Combinatory Logic and Lambda Calculus with Classical Types

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Combinatory Logic and Lambda Calculus with Classical Types Lagique A n a ly s e 137-138 (1992), 69-79 COMBINATORY LOGIC AND LAMBDA CALCULUS WITH CLASSICAL TYPES M.W. BUNDER Type Assignment in Lambda Calculus The primitive terms of lambda calculus are variables x, y, a n d possibly some constants. Other X-terms are formed by application (if X and Y are X-terms then poo is a X-term) and lambda abstraction (If X is a X-term and x a variable then (Xx.X) is a X-term). (XY) can be interpreted as the value of the function X at Y and (Xx.X) as the function whose value at x is X. There is an equality relation between X-terms which satisfies the following axiom (amongst others): (j3) ( Xx .M) N [N /x ]M( ') . Most X-terms can be assigned an associated "type". The intention is that the type tells us what kind of term we have. We will describe types and the rules for assigning them to X-terms. Types are constructed from a class of type variables and/or certain type constants using the binary operation ->. X: oQ/-* ge3 will be read "If U E oWthen (XU) E 93" Given an arbitrary assignment of types to the free variables (and constants) the types of compound X-terms are usually assigned by the following rules:( 2 ). [Nix1M is the result of substituting N for the free occurrences of x in M. For details of the definition and the full axioms and rules for equality see Hindley and Seldin [6]. ( 2 ) F o r f u l l d e t a i l s s e e H i n d l e y a n d S e l d i n [ 6 1 . 70 M W . B U N D E(X) R X : C , f2t g3 (Xx. Y): c),2"-• X:cs4T Y : (pm' (XY): Here is a formal definition of a type of a X-term and also of the principal type scheme of a X-term. Definition of Type and Principal Type Scheme (p.t.s.) If X: oWcan be derived by a n d -4., in a deduction that has no uncancelled hypotheses then X is said to have type mt. Every X-term that has a type has what is called a principal type scheme (p.t.s.) built up from type variables and A l l other types of a X-term X will be substitution instances of the p.t.s. Note that some X-terms such as (Xx.Xy.xyy)(Xz.z) have no types assigned by the rules. 1)1pe Assignment in Combinatory Logic The primitive terms of a combinatory logic are a finite set of operators called combinators. Other combinators are formed by application. Each combinator has associated with it an axiom; for example: KXY = X SXYZ = XZ(YZ) = X These combinators correspond to the following X-terms: K to Xx.Xy.x, S to Xx.Xy.Xz.xz(yz) and Ito kx.x. Given this identification and the type assignment rules of the lambda COMBINATORY LOGIC AND X CALCULUS WITH CLASSICAL TYPES 7 1 calculus we can derive the following p.t.s.s K : a ( b a ) and S : (a ( b c ) ) -0 ((a b ) ( a c ) ) . In this paper we will take these assignments of p.t.s.s to K and S as axioms and not use, directly, any of their substitution instances. To compen- sate for this we replace b y the following rule: Condensed Detachment (D) If X: nand Y: 913 and a, and 0 0 2 a r e t h e t'hes muaxbimsal ntumi bt eur otf di isotinnct type variables, then (XY) : W 1(Tshis, formulation is a somewhat more consice one than that in Hindley and (Moeredith [61f .) 0 tThe tyhpe assoignmenst axioms for K and S and rule (D) lead exactly to the p.t.s.s of combinators. In the same way p.t.s.s. of X-terms can be generated 5 e using a n d a generalised version of (D), provided that all hypotheses are i4nfitially of othe form x:a.r ) w h i = c h Faormulas as Types 2 A( special case of (D), where v, and v 2Tby :a r e i d e n t i t y s) u b s t i t u t i o n s X : c0--• : (JO ,W i s gh i v e n (XY) : a swh ich, ignoring the terms, looks like modus ponens if i s read as implica- tion and osiand g3 are formulas rather than types. t As the types for K and S are exactly the usual axioms for intuitionistic h logic and (D) encorporates some substitution and modus ponens it is not e surprising (for details see Hindley and Meredith [51) that the types are el xactly the theorems of implicational intuitionistic propositional logic. e a s t n u m b e r o f - 1 . s , f o r w h i c h a 1 ( 0 V ) h a s 72 M.W. BUNDER Classical Theorems as Types The aim of this paper is to extend the type theory and if necessary the combinatory logic or lambda calculus in such a way that the type theory becomes a full classical propositional logic rather than just an intuitionistic implicational one. The extension to classical logic can be achieved most simply by adding a constant proposition f and an axiom: ((a -4 , 0 The usual logical connectives- c-an then be defined by: o — aQt= f f pszt v = — ) and p!:2/ A Y6 — (ovt-÷ — - o We will assign a "new" combinator or X-term U the above type as p.t.s. i.e. a . : ((a -o 0 t ) -0 a The constant f seen in type terms, will be an empty type. What U does as a combinator will be investigated later. First we will look at certain classical theorems and their corresponding (extended) combinators. We will use some further combinators (definable using S and K) and their types (derivable from those for S and K): D( = X I = SKK BXYZ = X(YZ) where B = S(KS)K CXYZ = XZY C = S(BBS)(KK) WXY = XYY W CSI I : a -o a B : (a -0 b) ( ( c -0 a) -o (c -o b)) C : (a -o (b -o c)) -o (b -o (a -* c)) W : (a -o (a b ) ) -o (a -o b). COMBINATORY LOGIC AND X CALCULUS WITH CLASSICAL TYPES 7 3 Using (D) we obtain successively: BU: (c ( ( a -» 0 -• 0) ( c -• a) BUK : a Thus the p.t.s. of BUK is the well known theorem that false implies all propositions. Note also that BUK gives us exactly the proof of f -• a using the axioms or theorems B, U, and K and rule (D). The classical theorem a A b -• a can be written as ((a -* (t) 0 ) - b 0 - Its proof given by BU(CbB( BKa)) ca.n be written out as follows using (D). B: (a -0b) -• ((e -•a) -• (c -•b)) K; e -0 (d -•e) BK: (c -oe) -• (c -• (d -•e)) C: (g -•(h - • (h -.(g CB: (e -•a) -• ((a -0b) -• (c -•b)) CB(BK): ((c -• (d -0e)) -• b) ( ( c -•e) b ) U: (0 - BU: b(k 0- BU(CB(BK)): (-b(c ( d -00) -0 - • c *( The following are0 the r esults of the substitutions induced by the use of (D) in the above proof. - b k = (c -•(d -•e)) b , p j = c,I e - b b Thetheorem of cl0assical implicational logic (Peirce's law) which reduces intuitionistic logic to) cla ssical logic corresponds to the following combinator: ( BUMBS(CB)11B(BUK)])k : ((a b ) -• a) -• a 74 M.W. BUNDER Proof Transformations Combinators (or equivalently X-terms) do not only give a precise representa- tion of a proof, they also allow a proof to be transformed easily into one where the more basic axioms (of some weaker system) are used first and ones needed to extend the system to a stronger one as late as possible. We will treat the p.t.s.s of I, B, C, K and W as potential axioms for these weaker systems. The proof of a A b —> a can be rewritten as follows using the properties of B and C: BLI(CB(BK)) = CB(CB(B10)U = CB(B(CB)BK)U = B(CB)(B(CB)B)KU. As the equations for B and C preserve type (see Curry and Feys [3]) the combinator B(CB)(B(CB)B)KU also represents a proof of a A b a . Its initial part B(CB)(B(CB)B) represents the proof of a theorem in the very weak logic based on the p.t.s.s of B and C and Rule (D) and the proof is comple- ted by just two applications of (D) with respectively the types of K and U as minor premises. Note that as W is not used this is a theorem of a "classical BCK logic". We can summarise results of this kind in the following theorem. Theorem 1 Any proof in a (sub-) classical logic having at least B and C as theorems can be reorganised to the form: ZI IK KW WU -(1) where Z is a BC combinator and each of I, K, W and U will appear zero or more times. Proof A proof can be represented by a combinator involving zero or more of B, C, K, I, W and U.
