Addressing Anthropocentrism in Nonhuman Ethics: Evolution, Morality, and Nonhuman Moral Beings

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Addressing Anthropocentrism in Nonhuman Ethics: Evolution, Morality, and Nonhuman Moral Beings ADDRESSING ANTHROPOCENTRISM IN NONHUMAN ETHICS: EVOLUTION, MORALITY, AND NONHUMAN MORAL BEINGS By Andrew Woodhall A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Law University of Birmingham September 2016 University of Birmingham Research Archive e-theses repository This unpublished thesis/dissertation is copyright of the author and/or third parties. The intellectual property rights of the author or third parties in respect of this work are as defined by The Copyright Designs and Patents Act 1988 or as modified by any successor legislation. Any use made of information contained in this thesis/dissertation must be in accordance with that legislation and must be properly acknowledged. Further distribution or reproduction in any format is prohibited without the permission of the copyright holder. ABSTRACT In this thesis I put forward a new definition of anthropocentrism based on a thorough overview of use in the literature and via analogy with other centrisms, such as androcentrism. I argue that thus clarified anthropocentrism is unjustified and results in problems for nonhuman animals and that any nonhuman ethic should wish to avoid. I then demonstrate how important nonhuman ethics theories are anthropocentric on this definition, and do not address anthropocentrism, in a way that results in these problems for nonhumans. I therefore propose a nonhuman ethic that aims to be less anthropocentric. I do this by first considering morality in light of evolution and second by looking at nonhuman moral codes. I draw upon both of these to set out a less anthropocentric nonhuman ethic and show why this account is at least as viable as, and less problematic than, the current theories as well as outlining its beneficial implications for nonhuman animals and the field. I conclude that anthropocentrism and approaching nonhuman ethics in the manner I have is therefore important for considering nonhuman issues, and that the theory I have put forward is advantageous. For my mother and father, who have given so much for me. You are, and have always been, the wind beneath my wings. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to acknowledge and thank the following people and groups, without whom this work – and myself – would be but a shadow of what they have become: My deepest and most eternal gratitude to my lead supervisor Professor Lisa Bortolotti – whose confidence, interest, support, immense knowledge, and positivity have guided and enlightened me throughout the last four years. I cannot express the enormity of the impact you have had on myself, my work, and the development of this thesis. You are my inspiration. Professor Heather Widdows, my co-supervisor, who believed in me from day one, taught me more of how to be an academic than anyone, and whose patience, insight, knowledge, guidance, and instruction have been more than invaluable – they have been the foundation without which this thesis would have been impossible. All that I have achieved begins with you. The Arts and Humanities Research Council for funding support, without which I would never have been able to undertake a PhD. Gabriel Garmendia da Trindade, for all of the arguments we had that helped me refine my position and for being a Samwise Gamgee to my Frodo as I walked through this anthropocentric Mordor. All members of the Global Ethics reading group over the last four years, those at Minding Animals Conference 3, and all of those over the last three years of MANCEPT, your comments and feedback have been invaluable. Professor Gary Steiner and Dr Tony Milligan, for their continued support, advice, enthusiastic encouragement, and belief in me. Dr Herjeet Marway and Dr Lauren Traczykowski whose love, support, and encouragement has been a light, comfort, and perpetual strength. My family, for their never- ending love, support, and understanding. And most importantly, all of the nonhuman animals who lived around me, shared their lives and love with me, and reminded me of why I was working on this thesis: it was you who gave me the endurance and desire to fight through the hardest moments and do the best I could. Finally, anyone else my tequila-addled brain has embarrassingly forgotten - you know who you are, and with all of my heart I thank you. CONTENTS Introduction ............................................................................................................... p. 1 1. Clarifying Anthropocentrism .................................................................................. p. 8 1.1 Value Assumptions ....................................................................................... p. 8 1.2 Speciesism .................................................................................................... p. 12 1.3 Human Chauvinism....................................................................................... p. 17 1.4 Anthropocentrism ......................................................................................... p. 22 1.4.1 The Uses of Anthropocentrism ............................................................ p. 24 1.4.1.1 Use (a): Distinctions of Value ....................................................... p. 24 1.4.1.2 Use (b): Human Modus Operandi or Understanding ..................... p. 26 1.4.1.3 Anomalous Uses ........................................................................... p. 29 1.4.1.4 Use (c): Both Understanding and Value ........................................ p. 32 1.4.2 Anthropocentrism as a Centrism ......................................................... p. 33 1.4.2.1 The Relation of A(i) and A(ii) ...................................................... p. 38 1.4.3 Anthroparchy ...................................................................................... p. 40 1.5 Conclusion .................................................................................................... p. 42 2. Is Anthropocentrism Justified? ............................................................................... p. 44 2.1 The Origin of Anthropocentrism ................................................................... p. 45 2.2 Species Membership ..................................................................................... p. 52 2.3 Morally Relevant Characteristics................................................................... p. 57 2.4 The Necessity of Anthropocentrism for Ethics .............................................. p. 70 2.5 One Property Among Many .......................................................................... p. 77 2.6 Rejecting Anthropocentrism is Unnecessary.................................................. p. 80 2.7 Conclusion .................................................................................................... p. 83 3. The Problems of Anthropocentrism ........................................................................ p. 84 3.1 Problems of Anthropocentrism ...................................................................... p. 84 3.1.1 A Counterintuitive Problem ................................................................ p. 85 3.1.2 Anthropocentrism as a Centrism ......................................................... p. 87 3.1.3 The Relation of A(i) and A(ii) ............................................................. p. 93 3.1.4 Problems Caused by A(i) .................................................................... p. 94 3.1.5 The Aim of Nonhuman Ethics ............................................................. p. 102 3.1.6 Anthropocentrism in Nonhuman Ethic Debates ................................... p. 105 3.2 Conclusion .................................................................................................... p. 113 4. Nonhuman Ethics Theories: Singer & Regan .......................................................... p. 114 4.1 ‘Can They Suffer?’ ....................................................................................... p. 115 4.2 Nonhuman Animal Rights ............................................................................. p. 119 4.3 Anthropocentrism ......................................................................................... p. 124 4.3.1 Arguing From Humans ....................................................................... p. 125 4.3.1.1 Regan ........................................................................................... p. 128 4.3.1.2 Singer ........................................................................................... p. 133 4.3.2 The Hierarchy of Value ....................................................................... p. 136 4.3.2.1 Singer ........................................................................................... p. 136 4.3.2.2 Regan ........................................................................................... p. 142 4.4 Addressing Anthropocentrism ....................................................................... p. 145 4.5 Conclusion .................................................................................................... p. 147 5. Nonhuman Ethics Theories: ‘Non-Anthropocentric’ Positions ................................ p. 149 5.1 Environmental Ethics .................................................................................... p. 150 5.1.1 Deep Ecology ..................................................................................... p. 152 5.1.1.1 Anthropocentrism ........................................................................
Recommended publications
  • Are Illegal Direct Actions by Animal Rights Activists Ethically Vigilante?
    260 BETWEEN THE SPECIES Is the Radical Animal Rights Movement Ethically Vigilante? ABSTRACT Following contentious debates around the status and justifiability of illegal direct actions by animal rights activists, we introduce a here- tofore unexplored perspective that argues they are neither terrorist nor civilly disobedient but ethically vigilante. Radical animal rights movement (RARM) activists are vigilantes for vulnerable animals and their rights. Hence, draconian measures by the constitutional state against RARM vigilantes are both disproportionate and ille- gitimate. The state owes standing and toleration to such principled vigilantes, even though they are self-avowed anarchists and anti-stat- ists—unlike civil disobedients—repudiating allegiance to the con- stitutional order. This requires the state to acknowledge the ethical nature of challenges to its present regime of toleration, which assigns special standing to illegal actions in defense of human equality, but not equality and justice between humans and animals. Michael Allen East Tennessee State University Erica von Essen Environmental Communications Division Swedish University of Agricultural Sciences Volume 22, Issue 1 Fall 2018 http://digitalcommons.calpoly.edu/bts/ 261 Michael Allen and Erica von Essen Introduction We explore the normative status of illegal actions under- taken by the Radical Animal Rights Movement (RARM), such as animal rescue, trespass, and sabotage as well as confronta- tion and intimidation. RARM typically characterizes these ac- tions as examples of direct action rather than civil disobedience (Milligan 2015, Pellow 2014). Moreover, many RARM activ- ists position themselves as politically anarchist, anti-statist, and anti-capitalist (Best 2014, Pellow 2014). Indeed, the US and UK take these self-presentations at face value, responding to RARM by introducing increasingly draconian legislation that treats them as terrorists (Best 2014, McCausland, O’Sullivan and Brenton 2013, O’Sullivan 2011, Pellow 2014).
