A Treatise on Democratic Rhetoric and Rhetorical Democracy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Treatise on Democratic Rhetoric and Rhetorical Democracy University of Denver Digital Commons @ DU Electronic Theses and Dissertations Graduate Studies 8-1-2013 The Nature of Authentic Governance: A Treatise on Democratic Rhetoric and Rhetorical Democracy Daniel L. Foster University of Denver Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.du.edu/etd Part of the History Commons, and the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Foster, Daniel L., "The Nature of Authentic Governance: A Treatise on Democratic Rhetoric and Rhetorical Democracy" (2013). Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 205. https://digitalcommons.du.edu/etd/205 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate Studies at Digital Commons @ DU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ DU. For more information, please contact [email protected],[email protected]. THE NATURE OF AUTHENTIC GOVERNANCE: A TREATISE ON DEMOCRATIC RHETORIC AND RHETORICAL DEMOCRACY __________ A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of Social Sciences University of Denver __________ In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy __________ by Daniel L. Foster August 2013 Advisor: Dr. Darrin Hicks ©Copyright by Daniel L. Foster 2013 All Rights Reserved Author: Daniel L. Foster Title: THE NATURE OF AUTHENTIC GOVERNANCE: A TREATISE ON DEMOCRATIC RHETORIC AND RHETORICAL DEMOCRACY Advisor: Dr. Darrin Hicks Degree Date: August 2013 ABSTRACT Democracy is a form of governance that allows for the flourishing of human potentiality. Unfortunately, democracy has become less of a means of governance and more of a rhetorical device to secure the consent of the people to be ruled by the elite few. Thus the current study seeks to disrupt this hegemonic means of control through an explication of authentic governance and democracy in order to demonstrate that the current manifestations of governance associated with democracy are inauthentic. To begin, authentic democracy –direct or as it is constituted here, rhetorical democracy– can foster a citizenry of active and empowered participants who express their public wills through rhetorical engagements so as to generate a collective will productive of a collectively binding decision that is reflective of a societal common good. To achieve this end, the foundation of the communicative process is set up as being inherently rhetorical and fundamental for the establishment and continuance of the symbolic orders generative of society’s macro- and micro-cultures. Next, engagement of these symbolic orders through democratic rhetoric is necessary for authentic governance to be actualized. Democratic rhetoric posits a new way of understanding and employing invention for rhetorical engagements concerning public problems, as well as constructing a new notion of rhetorical accountability. It is in one’s participation in the collectively binding decision-making process of a rhetorical democracy, which necessitates inventing through ii the symbolic orders of others, that the educative and transformative power of rhetoric is facilitated and realized. Additionally, this study reconceptualizes ideology as primarily a sense-making system that provides a method for critical ideological analysis of both Athenian democracy and American governance. Democratic rhetoric hinges upon the citizenry’s ability to participate as empowered, functional equals – core ideological constructs of Athenian democracy – in the collectively binding decision-making process. Finally, to facilitate the possibility of democratic rhetoric within governance the current research constructs the possible means, functions and structures, for enacting a rhetorical democracy within the contemporary political context. The implications of this investigation into meaningful symbol systems, culture, rhetoric, ideology, and democracy and the subsequent theory building will prove to be fruitful within the contexts discussed here and in many others. iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The wonder of writing a dissertation is that it is both a singular and collective act. Acknowledging those who have poured into the process is a significant moment of learning and celebration. I cannot express how wonderfully my committee has exhibited extraordinary grace and favor as I persevered through my research and writing. The judicious and timely contributions of Dr. Darrin Hicks were not only inspirational but also invaluable for the directions pursued. Modeling an intelligence and excellence that necessitated my own pursuit of both, Dr. Christina Foust from the very beginning has demonstrated to me that our work should be meaningful for the lives of others who are resisting oppression. In the teaching of Dr. Bernadette Calafell my reflective thinking about the implications of culture pushed my understanding of rhetoric and democracy. The heart of Dr. Sandra Dixon to serve and lead will constantly remind me of a true example of how to be a compassionate educator and scholar. To my supportive community – filled with wonderful individuals who have amazingly contributed to all of my being and scholarship – I certainly have achieved this moment only because of you all. Dr. Brant Short and Dr. Dayle Hardy-Short have not only encouraged me, they have also been my ongoing mentors. Dr Arianna Molloy, you were my respondent and wise counselor throughout this journey. Our talking walks were imperative for the development and refinement of the ideas presented here. My family’s loving support has brought me through the dissertation process by being a means of restoring my physical and mental capacities each Christmas and summer break. The common thread that holds us all together is our love for God who has never failed to walk beside or carry me to this new beginning. You are my Shield and the Lifter of my head. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter One: American Democracy? ................................................................................. 2 Authentic Democracy and Democratic Inauthenticity: A Sketch ........................... 8 Critiquing the Critiques of Direct Democracy ...................................................... 21 Pushing Beyond Limitations of Nature and Structure .............................. 22 Being too Fearful to Rule .......................................................................... 24 Difference Necessitates a Place for Public Appearance ........................... 