Recommended publications
  • The Lambda Calculus Is Algebraic
    Under consideration for publication in J. Functional Programming 1 2 P. Selinger point of view. We suggest another way of looking at the problem, which yields a sense in which the lambda calculus is equivalent to an algebraic theory. The Lambda Calculus is Algebraic The basic observation is that the failure of the ξ-rule is not a deficiency of the lambda calculus itself, nor of combinatory algebras, but rather it is an artifact of the way free variables are interpreted in a model. Under the usual interpretation, free variables are in- PETER SELINGER terpreted as elements of a lambda algebra A. Thus, an equation M = N between terms Department of Mathematics and Statistics University of Ottawa, Ottawa, Ontario K1N 6N5, Canada is said to be satisfied if it holds whenever the free variables of M and N are replaced by (e-mail: [email protected]) elements of A. We call this the local interpretation. We suggest a different interpretation, called the absolute interpretation, under which free variables are interpreted as indetermi- nates. Let A[x1 ...xn] be the lambda algebra obtained from A by freely adjoining elements Abstract x1 ...xn. Under the absolute interpretation, an equation M = N is said to be satisfied if it holds in A[x1 ...xn]. This paper serves as a self-contained, tutorial introduction to combinatory models of the untyped The fundamental observationof this paper is that the two interpretations do not coincide, lambda calculus. We focus particularly on the interpretation of free variables. We argue that free and that the absolute interpretation satisfies all rules of the lambda calculus, including the variables should not be interpreted as elements in a model, as is usually done, but as indeterminates.
    [Show full text]
  • Deriving Logical Relations from Interpretations of Predicate Logic
    Replace this file with prentcsmacro.sty for your meeting, or with entcsmacro.sty for your meeting. Both can be found through links on the ENTCS Web Page. Deriving Logical Relations from Interpretations of Predicate Logic Claudio Hermida1 Uday S. Reddy2 University of Birmingham Edmund P. Robinson3;4 Queen Mary, University of London Abstract This paper extends the results of Hermida's thesis about logical predicates to more general logical relations and a wider collection of types. The extension of type constructors from types to logical relations is derived from an interpretation of those constructors on a model of predicate logic. This is then further extended to n-ary relations by pullback. Hermida's theory shows how right adjoints in the category of fibrations are composed from a combination of Cartesian lifting and a local adjunction. This result is generalised to make it more applicable to left adjoints, and then shown to be stable under pullback, deriving an account of n-ary relations from standard predicate logic. A brief discussion of lifting monads to predicates includes the existence of an initial such lifting, generalising existing results. Keywords: logical relations, fibrations, categorical type theory, monadic types 1 Introduction The purpose of this paper is to illustrate a link between logical relations and predicate logics. We begin by revisiting the conditions under which the predicates in a predicate logic for reasoning about a type theory can be shown to carry the structure of that type theory. We then show that similar structure on binary and more generally n-ary relations can be derived from that on unary predicates.
    [Show full text]
  • The Proper Treatment of Variables in Predicate Logic
    The Proper Treatment of Variables in Predicate Logic Kai F. Wehmeier University of California, Irvine Abstract Bertrand Russell (1903, x93) observed that “the variable is a very complicated logi- cal entity, by no means easy to analyze correctly”. This assessment is borne out by the fact that even now we have no fully satisfactory understanding of the role of variables in a compositional semantics for first-order logic. In standard Tarskian semantics, variables are treated as meaning-bearing entities; moreover, they serve as the basic building blocks of all meanings, which are constructed out of variable assignments. But this has disquieting consequences, including Fine’s antinomy of the variable and an undue dependence of meanings on language (representation- alism). Here I develop an alternative, Fregean version of predicate logic that uses the traditional quantifier–variable apparatus for the expression of generality, pos- sesses a fully compositional, non-representational semantics, and is not subject to the antinomy of the variable. The advantages of Fregean over Tarskian predicate logic are due to the former’s treating variables not as meaningful lexical items, but as mere marks of punctuation, similar to parentheses. I submit that this is indeed how the variables of predicate logic should be construed. 1 1 Introduction In standard, Tarski-style syntax for first-order logic, atomic formulas are constructed from predicate symbols and an appropriate number of variables and names. Truth- functional connectives can be used to form new formulas out of ones already con- structed. From any formula already constructed, and any individual variable, a new formula can be obtained by first writing a quantifier symbol, appending the chosen variable, and then appending the original formula.