    [Show full text]
  • Climate Change Impacts on Free-Living Nonhuman Animals
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Redfame Publishing: E-Journals Studies in Media and Communication Vol. 7, No. 1; June 2019 ISSN: 2325-8071 E-ISSN: 2325-808X Published by Redfame Publishing URL: http://smc.redfame.com Climate Change Impacts on Free-Living Nonhuman Animals. Challenges for Media and Communication Ethics Núria Almiron1, Catia Faria2 1Department of Communication, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Roc Boronat, 138 08018 Barcelona, Spain 2Centro de Ética, Política e Sociedade, ILCH, Universidade do Minho, Campus de Gualtar, 4710-057 Braga, Portugal Correspondence: Núria Almiron, Department of Communication, Universitat Pompeu Fabra, Barcelona, Roc Boronat, 138 08018 Barcelona, Spain. Received: April 21, 2019 Accepted: May 21, 2019 Online Published: May 29, 2019 doi:10.11114/smc.v7i1.4305 URL: https://doi.org/10.11114/smc.v7i1.4305 Abstract The mainstream discussion regarding climate change in politics, public opinion and the media has focused almost exclusively on preventing the harms humans suffer due to global warming. Yet climate change is already having an impact on free-living nonhumans, which raises unexplored ethical concerns from a nondiscriminatory point of view. This paper discusses the inherent ethical challenge of climate change impacts on nonhuman animals living in nature and argues that the media and communication ethics cannot avoid addressing the issue. The paper further argues that media ethics needs to mirror animal ethics by rejecting moral anthropocentrism. Keywords: media ethics, egalitarianism, climate change, wildlife, anthropocentrism 1. Introduction Since evidence of climate change was brought to light by the first Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change in 1990, concerns regarding the issue have focused almost exclusively on preventing the harm humans suffer due to global warming.
    [Show full text]
  • CONCEPTUAL CHALLENGES in the CHARACTERISATION and EXPLANATION of PSYCHIATRIC PHENOMENA LISA BORTOLOTTI University of Birmingham LUCA MALATESTI University of Rijeka
    EuJAP | VOL. 6 | No. 1 | 2010 INTRODUCTION: CONCEPTUAL CHALLENGES IN THE CHARACTERISATION AND EXPLANATION OF PSYCHIATRIC PHENOMENA LISA BORTOLOTTI University of Birmingham LUCA MALATESTI University of Rijeka Historically, analytic philosophy has not been as close to psychiatry as the continental tradition. For instance, no analytic philosopher has produced a treatise as important and comprehensive as Karl Jaspers’s General Psychopathology (Jaspers 1963 [1913]), a work deeply infl uenced by phenomenology. Similarly, no analytic philosopher so far has critically engaged with the practice and history of psychiatry as Michel Foucault did in his Madness and Civilization (Foucault 1965 [1961]). As late as in the eight- ies Anthony Quinton, by referring to analytic thinkers, was justifi ed to claim that it was a “remarkable fact that philosophers, in a sense the experts on rationality, should have taken so little interest in irrationality” (1985). Although at that time some rel- evant research was done within the philosophy of science (see for instance, Boorse 1976 and Grünbaum 1984) and moral philosophy (see for instance, Margolis 1966 and Glover 1970), philosophy of psychiatry could not be considered a mainstream discipline. It is surely a fact that in recent years analytically oriented philosophers have acquired and sustained an interest for psychiatry. b is movement, that concerns prominently philosophy but has also had some impact on psychiatry and cognitive psychology, has been given a name, the “new philosophy of psychiatry” (Banner and b ornton 2007). Psychiatry, as other branches of medicine, involves a theoretical dimension concerned with the description, classifi cation and explanation of mental disorders and a practi- cal dimension of intervention and treatment.
