The Structure of Evolutionary Theory

The Structure of Evolutionary Theory

STEPHEN JAY GOULD The Structure Of Evolutionary Theory THE BELKNAP PR ES S OF HARVAR D UNIVERSITY PRESS CAMBRIDGE , MASSACHUSETTS AN D LONDO N , ENGLAND 2002 I ' 652 THE STRUCTURE OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY Species as Individuals in the Hie~archical Theory of Selection 653 trends within a clade. Change must therefore be concentrated in events of fitness different from life in another kind of deme, then selection includes a branching speciation, and trends must arise by the differential sorting of spe­ group effect from the deme level. (We invoke this formulation, for example, if cies with favored attributes. If new species generally arise in geological mo­ we argue for group selection by showing that organisms in a deme with altru­ 11 ments, as the theory of punctuated equilibrium holds, then trends owe their ists do better than identical organisms in a group lacking altruists.) I ~ explanation even more clearly to higher-level sorting among species-individu­ In the second approach, strongly favored here, we hold firm to the classi­ als acting as discrete entities with momentary births and stable durations in cal bare-bones Darwinian definition, but recognize that selection can work ; I geological time. on evolutionary individuals at many hierarchical levels. Selection has tradi­ I , Organismic selection may trump species selection in principle when both tionally been defined as the differential reproductive success of evolutionary processes operate at maximal efficiency, but if change associated with speci­ individuals based on the fitnesses of their traits in interaction with the en­ ation operates as "the only game in town," then a weak force prevails while a vironment. Thus, we recognize higher-level selection by the differential pro­ potentially stronger force lies dormant. N uclear bombs certainly make con­ liferation of some higher-level individuals (demes, species, clades) over oth­ ventional firearms look risible as instruments of war, but if we choose not to ers-just as we define conventional natural selection by the differential employ the nukes, then bullets can be devastatingly effective. The empirical reproductive success of some organisms based on phenotypic traits that con­ pattern of punctuated equilibrium therefore becomes the factual "weapon" fer fitness. that overcomes Fisher's strong theoretical objection to the efficacy of species These two approaches often yield concordant results for the obvious rea­ selection. son that differential proliferation of higher-level units (the second criterion) (This argument provides a second example for the importance of punctu­ often defines the group effect that influences the fitness of lower-level individ­ ated equilibrium in validating the independence of macroevolutionary theory uals chosen as a focus (the first criterion). But the two criteria need not corre­ 'i by failure of pure extrapolationism from microevolutionary dynamics. We spond, leading to situations where we would identify group se lection by one saw previously (pp. 604-608) that punctuated equilibrium strongly fosters criterion, but deny the same process by the other. For example, under the first the argument for species as evolutionary individuals capable of operating as criterion of group effects on lower-level fitness, some higher-level properties units of selection. We now note that punctuated equilibrium also affirms the of groups can influence lower units without causing any differential repro­ potential strength of species selection against a cogent theoretical claim for its duction of the groups themselves. On this criterion, for example, some biolo­ impotence.) gists have held that frequency dependent selection must be viewed, ipso facto, In summary, three of four classical arguments against higher-level se lection as an example of group selection- a claim simply incomprehensible under do not apply to species, while the fourth loses its force in a world dominated the alternative criterion of differential group proliferation. (The unresolved, by punctuated equilibrium. I see no barrier to the cardinal importance of spe­ and perhaps largely semantic, issue of whether kin selection should be inter­ cies selection in the history of life. preted as a form of group selection, or only an extension of conventional lower-level selection, also presupposes this criterion of group effect upon EMERGEN CE AND THE PROPER CRITERION lower-level fitness-see Wilson and Sober, 1994.) FOR SPECIES SELECTION A predominantly sociological issue has often set preferences between these criteria. Paleontologists, and other students of species selection, myself in­ Differential proliferation or downward effect? cluded, have strongly advocated the criterion of differential reproduction for This subject and its literature, as I have noted throughout the chapter, have higher-level individuals as a strict and obvious analog of ordinary natural se­ been plagued to an unusual degree by conceptual confusions and disputes lection as conventionally understood. Neontologists and students of group about basic definitions and terminology. As an important example, and as se lection have generally (though not always) preferred the criterion of "group many participants have noted (see especially Damuth and Heisler, 1988; and effect on gene or organismal fitness," both from fealty to Darwinian tradi­ Brandon, 1988, 1990), two quite different criteria for the definition of higher­ tions for using