1 Justice as fairness, utilitarianism, and mixed conceptions David O. Brink It would be hard to overstate the philosophical significance of John Rawls’s TJ.1 It articulates and defends an egalitarian conception of liberalism and distributive justice that consists of two principles of justice: a principle of equal basic liberties and a principle that distributes social and economic goods and opportunities so as to be to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged. Rawls defends this liberal egalitarian conception of justice primarily as an alternative to utilitarianism.2 He situates his defense of this liberal egalitarian conception of justice within the social contract tradition by arguing that his principles of distributive justice would be preferred to utilitarianism and other Thanks to David Estlund, Tim Hinton, Theron Pummer, and Paul Weithman for comments on an earlier draft. I learned much of what I know about the appeal and resources of justice as fairness while I was at MIT in the late 1980s and early 1990s, especially from interactions with John Rawls, Tim Scanlon, Derek Parfit, and my (then) colleague Joshua Cohen. This essay develops ideas in lectures that I gave on justice as fairness during that period, which Tim Hinton attended and discussed with me. 1 Unless otherwise noted, all references to Rawls will be to TJ. The second edition (TJR) was published in 1999. Because the section numbering is the same in the two editions, I will refer to TJ using section numbers as much as possible. Rawls offers a restatement and reinterpret- ation of justice as fairness in JFR. Though JFR corrects TJ in places, its main point is to reinterpret justice as fairness as part of a specifically political conception of liberalism that aims to justify liberal essentials by identifying an overlapping consensus among different comprehensive religious, moral, and political commitments. This political reinterpretation of justice as fairness seems largely orthogonal to my main concern with the contractual argument for justice as fairness in TJ. I will take notice of JFR only insofar as it seems to bear directly on the reasoning within the contractual argument. 2 Rawls also defends justice as fairness against libertarian conceptions of justice. The libertarian conception gives moral significance, as justice as fairness does not, to the morally arbitrary effects of the natural and social lotteries – the distribution of natural talents and of social class and advantage (§§12–13). The argument against libertarian conceptions is an important part of the case for justice as fairness. Nonetheless, Rawls regards utilitarianism as the main rival to justice as fairness, both inside and outside the contractual argument, and the argument against libertarianism is largely a contract-independent argument. So in reconstructing and assessing Rawls’s contractual argument for justice as fairness, I will focus on the contrast with utilitar- ianism, largely ignoring his interesting and important discussion of libertarianism. Justice as Fairness 19 rivals by parties to a social contract in which they were represented fairly, that is, as free and equal moral persons. This explains why Rawls calls his conception justice as fairness and the importance of the hypothetical original position as a way of modeling a fair initial position from which principles of justice might be selected. Rawls thinks not only that justice as fairness would be preferred to utilitarianism in a fair social contract but also that it provides a better reconstruction than utilitarianism of our considered views about individual rights and justice. Though Rawls’s primary focus is on the justice of the basic structure of society, his critique of utilitarianism, his contractu- alist methodology, and his defense of equal basic rights have had much wider philosophical influence, extending to a variety of issues in ethical theory and normative ethics. In this way, the publication of TJ transformed and reinvigorated ethics as well as political philosophy. Any assessment of justice as fairness must address the adequacy of Rawls’s contractual argument for his two principles of justice and against utilitarian rivals. In this context it is worth noting that Rawls has two kinds of ambition. On the one hand, he has the substantial but comparatively modest ambition to defend a more egalitarian alternative to utilitarianism. He would succeed in this ambition insofar as parties in the original position would indeed prefer his two principles of justice to traditional utilitarian rivals. On the other hand, Rawls also has the more ambitious aim of showing his two principles of justice to be uniquely plausible, that is, to be superior to all reasonable alternatives. He would succeed in this ambition insofar as parties in the original position would prefer his two principles of justice to any plausible rival. Basically, the more ambitious claim consists in claiming that Rawls’s two principles are superior to a greater number of rivals. Of