    [Show full text]
  • Exceptionally Monadic Error Handling
    Exceptionally Monadic Error Handling Looking at bind and squinting really hard Jan Malakhovski∗ IRIT, University of Toulouse-3 and ITMO University February 2014 - October 2018 Abstract We notice that the type of catch :: c a -> (e -> c a) -> c a operator is a special case of monadic bind operator (>>=) :: m a -> (a -> m b) -> m b, the semantics (surprisingly) matches, and this observation has many interesting consequences. For instance, the reader is probably aware that the monadic essence of the (>>=) operator of the error monad λA.E ∨ A is to behave like identity monad for "normal" values and to stop on "errors". The unappreciated fact is that handling of said "errors" with a catch operator of the "flipped" "conjoined" error monad λE.E ∨ A is, too, a monadic computation that treats still unhandled "errors" as "normal" values and stops when an "error" is finally handled. We show that for an appropriately indexed type of computations such a "conjoined" struc- ture naturally follows from the conventional operational semantics of throw and catch operators. Consequently, we show that this structure uniformly generalizes all conventional monadic error handling mechanisms we are aware of. We also demonstrate several more interesting instances of this structure of which at least bi-indexed monadic parser combinators and conventional exceptions implemented via continuations have immediate practical applications. Finally, we notice that these observations provide surprising perspectives on error handling in general and point to a largely unexplored trail in programming language design space. Contents 1 Extended Abstract 3 2 Preliminaries 4 3 Introduction 5 4 Not a Tutorial: Side A 7 arXiv:1810.13430v3 [cs.PL] 30 Jan 2019 4.1 Before-Monadic.................................
    [Show full text]
  • Two Lectures on Constructive Type Theory
    Two Lectures on Constructive Type Theory Robert L. Constable July 20, 2015 Abstract Main Goal: One goal of these two lectures is to explain how important ideas and problems from computer science and mathematics can be expressed well in constructive type theory and how proof assistants for type theory help us solve them. Another goal is to note examples of abstract mathematical ideas currently not expressed well enough in type theory. The two lec- tures will address the following three specific questions related to this goal. Three Questions: One, what are the most important foundational ideas in computer science and mathematics that are expressed well in constructive type theory, and what concepts are more difficult to express? Two, how can proof assistants for type theory have a large impact on research and education, specifically in computer science, mathematics, and beyond? Three, what key ideas from type theory are students missing if they know only one of the modern type theories? The lectures are intended to complement the hands-on Nuprl tutorials by Dr. Mark Bickford that will introduce new topics as well as address these questions. The lectures refer to recent educational material posted on the PRL project web page, www.nuprl.org, especially the on-line article Logical Investigations, July 2014 on the front page of the web cite. Background: Decades of experience using proof assistants for constructive type theories, such as Agda, Coq, and Nuprl, have brought type theory ever deeper into computer science research and education. New type theories implemented by proof assistants are being developed. More- over, mathematicians are showing interest in enriching these theories to make them a more suitable foundation for mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Code-Free Recursion & Realizability
    Code-free recursion & realizability Eric Faber Universiteit Utrecht February 24, 2014 Outline 1 History Combinatory Logic Computability Theory Motivation 2 Partial combinatory algebras PCAs are very rich PCAs allow for Abstract Recursion Theory 3 Realizability Toposes From Categories of Assemblies . to Realizability Toposes Morphisms Subtoposes Eric Faber ( Universiteit Utrecht ) Code-free recursion & realizability February 24, 2014 2 / 30 History Combinatory Logic Combinatory Logic • Combinatory logic was founded by Moses Schönfinkel in his article “Über die Bausteine der mathematischen Logik” in 1924. • Intended as a pre-logic that would solve foundational issues that arise from the use of variables by eliminating them. • Further development was mostly due to Haskell Curry in the 50s, after which combinatory logic regained interest in theoretical computer science Moses Schönfinkel Haskell Curry Eric Faber ( Universiteit Utrecht ) Code-free recursion & realizability February 24, 2014 3 / 30 History Computability Theory Computability Theory • Founded in 1936 by work of Alan Turing, Alonzo Church, Stephen Kleene and Emil Post • Mathematical rigorous definition of a computation • First results on undecidability Turing Church Kleene Post Eric Faber ( Universiteit Utrecht ) Code-free recursion & realizability February 24, 2014 4 / 30 History Computability Theory The Effective Topos • In 1982, Martin Hyland discovered the “Effective Topos” • From the viewpoint of a Topos as a “constructive universe”, the Effective Topos is an effective universe. • The internal first-order logic of the Effective Topos coincides with Kleene’s notion of realizability Martin Hyland Eric Faber ( Universiteit Utrecht ) Code-free recursion & realizability February 24, 2014 5 / 30 History Motivation Why Study PCAs and Realizability Toposes? • PCAs give rise to a lot of interpretations of constructive proofs • Realizability Toposes give higher-order interpretations of this logic and help understand them • Applications in Computer Science (e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • Representation of Compositional Relational Programs
    Representation of Compositional Relational Programs Representation of Compositional Relational Programs Görkem Paçacı Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Lecture hall 2, Ekonomikum, Uppsala, Friday, 28 April 2017 at 13:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Professor Alberto Pettorossi (University of Rome Tor Vergata). Abstract Paçacı, G. 2017. Representation of Compositional Relational Programs. 216 pp. Uppsala: Department of Informatics and Media, Uppsala University. ISBN 978-91-506-2621-6. Usability aspects of programming languages are often overlooked, yet have a substantial effect on programmer productivity. These issues are even more acute in the field of Inductive Synthesis, where programs are automatically generated from sample expected input and output data, and the programmer needs to be able to comprehend, and confirm or reject the suggested programs. A promising method of Inductive Synthesis, CombInduce, which is particularly suitable for synthesizing recursive programs, is a candidate for improvements in usability as the target language Combilog is not user-friendly. The method requires the target language to be strictly compositional, hence devoid of variables, yet have the expressiveness of definite clause programs. This sets up a challenging problem for establishing a user-friendly but equally expressive target language. Alternatives to Combilog, such as Quine's Predicate-functor Logic and Schönfinkel and Curry's Combinatory Logic also do not offer a practical notation: finding a more usable representation is imperative. This thesis presents two distinct approaches towards more convenient representations which still maintain compositionality. The first is Visual Combilog (VC), a system for visualizing Combilog programs.
