0;Mt;1 ⊂ Mt with Mt;0 < Mt;1 and diam(Mt;i) ≤ 4 diam(Mt) n for i = 0; 1. By recursion on n, for all r; s 2 f0; 1g we have diam(Ms) ≤ 3 n diam(A), and if r < s in the lexicographical ordering then Mr < Ms, i.e. 4 S x 2 Mr; y 2 Ms implies x < y. Moreover, for any fixed n, A = s2f0;1gn Ms. Step 3. Fix x 2 A. The construction in Step 2 generates a descending sequence of sets (M ) n , each containing x. Since for all n we have tn tn2f0;1g tn+1 = tn; i for some i 2 f0; 1g, this sequence of sets determines a unique N element f(x) 2 f0; 1g such that, for any n, the first n entries of f(x) are tn. N To see that f is bijective, note that if t 2 f0; 1g and tn = (t(1); t(2); :::t(n)), −1 T1 then f (t) = n=1 Mtn contains exactly one point, since Mtn is a descending chain of compact sets with diameters going to 0. To see that f is continuous, let x 2 A. If xm ! x then, for every Mtn containing x, all but finitely many xm lie in Mtn since Mtn is open relative to −n A. Thus, f(xm) ! f(x) since diam(f(Mtn )) = 2 ! 0 as n ! 1. Since A is compact, the continuity of f implies f −1 is also continuous. To see that f is order-preserving, if x < y there exists n so large that x 2 Ms; y 2 Mt for s; t of length n with s 6= t. By Step 2, this implies s < t. Hence, f(x) < f(t). Theorem 3. If S ⊂ R is a Cantor space, there exists a nondecreasing, onto, continuous function g : S ! [0; 1]. N P1 −i Proof. Let h : f0; 1g ! [0; 1] be defined by h(x) = i=0 x(i)2 . Defining f as in Theorem 2, let g = h ◦ f. Thus, it suffices to show that h is nondecreasing, onto, and continuous. N P1 −i P1 Let x; y 2 f0; 1g . Then jh(x)−h(y)j = j i=0(x(i)−y(i))2 j ≤ i=0 jx(i)− y(i)j2−i = d(x; y), so h is continuous. If x < y, then there exists a min- imal n such that x(n) 6= y(n). By the definition of lexicographical order- P1 −i ing, x(n) = 0 and y(n) = 1. Thus, h(y) − h(x) = i=n(y(i) − x(i))2 = −n P1 −i −n P1 −i 2 + i=n+1(y(i) − x(i))2 ≥ 2 + i=n+1(−1)2 = 0. Hence, h is nonde- N creasing. To see that h is onto, let En := fx 2 f0; 1g : x(i) = 0 for all i > ng. −n+1 Then each h(En) is a 2 -net for [0; 1], so the image of h is dense in [0; 1]. Since S is compact, h(S) is compact, so h is onto. Lemma 1. If f :[a; b] ! [0; 1] is nondecreasing and onto, then f is continuous. Proof. Let c 2 (a; b]. Since f is nondecreasing, supx<c f(x) ≤ f(c) = infx≥c f(x). Hence, since f is onto, supx<c f(x) = f(c). To see that f(c−) = f(c), set > 0. By the definition of supremum, there exists a < c such f(c) − f(a) < . Then if a < x < c, since f is nondecreasing, f(c) − f(x) < . Hence, f(c−) = f(c). The proof for right continuity is analogous. 2 Lemma 2. Every compact metric space K can be written as K = A [ B, where A is perfect (hence compact), B is countable, and A \ B = ;. Proof. Let U be a countable base for K. Let V := fS 2 U : S is countableg, S and W := U n V . Then B := S2V S is countable and open. Let A := K n B. Then A is closed, hence compact. I claim that Wf := fS \ A : S 2 W g is a base for the topology of A. Suppose C ⊂ A is open in A, and x 2 C. Then C [B is open in K, so there exists S 2 U with x 2 S ⊂ (C [ B). Since x2 = B, S cannot be countable, so S 2 W . Hence, x 2 S \ A ⊂ C, so Wf is a base for A. Note that every element of W is uncountable, so, since B is countable, every element of Wf is also uncountable. Thus, A has no isolated points, so A is perfect. Definition 2. Given an nondecreasing function α : R ! R, the α-exterior measure of a set E ⊂ R is defined to be 1 1 ∗ X [ mα(E) := inff α(bi) − α(ai): E ⊂ (ai; bi)g i=1 i=1 ∗ Theorem 4. Let E ⊂ R be a closed set. Then E is countable iff mα(E) = 0 for all nondecreasing, continous α : R ! R. Proof. The forward implication is obvious. For the converse, suppose E were uncountable. If E contains a nontrivial interval, then let α be the identity. Since E contains an interval, it contains a compact set of the form [a; b] for a < b. Hence, any cover of E by open intervals must contain a finite subcover of [a; b]. The sum of the lengths of intervals in this subcover must be at least b − a, so ∗ mα(E) ≥ b − a > 0, a contradiction. Suppose E does not contain any nontrivial intervals. Note that E \[n; n+1] must be uncountable for some n, so WLOG, E is compact. Then, by Lemma 2, E = A [ B where A is a Cantor space and B is countable. Since A ⊂ E, ∗ ∗ ∗ mα(A) ≤ mα(E), so it suffices to show that mα(A) > 0. Let f : A ! [0; 1] be the increasing, onto, continuous function defined in Theorem 3. Define 0 : x ≤ inf(A) α(x) = supff(y): y 2 A \ (−∞; x)g : x > inf(A) Since A is closed and f is onto [0; 1], α is onto [0; 1]. Also, α is clearly non- decreasing. Since α is constant outside (inf(A); sup(A)), Lemma 1 implies α is continuous. Let U be a cover of A by open intervals. Since A is compact, there exists a n finite subcover F ⊂ U.
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages4 Page
-
File Size-