    [Show full text]
  • The Affliction of Human Supremacy
    www.ecologicalcitizen.net LONG ARTICLE The affliction of human supremacy This article dissects the motivations behind and consequences of the worldview of Eileen Crist anthropocentrism, or human supremacy. Firstly, the author presents the just-so stories arising from the notion that the impact of humanity stems from our species’ essence. Instead, About the author the author argues, it is socio-cultural conditioning – specifically, the human-supremacist Eileen has been teaching credo propagated by the dominant culture – to which we must turn in order to properly at Virginia Tech in the understand humanity’s impact. Next, the typical beliefs arising from human supremacy Department of Science and are exposed, as are examples of its products: ideational and physical displacements. The Technology in Society since 1997. She has written and author also discusses the wisdom of limitations, the danger of shifting ecological baselines co-edited numerous papers and general ignorance of the current mass extinction event. Finally, after cautioning against and books, with her work the cult of techno-fixes, a brighter future is presented, which would be made possible by focusing on biodiversity rejecting the human-supremacist credo. loss and destruction of wild places, along with pathways to halt these trends. Eileen 2013 Economist article titled By contrast, the positive version of is a Consulting Editor to “Robochop: An Automated Jellyfish human nature as underlying driver of the Journal and lives in A Exterminator Takes to the Sea” planetary impact insists that we are after Blacksburg, VA, USA. reported a problem: innumerable jellyfish all special, perhaps even god-like. But so clogged the pipes of a Swedish nuclear far, this storyline continues, humans have Citation power plant, forcing it to shut down.
    [Show full text]
  • 2. Animal Ethics
    2. Animal ethics It was started to provide animal welfare and stop cruel practices on animals, for example factory farming, animal testing, using animals for experimentation or for entertainment. In the most of Western philosophy animals were considered as beings without moral standing, namely those that do not have to be included into our moral choices. The very typical example of this approach is the Cartesian one, according to Rene Descartes (1596-1650), animals are just simple machines that cannot experience pain. The philosopher was known for making vivisections on living animals and claiming that none of the animals could feel the pain during this. In consequence of this approach until modern times there were conducted many unnecessary and cruel experiments with animal usage, also animal’s condition at factory farms or in entrainment were terrible. All these practices caused a huge amount of suffering of animals. The approach to animals was changed with Peter Singer’s influential book on Animal Liberation (1975). Singer raised the issue that animals can suffer and amount of suffering that they experience is not worth what we gain from these cruel practices. His argumentation was utilitarian, which is one of the approaches of normative ethics. Deontological and utilitarian argumentation in animal ethics Normative ethics aims at providing moral standards that regulate right and wrong conduct. This may involve articulating the good habits that we should acquire, the duties that we should follow, or the consequences of our behavior on others. The most popular approaches to normative theory are: deonotology and conseqentialism. The word deontology derives from the Greek words for duty (deon) and science (or study) of (logos).
    [Show full text]
  • Neoliberalism and Justice in Education for Sustainable Development: a Call for Inclusive Pluralism
    Environmental Education Research ISSN: 1350-4622 (Print) 1469-5871 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/ceer20 Neoliberalism and justice in education for sustainable development: a call for inclusive pluralism Helen Kopnina & Brett Cherniak To cite this article: Helen Kopnina & Brett Cherniak (2016) Neoliberalism and justice in education for sustainable development: a call for inclusive pluralism, Environmental Education Research, 22:6, 827-841, DOI: 10.1080/13504622.2016.1149550 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/13504622.2016.1149550 © 2016 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group Published online: 15 Mar 2016. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 938 View related articles View Crossmark data Citing articles: 3 View citing articles Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=ceer20 Environmental Education Research, 2016 Vol. 22, No. 6, 827–841, http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13504622.2016.1149550 Neoliberalism and justice in education for sustainable development: a call for inclusive pluralism Helen Kopninaa* and Brett Cherniakb aFaculty Social and Behavioural Sciences, Institute Cultural Anthropology and Development Sociology, Leiden University, Leiden, The Netherlands; bIndependent Researcher, Ontario, Canada (Received 5 March 2015; accepted 24 January 2016) Commonly conceived, sustainable development is concerned with social and economic equity and maintenance of ecological stability for future generations. The Brundtland Report addresses the ethical principles of intragenerational and intergenerational equity as fundamental pillars of sustainable development. This equity is often defined in economic terms, involving fair distribution of natural resources, and in practice dependent on the workings of a neoliberal market economy.