organisms as a primary focus, and because certain contentious level selection have circulated through the literature. (In most cases, they yield issues, especially the evolution of altruism, have generally been posed in the same conclusion, so this situation has not produced anarchy; but in a few organismal terms- "why can saintly Joe be so nice if he loses reproductive cases, some crucial, they may lead to different assertions, so the situation has success thereby?" fostered confusion.) Three major reasons lead to my strong preference for the criterion of differ­ In the first approach, one chooses a focal level of analysis (conventionally ential proliferation correlated with properties of relevant evolutionary indi­ one of the two lower levels of organism or gene), and then considers the effect viduals that confer fitness in interaction with their environment. First, we of membership in a higher-level group upon fitness values of the chosen thereby follow standard definitions of selection, which have always been lower-l evel unit. If, for an identical organism, life in one kind of deme yields a based on causal plurifaction, not on mere effect. Second, why would we ever 655 Species as Individuals in the Hierarchical Theory of Selection 654 THE STRUCTURE OF EVOLUTIONARY THEORY ense of strong psychological frustration must arise when you and your oppo~ prefer an elaborate and indirect definition-in terms of effects on something s to be saying the same thing, but in such utterly different ways, an else at a scale far removed from the causal interaction-over a simpler ac­ nents seem h. 1 t' ·st to such radically different effect. Thus, Dawkins presents is gene-s\~c ~o~~e count rooted in the direct result of the causal process itself? Considered reformulation of Wilson and Saber's Weltanschauung (mme as we ' y in these terms, the criterion of "group effect .on organismal fitness" seems downright peculiar. We only entertain such a standard for contingent reasons way): . R l' t s are judged by their of history and philosophical preference-the Darwinian tradition for focus­ Selection chooses only replicators . ep ica or b died to- ing on organisms, and our larger scientific allegiance to reductionism. Third henotypic effect. Phenotypic effects may happen to be un ' we can too easily lose the force and location of causality when we study ~ ~ether with the phenotypic effects of other replicators, m vehicles. Those phenomenon through indirect effects expressed elsewhere, rather than by im­ vehicles often turn out to be the objects that we recogmze as organ~s~s, mediate operation. True, we are supposed to assess the separate effects upon but this did not have to be so .... There did .not have to be any ve ices lower-level focal units-from deme membership, or species membership, for The environment of a replicator includes the outside world, at a 11 · · · · l' th genes m example. But since several higher levels may simultaneously affect a lower fo­ but it also includes, most importantly, other rep icators, o e~ . I ' cal unit, we may not be able to untangle the differences, and we may end up the same organism and in different organisms, and theu p enotypic with an account of consequences, rather than causes. products. As an obvious example of these pitfalls, I point out that gene-selectionism, · · previous summary- gene (Note that I did not exaggerate or cancature m my . cl h ' I with all its fallacies, arises from an erroneous inversion in the criterion of . d egard "clumping" into vehicles as beside the pomt, an t ey I 11! "group effect on lower-level fitness." One begins with the basic statement se 1ect10msts o r . · " · ment" do dissolve these vehicles-the true units of select10n-mto environ that membership in higher-level units affects the fitness of genes. So far, so good. But if one then makes the error of assuming that replicators, rather considered as the sum of contexts for any gene.) . I: I Wilson and Sober (1994, P· 641) responded to Dawkins with their own than interactors, should be units of selection-and then chooses genes as fun­ damental replicators both by general reductionistic preference, and by alle­ frustration: . f W uld not ask for a better giance to faithfulness in replication as a necessary criterion-then one be­ Dawkins remains so near, yet so ar . e co . f 1 . The question is are vehicles o se ec- comes tempted to misidentify effects as causes. The gene selectionist then summary of the gene-centere d view. ' l' d slides down the following slippery slope: why should I talk about higher-level tion absent from this account or have they merely been reco.ncerua ize interactors affecting gene fitness? why don't I just consider higher-level inter­ as environments of the genes.

View Full Text

Details

  • File Type
    pdf
  • Upload Time
    -
  • Content Languages
    English
  • Upload User
    Anonymous/Not logged-in
  • File Pages
    12 Page
  • File Size
    -

Download

Channel Download Status
Express Download Enable

Copyright

We respect the copyrights and intellectual property rights of all users. All uploaded documents are either original works of the uploader or authorized works of the rightful owners.

  • Not to be reproduced or distributed without explicit permission.
  • Not used for commercial purposes outside of approved use cases.
  • Not used to infringe on the rights of the original creators.
  • If you believe any content infringes your copyright, please contact us immediately.

Support

For help with questions, suggestions, or problems, please contact us