special interest here is the possibility of rivals to Rawls’s two principles that differ from traditional forms of utilitarianism (whether classical or average) but nonetheless combine elements of utilitarianism with elements of liberal egali- tarianism. Rawls calls these hybrids mixed conceptions (TJ, §21). So one question is whether Rawls’s contractual argument succeeds against mixed conceptions, as well as against traditional utilitarian conceptions. Of course, the more modest claim that justice as fairness is superior to traditional forms of utilitarianism is a very important claim, whether or not Rawls can support his stronger claim that justice as fairness is uniquely plausible among reasonable alternatives. Moreover, the more modest claim would be positively relevant to establishing the stronger claim. But it is worth noticing that Rawls might succeed in the more modest aim without succeeding in the more ambitious claim if there are other rivals that justice as fairness does not 20 David O. Brink defeat. Rawls himself distinguishes between these two ambitions in the second edition of TJ, where he reasserts both ambitions but expresses greater confidence in the more modest comparative claim than in the more ambitious one (TJR, p. xiv).3 It is worth distinguishing these modest and ambitious claims not just to display logical possibilities. In fact, Rawls’s ambitious claim turns out to be much harder to justify than the more modest one, and his main contractual arguments for justice as fairness fail to demonstrate that it is uniquely reasonable, whether or not they succeed against more traditional utilitarian rivals. In section 1.1 I will provide a brief reconstruction of the main elements of justice as fairness. In section 1.2 I will contrast Rawls’s general and special conceptions and ask whether something like the general conception isn’ta more plausible conception than the special conception, even when we restrict our attention to the circumstances that Rawls thinks justify adoption of the special conception. Then in section 1.3 I will reconstruct and assess Rawls’s specifically contractual arguments for his special conception of justice, focusing on the contrast between Rawls’s conception and traditional utilitar- ian principles. In section 1.4 I will focus on the adequacy of Rawls’s argument against a larger range of alternatives, including mixed and other conceptions. I will argue that even if Rawls can defend his more modest claim that justice as fairness is superior to traditional utilitarianism, his more ambitious claim that it is superior to mixed conceptions is problematic. 1.1 Justice as fairness: the two principles One of the most distinctive features of justice as fairness is that Rawls develops an egalitarian conception of social justice that he defends by appeal to a hypothetical social contract, which he claims fits within the social contract tradition of Locke, Rousseau, and Kant. The contractual argument represents the basic structure of society and its provision of liberties, oppor- tunities, and rights as just insofar as it satisfies principles that would be chosen in fair initial conditions in which contracting parties were represented as free and equal moral persons. It is essential to this sort of social contract that the contract be both hypothetical and moralized. The contractual argument 3 Similarly, in Part III of JFR Rawls distinguishes two “fundamental comparisons,” which correspond to the moderate and ambitious claims respectively. Though he still thinks that justice as fairness is superior to both unrestricted average utilitarianism and restricted average utilitarianism, he is more confident about the first comparison than the second. Justice as Fairness 21 requires Rawls to specify (a) fair initial contractual circumstances and (b) the principles that would be chosen in these circumstances. We might begin with a preliminary specification of the principles that Rawls thinks would be chosen in this hypothetical contract. We will discuss issues introduced by Rawls’s distinction between general and special concep- tions of justice later (section 1.2 below). But his primary focus is on the circumstances of justice faced by societies in conditions of moderate scarcity in which there is sufficient economic development and security to make possible a decent minimum standard of living for all (§26). For these condi- tions, Rawls defends what he calls the special conception of justice, which consists of two main principles (§§11, 46): 1 Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all [equal basic liberties]. 2 Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with the just savings principle, [the difference principle] and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity [fair equality of opportunity]. The currency of distributive justice for utilitarians is utility or well-being.
Details
-
File Typepdf
-
Upload Time-
-
Content LanguagesEnglish
-
Upload UserAnonymous/Not logged-in
-
File Pages21 Page
-
File Size-