The Banach–Tarski Paradox and Amenability Lecture 25: Thompson's Group F

The Banach–Tarski Paradox and Amenability Lecture 25: Thompson's Group F

The Banach{Tarski Paradox and Amenability Lecture 25: Thompson's Group F 30 October 2012 Thompson's groups F , T and V In 1965 Richard Thompson (a logician) defined 3 groups F ≤ T ≤ V Each is finitely presented and infinite, and Thompson used them to construct groups with unsolvable word problem. From the point of view of amenability F is the most important. The group F is not elementary amenable and does not have a subgroup which is free of rank ≥ 2. We do not know if F is amenable. The groups T and V are finitely presented infinite simple groups. The commutator subgroup [F ; F ] of F is finitely presented and ∼ 2 simple and F =[F ; F ] = Z . Definition of F We can define F to be the set of piecewise linear homeomorphisms f : [0; 1] ! [0; 1] which are differentiable except at finitely many a dyadic rationals (i.e. rationals 2n 2 (0; 1)), and such that on intervals of differentiability the derivatives are powers of 2. Examples See sketches of A and B. Lemma F is a subgroup of the group of all homeomorphisms [0; 1] ! [0; 1]. Proof. Let f 2 F have breakpoints 0 = x0 < x1 < ··· < xn = 1. Then f (x) = a1x on [0; x1] where a1 is a power of 2, so f (x1) = a1x1 is a dyadic rational. Hence f (x) = a2x + b2 on [x1; x2] where a2 is a power of 2 and b2 is dyadic rational. By induction f (x) = ai x + bi on [xi−1; xi ] with ai a power of 2 and bi a dyadic rational. It follows that f −1 2 F and that F is closed under composition. First properties of F Lemma F is nonabelian and torsion free. Proof. A does not commute with B. Consider a nontrivial f 2 F . Then there is a smallest dyadic rational x1 ≥ 0 such that f (x1) = x1 and on some interval [x1; x2], f is differentiable with slope not equal to 1. Consider powers of f on [x1; x2]. Lemma F has a subgroup isomorphic to F × F. Proof. Draw picture. Lemma F has a free abelian subgroup of rank 2, and a free abelian subgroup of infinite rank. Finite and infinite presentations for F Consider the finite presentation −1 −1 F = hx0; x1 j x1 x2x1 = x3; x1 x3x1 = x4i −1 −2 2 3 −3 where x2 = x0 x1x0, x3 = x0 x1x0 and x4 = x0 x1x0 and the infinite presentation −1 P = hxn; n ≥ 0 j xi xj xi = xj+1 if i < ji To see these presentations are equivalent, note that for all n > 1 −(n−1) (n−1) xn = x0 x1x0 so F is equivalent to F 0 defined by −1 −1 −(n−1) (n−1) hxn; n ≥ 0 j x1 x2x1 = x3; x1 x3x1 = x4; x0 x1x0 = xn8n > 1i Use induction to show that these relations imply −1 xi xj xi = xj+1 if i < j. Finite presentation for F Define a function φ from the group −1 −1 G = hx0; x1 j x1 x2x1 = x3; x1 x3x1 = x4i to F by φ(x0) = A, φ(x1) = B. Then φ is a group isomorphism. The proof uses a normal form for the elements of G and of F . Thus Thompson's group F has a finite presentation. In particular F is generated by A and B. Commutator subgroup of F Lemma 2 Let H be a 2-generator group and suppose ' : H ! Z is surjective. Then ker(') = [H; H]. We say an element f 2 F is trivial in neighbourhoods of 0 and 1 if f has slope 20 = 1 to the right of 0 and to the left of 1. Theorem [F ; F ] consists of all elements of F that are trivial in ∼ 2 neighbourhoods of 0 and 1. Also, F =[F ; F ] = Z . Proof. 