    [Show full text]
  • Lukasz LACHOWSKI on the COMPLEXITY of the STANDARD TRANSLATION of LAMBDA CALCULUS INTO COMBINATORY LOGIC
    REPORTS ON MATHEMATICAL LOGIC 53 (2018), 19–42 doi: 10.4467/20842589RM.18.002.8835 Lukasz LACHOWSKI ON THE COMPLEXITY OF THE STANDARD TRANSLATION OF LAMBDA CALCULUS INTO COMBINATORY LOGIC A b s t r a c t. We investigate the complexity of the standard translation of lambda calculus into combinatory logic. The main result shows that the asymptotic growth rate of the size of a trans- lated term is Θ(n3) in worst-case, where n denotes the size of the lambda term. .1 Introduction Both lambda calculus ([Chu36]) and combinatory logic ([Cur30]) are Turing- complete models of computation. As such, lambda calculus serves as a the- Received 8 June 2017 This work was partially supported by the grant 2013/11/B/ST6/00975 funded by the Pol- ish National Science Center. Keywords and phrases: combinatory logic, lambda calculus, complexity analysis, func- tional programming. AMS subject classification: 03B40, 68Q25, 68N18. 20 LUKASZ LACHOWSKI oretical basis for many functional programming languages, e.g. Haskell and SML. Evaluating expressions in lambda calculus is not easy since semantics of the substitution must be defined carefully to avoid problems with vari- ables binding. One of the motivations for introducing combinatory logic was to eliminate the notion of bound variables from logical formulas and to simplify the definition of substitution. Thereby, compared to lambda calcu- lus, combinatory logic is simpler in terms of computational interpretations. In the definition of combinatory logic we use only two combinators, namely S and K. Together with the notion of reduction, it is sufficient to define any recursive function in this model.
    [Show full text]
  • Lambda-Calculus : from Logic to Computation
    Introduction Context : development of functional systems Age 1 : Lambda-formalism in a system of logic Age 2 : Constitution of lambda-calculus Age 3 : Introduction of types Conclusions Lambda-Calculus : from logic to computation Wendy Hammache IRPhiL, Université Jean Moulin Lyon 3 PROGRAMme Autumn workshop: formalisms at the interface with machines, languages and systems, Bertinoro October 17, 2018 Wendy Hammache Lambda-Calculus : from logic to computation 1 / 25 Introduction Context : development of functional systems Age 1 : Lambda-formalism in a system of logic Topic of the talk Age 2 : Constitution of lambda-calculus Outline Age 3 : Introduction of types Conclusions Lambda-calculus Nowadays we say about lambda-calculus : It is the first programming language It is the formalism underlying every functional programming language It embodies the formalism to write every program we can code with traditional programming languages Wendy Hammache Lambda-Calculus : from logic to computation 2 / 25 Introduction Context : development of functional systems Age 1 : Lambda-formalism in a system of logic Topic of the talk Age 2 : Constitution of lambda-calculus Outline Age 3 : Introduction of types Conclusions Lambda-calculus Why would we want to create a programming language ? as computers did not exist yet What could be the resaons to create a language such as a programming one ? Motivations ? Usage ? Wendy Hammache Lambda-Calculus : from logic to computation 3 / 25 Introduction Context : development of functional systems Age 1 : Lambda-formalism
    [Show full text]
  • Categorical Combinators
    INFORMATION AND CONTROL 69, 188-254 (1986) Categorical Combinators P.-L. CURIEN CNRS-UniversitO Paris VII, LITP, Tour 55-56 ler dtage, 3 Place Jussieu, 75221 Paris Cedex 05, France Our main aim is to present the connection between 2-calculus and Cartesian closed categories both in an untyped and purely syntactic setting. More specifically we establish a syntactic equivalence theorem between what we call categorical com- binatory logic and j--calculus with explicit products and projections, with fl and q-rules as well as with surjective pairing. "Combinatory logic" is of course inspired by Curry's combinatory logic, based on the well-known S, K,/. Our combinatory logic is "categorical" because its combinators and rules are obtained by extracting untyped information from Cartesian closed categories (looking at arrows only, thus forgetting about objects). Compiling J.