    [Show full text]
  • Environmental Ethics Anthropocentrism
    Environmental Ethics Anthropocentrism Introduction Anthropcentrism is the world view that places human beings as the center of the cosmos Five Interconnected Themes: 1) natural order has a grand hierarchy (a “Great Chain of Being) 2) the ontological divide between human and nonhuman nature 3) nature as a machine 4) only humans beings have intrinsic value/nature has only instrumental value 5) the moral community is limited to human beings Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) The Summa Contra Gentiles develops the ethical implications of the Great Chain of Being humans are closest to the likeness of God rational creatures exercise free will God bestows intrinsic value on rational creatures “Accordingly intellectual creatures are ruled by God, as though He cared for them for their own sake, while other creatures are ruled as being directed to rational creatures” (63) other creatures are slaves to their environment their actions casually determined by the environment thus human beings alone are morally considerable only human beings have freedom “he is free who is cause of himself . intellectual nature alone is free” human beings have the right to subjugate other beings below on the hierarchy “Hereby is refuted the error of those who said it is sinful for man to kill dumb animals: for by divine providence they are intended for man’s use in the natural order” (64) anticipating Kant, the only danger in killing dumb animals is that such behavior might lead to cruelty to human beings Francis Bacon (1561-1626) The Great Instauration focus of knowledge should be practical the improvement of the human condition knowledge is power over nature “the roads to human power and to human knowledge lie close together, and are nearly the same” this view of knowledge as power is stated more clearly in New Organon (1620) Title refers to Aristotle’s logical and methodological works known collectively as the Organon this will be a new organon, thus a new scientific method “Human knowledge and human power meet in one; for where the cause is not known the effect cannot be produced.
    [Show full text]
  • The Scope of the Argument from Species Overlap
    bs_bs_banner Journal of Applied Philosophy,Vol.31, No. 2, 2014 doi: 10.1111/japp.12051 The Scope of the Argument from Species Overlap OSCAR HORTA ABSTRACT The argument from species overlap has been widely used in the literature on animal ethics and speciesism. However, there has been much confusion regarding what the argument proves and what it does not prove, and regarding the views it challenges.This article intends to clarify these confusions, and to show that the name most often used for this argument (‘the argument from marginal cases’) reflects and reinforces these misunderstandings.The article claims that the argument questions not only those defences of anthropocentrism that appeal to capacities believed to be typically human, but also those that appeal to special relations between humans. This means the scope of the argument is far wider than has been thought thus far. Finally, the article claims that, even if the argument cannot prove by itself that we should not disregard the interests of nonhuman animals, it provides us with strong reasons to do so, since the argument does prove that no defence of anthropocentrism appealing to non-definitional and testable criteria succeeds. 1. Introduction The argument from species overlap, which has also been called — misleadingly, I will argue — the argument from marginal cases, points out that the criteria that are com- monly used to deprive nonhuman animals of moral consideration fail to draw a line between human beings and other sentient animals, since there are also humans who fail to satisfy them.1 This argument has been widely used in the literature on animal ethics for two purposes.
    [Show full text]
  • Animals Liberation Philosophy and Policy Journal Volume 5, Issue 1
    AAnniimmaallss LLiibbeerraattiioonn PPhhiilloossoopphhyy aanndd PPoolliiccyy JJoouurrnnaall VVoolluummee 55,, IIssssuuee 11 -- 22000077 Animal Liberation Philosophy and Policy Journal Volume 5, Issue 1 2007 Edited By: Steven Best, Chief Editor ____________________________________________________________ TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction Steven Best, Chief Editor Pg. 2-3 Introducing Critical Animal Studies Steven Best, Anthony J. Nocella II, Richard Kahn, Carol Gigliotti, and Lisa Kemmerer Pg. 4-5 Extrinsic and Intrinsic Arguments: Strategies for Promoting Animal Rights Katherine Perlo Pg. 6-19 Animal Rights Law: Fundamentalism versus Pragmatism David Sztybel Pg. 20-54 Unmasking the Animal Liberation Front Using Critical Pedagogy: Seeing the ALF for Who They Really Are Anthony J. Nocella II Pg. 55-64 The Animal Enterprise Terrorism Act: New, Improved, and ACLU-Approved Steven Best Pg. 65-81 BOOK REVIEWS _________________ In Defense of Animals: The Second Wave, by Peter Singer ed. (2005) Reviewed by Matthew Calarco Pg. 82-87 Dominion: The Power of Man, the Suffering of Animals, and the Call to Mercy, by Matthew Scully (2003) Reviewed by Lisa Kemmerer Pg. 88-91 Terrorists or Freedom Fighters?: Reflections on the Liberation of Animals, by Steven Best and Anthony J. Nocella, II, eds. (2004) Reviewed by Lauren E. Eastwood Pg. 92 Introduction Welcome to the sixth issue of our journal. You’ll first notice that our journal and site has undergone a name change. The Center on Animal Liberation Affairs is now the Institute for Critical Animal Studies, and the Animal Liberation Philosophy and Policy Journal is now the Journal for Critical Animal Studies. The name changes, decided through discussion among our board members, were prompted by both philosophical and pragmatic motivations.