2 a Define ' : F ! Z by '(f ) = (a; b) where f has slope 2 to the right of 0 and slope 2b to the left of 1. Then ' is a group homomorphism. The map ' is surjective since '(A) = (−1; 1) and '(B) = (0; 1). So by the Lemma, ker(') = [F ; F ]. Subgroups of F Theorem Every nonabelian subgroup of F contains a free abelian group of infinite rank. Corollary F does not contain a nonabelian free group of rank 2. Let H be a subgroup of F generated by elements f and g such that fg 6= gf . Let I1;:::; In be the closed intervals in [0; 1] with nonempty interiors s.t. 8 1 ≤ k ≤ n if x is an endpoint of Ik then f (x) = g(x) = x, and if x is an interior point of Ik then either f (x) 6= x or g(x) 6= x. We claim that for all k, the endpoints of Ik are cluster points of the H-orbit of every interior point of Ik . Let x be in the interior of Ik and let y be the greatest lower bound of the H-orbit of x. If y is not the left endpoint of Ik then wlog f (y) 6= y, so f (y) < y or f −1(y) < y. But then there is a neighbourhood of y such that the image of this neighbourhood under either f or f −1 is less than y, so the H-orbit of x contains points less than y, a contradiction. Thus y is the left endpoint of Ik . Similarly for least upper bounds. Subgroups of F Define the support of h 2 H to be the subset of [0; 1] on which h is not x 7! x. Similarly for the support of h 2 H in Ik . Let h1 = [f ; g] 2 [H; H]. Then h1 is trivial in neighbourhoods of the endpoints of I1. Then since the left endpoint of I1 is a cluster point of the H-orbit of any interior point of I1, there is an h 2 H −1 such that the support in I1 of h2 = hh1h is disjoint from the support of h in I1. So we can find an infinite sequence of functions h1; h2; h3;::: in H whose supports in I1 are mutually disjoint. So [hi ; hj ] is trivial on I1 for all i; j. If [hi ; hj ] 6= 1 then there is a k > 1 on which [hi ; hj ] is nontrivial. Repeat the argument for [hi ; hj ] on Ik . After finitely many repetitions we get an infinite sequence of functions in H which generate a free abelian subgroup. Elementary amenability Theorem Thompson's group F is not elementary amenable. We use results of Chou. Define EG0 to be the collection of all finite and abelian groups. For each ordinal α i.e. 0; 1; 2; : : : ; !; ! + 1;! + 2;:::;! + ! = ! · 2;! · 2 + 1;:::;!2;:::; 3 ! ! ;:::;! , . , if α is a successor define EGα to be the collection of amenable groups obtained from groups in EGα−1 by the following processes: I forming group extensions I taking directed unions and if α is a limit define [ EGα = EGβ β<α By a result of Chou, it suffices to show that F is not in EGα for any ordinal α. Thompson's group F is not elementary amenable We will use transfinite induction. Let P(α) be the statement that F is not in EGα. To prove P(α) for all ordinals α, it suffices to prove: I P(0) and I P(α) follows from [P(β) for all β < α] Now F 62 EG0 since F is infinite and nonabelian. Assume that α > 0 and that F 62 EGβ for each ordinal β < α. If α is a limit ordinal then by definition of EGα we are done. So suppose α is a successor and F 62 EGα−1. We want to show F cannot be constructed from groups in EGα−1 as a group extension or directed union. Thompson's group F is not elementary amenable The group F is not a directed union of groups in EGα−1, because F is finitely generated. To show F is not obtained as a group extension from groups in EGα−1 we will use the following theorem which is proved using normal forms: Theorem Every proper quotient of F is abelian. Suppose there is a short exact sequence 1 −! N −! F −! Q ! 1 with N; Q 2 EGα−1. Then N is nontrivial since F 62 EGα−1. So Q is a proper quotient. Hence by the theorem above, Q is abelian. Thus [F ; F ] ⊂ N. Since [F ; F ] consists of elements of F which are trivial in neighbourhoods of 0 and 1, we can find a copy of F in N. By a result of Chou, subgroups of groups in EGα−1 are in EGα−1, so F is in EGα−1, a contradiction..

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    12 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us