-calculus into these combinators happens to be natural and provokes only n log n code expansion. Moreover categorical com- binatory logic is entirely faithful to /~-reduction where combinatory logic needs additional rather complex and unnatural axioms to be. The connection easily extends to the corresponding typed calculi, where typed categorical combinatory logic is a free Cartesian closed category where the notion of terminal object is replaced by the explicit manipulation of applying (a function to its argument) and coupling (arguments to build datas in products). Our syntactic equivalences induce equivalences at the model level. The paper is intended as a mathematical foun- dation for developing implementations of functional programming languages based on a "categorical abstract machine," as developed in a companion paper (Cousineau, Curien, and Mauny, in "Proceedings, ACM Conf.
    [Show full text]
  • Functional Programming with Overloading and Higher-Order Polymorphism
    Functional Programming with Overloading and Higher-Order Polymorphism Mark P. Jones Department of Computer Science, University of Nottingham, University Park, Nottingham NG7 2RD, UK. Abstract. The Hindley/Milner type system has been widely adopted as a basis for statically typed functional languages. One of the main reasons for this is that it provides an elegant compromise between flexibility, al- lowing a single value to be used in different ways, and practicality, freeing the programmer from the need to supply explicit type information. Focusing on practical applications rather than implementation or theo- retical details, these notes examine a range of extensions that provide more flexible type systems while retaining many of the properties that have made the original Hindley/Milner system so popular. The topics discussed, some old, but most quite recent, include higher-order poly- morphism and type and constructor class overloading. Particular em- phasis is placed on the use of these features to promote modularity and reusability. 1 Introduction The Hindley/Milner type system [6, 19, 3], hereafter referred to as HM, repre- sents a significant and highly influential step in the development of type systems for functional programming languages. In our opinion, the main reason for this is that it combines the following features in a single framework: – Type security: soundness results guarantee that well-typed programs can- not ‘go wrong’. This should be compared with the situation in dynamically typed languages like Scheme where run-time tests are often required to check that appropriate types of value are used in a particular context, and the ex- ecution of a program may terminate if these tests fail.
    [Show full text]
  • The Monad.Reader Issue 17 by Douglas M
    The Monad.Reader Issue 17 by Douglas M. Auclair [email protected] and Neil Brown [email protected] and Petr Pudl´ak [email protected] January 9, 2011 Brent Yorgey, editor. Contents Brent Yorgey Editorial3 Douglas M. Auclair List Leads Off with the Letter λ 5 Neil Brown The InterleaveT Abstraction: Alternative with Flexible Ordering 13 Petr Pudl´ak The Reader Monad and Abstraction Elimination 35 2 Editorial by Brent Yorgey [email protected] You may have noticed this edition of The Monad.Reader is rather late. This is because for the past eight months I have been the prisoner of giant, evil, imperative- programming-obsessed naked mole rats. I have managed to stay connected to the outside world by training earthworms to transmit IP packets, but as you may imagine, this is rather slow. The earthworms have been working nonstop to bring you this issue, which consists of three fun articles I hope you will enjoy: Doug Auclair explains the ins and outs of difference lists, a functional list represen- tation allowing fast concatenation and appending; Neil Brown presents his new InterleaveT abstraction for flexible interleaving of streams of behavior; and Petr Pudl´akexplains abstraction elimination { the process carried out by lambdabot's @pl command { in terms of the Reader monad. By the way, if you happen to meet \me" in real life, beware! It is actually an evil robotic replica. List Leads Off with the Letter λ by Douglas M. Auclair [email protected] The list data type provides a powerful way to operate with a collection of objects using a very simple syntax.
    [Show full text]