    [Show full text]
  • A Fight for Life by Maria Sztybel
    A Fight for Life by Maria Sztybel ~ excerpts from a Holocaust memoir ~ Compiled by Dr. David Sztybel, Jr. with kind permission from translator, Lola Drach 1. Background In 2006, my article – “Can the Treatment of Nonhuman Animals Be Compared to the Holocaust?” – was published in the peer-reviewed journal, Ethics and the Environment. Later, based on extending that research, I created the Holocaust Comparison Project at davidsztybel.info/16.html. Maria Sztybel – who changed her name to “Maria Rok” after marrying – is my aunt, now long deceased. Maria was the eldest of my father’s siblings, all children of David Sztybel, Senior. Many individuals object to comparing the treatment of nonhuman animals to the Holocaust partly because it is put forward by non-Jews, non- Holocaust-survivors, or people who do not take seriously the egregious death and suffering that occurred during this historical phenomenon. This compilation belies these logically off-base attempts to discredit the comparison. I, David Sztybel, Jr., consider myself to be an indirect Holocaust survivor. After all, first and most obviously, the Nazi death-mechanisms of deportation to killing camps – and associated horrors – very nearly consumed my grandparents’ whole family, but for a rather strange historical contingency that I will detail below. Second, there were also threats from a near-pogrom (or massacre of Jews – recounted below). Third, there was the Nazi military invasion of Poland. The latter killed many of my father’s fellow townspeople. And fourth and fifth, more particularly, my father, Bernard Sztybel, almost died during this period, as narrated in two childhood incidents documented below.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Birmingham Philosophy Bias
    University of Birmingham Philosophy bias and stigma Bortolotti, Lisa; Puddifoot, Kathy DOI: 10.1515/9783110650990-007 License: Creative Commons: Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Citation for published version (Harvard): Bortolotti, L & Puddifoot, K 2019, Philosophy bias and stigma. in D Bubbio & J Malpas (eds), Why Philosophy?. De Gruyter, pp. 51-64. https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110650990-007 Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal General rights Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes permitted by law. •Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication. •Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial research. •User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?) •Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain. Where a licence is displayed above, please note the terms and conditions of the licence govern your use of this document. When citing, please reference the published version. Take down policy While the University of Birmingham exercises care and attention in making items available there are rare occasions when an item has been uploaded in error or has been deemed to be commercially or otherwise sensitive.
    [Show full text]
  • Living with Animals Conference Co-Organized by Robert W. Mitchell, Radhika N
    Living with Animals Conference Co-organized by Robert W. Mitchell, Radhika N. Makecha, & Michał Piotr Pręgowski Eastern Kentucky University, 19-21 March 2015 Cover design: Kasey L. Morris Conference overview Each day begins with a keynote speaker, and follows with two tracks (in separate locations) that will run concurrently. Breakfast foods and coffee/tea/water will be available prior to the morning keynotes. Coffee breaks (i.e., snacks and coffee/tea/water) are scheduled between sequential groups of talks. Thus, for example, if one session is from 9:05-10:15, and the next session is 10:40-11:40, there is a coffee break from 10:15-10:40. Drinks and edibles should be visible at or near the entry to the rooms where talks are held. Book display: Throughout the conference in Library Room 201, there is a book display. Several university presses have generously provided books for your perusal (as well as order sheets), and some conference participants will be displaying their books as well. Thursday features the “Living with Horses” sessions, as well as concurrent sessions, and has an optional (pre-paid) trip to Berea for shopping and dinner at the Historic Boone Tavern Restaurant. Friday features the “Teaching with Animals” sessions throughout the morning and early afternoon (which includes a boxed lunch during panel discussions and a movie showing and discussion); “Living with Animals” sessions continuing in the late afternoon, and a Conference Dinner at Masala Indian restaurant. Saturday includes “Living with Animals” sessions throughout the day and Poster Presentations during a buffet lunch. In addition, there is the optional trip to the White Hall State Historic Site (you pay when you arrive at the site).
    [Show full text]