26 Democratic Dangers: Athenian Judgment Nearly Gone Awry ................. 31 The People as a Repository of Superior Knowledge ................................ 34 The Impermanency of Democratic Decisions........................................... 48 Oversight of Democratic Decisions that is Accountable to the People .... 51 Conclusion ............................................................................................................ 54 Dissertation Chapter Summaries ........................................................................... 55 Chapter Two: Justifications for Authentic Democracy .................................................... 57 Introduction: Justifications for Authentic Democracy .......................................... 57 Human Nature and Existence ................................................................................ 58 From Nature to Society ......................................................................................... 67 Citizenship ............................................................................................................ 79 Will a World into Being ........................................................................................ 82 To Act in the World .............................................................................................. 91 Conclusion: Fostering the Flourishing of Humanity ............................................ 94 Chapter Three: The Democratic Rhetoric Project ............................................................ 96 Introduction: Justifications for Authentic Democracy .......................................... 96 Authentic Governance .............................................................................. 97 Authentic Governance is Democratic Governance ................................... 99 Foundation of Rhetoric for Democratic Rhetoric ............................................... 103 From Symbols to Culture and Back Again ......................................................... 119 Symbols................................................................................................... 119 Meaning .................................................................................................. 124 Language ................................................................................................. 130 Culture..................................................................................................... 138 Habitus .................................................................................................... 144 Communication Communities ................................................................ 150 Symbolic Orders as Necessary Resources for Democratic Rhetoric .................. 157 Significance of Micro-Cultural Symbolic Orders for Democratic Rhetoric ................................................................................................................. 161 Necessity of Productive Difference for Democratic Rhetoric ................ 165 Symbolic Experimentation through the Process
Recommended publications
  • Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy the Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of Its Impending End
    Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End A doctoral thesis by O. H. Linderborg Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Engelska Parken, 7-0042, Thunbergsvägen 3H, Uppsala, Monday, 3 September 2018 at 14:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Docent Elton Barker (Open University). Abstract Linderborg, O. H. 2018. Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy. The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End. 224 pp. Uppsala: Department of Linguistics and Philology, Uppsala University. ISBN 978-91-506-2703-9. This investigation proposes a historical theory of the origins of political philosophy. It is assumed that political philosophy was made possible by a new form of political thinking commencing with the inauguration of the first direct democracies in Ancient Greece. The pristine turn from elite rule to rule of the people – or to δημοκρατία, a term coined after the event – brought with it the first ever political theory, wherein fundamentally different societal orders, or different principles of societal rule, could be argumentatively compared. The inauguration of this alternative-envisioning “secular” political theory is equaled with the beginnings of classical political theory and explained as the outcome of the conjoining of a new form of constitutionalized political thought (cratistic thinking) and a new emphasis brought to the inner consistency of normative reasoning (‘internal critique’). The original form of political philosophy, Classical Political Philosophy, originated when a political thought launched, wherein non-divinely sanctioned visions of transcendence of the prevailing rule, as well as of the full range of alternatives disclosed by Classical Political Theory, first began to be envisioned.
    [Show full text]
  • Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: the Medium As
    Isocrates & Europe - 1 Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: The Medium as Message I. Introduction: Overview The idea that Isocrates helped create the concept of transnationalism that fostered Europe both as an idea and as an eventual political union is common fare in rhetorical studies. De Romilly (1992) writes that “Isocrates was perhaps the first in antiquity to focus his political theories on the idea of Europe” (p. 2). Isocrates anticipated “the idea of Europe” (Hariman, 2004, p. 231) and used the words Europen and Europes 13 times in his essays. But, to date, critical exploration of Isocrates’ role in developing the idea of Europe has primarily dealt with the content of his works – with his eloquent and relentless focus on panhellenism and the related conflict between Europe and Asia. This paper, however, will focus on medium rather than message. It will focus on Isocrates’ pioneering use of a new medium – written documents/syggrammata – and the role that the new rhetorical medium played in forming Europe. The most famous passage in the Isocratean canon, the so-called Hymn to Logos (Jaeger, 1944/1971), which first appeared in Nicocles (5-9) and was repeated in Antidosis (253-257), holds that speech/logos is a civic and political unifier, by means of which “we have come together and founded cities and made laws and invented arts” (Nicocles 6). Yet before Isocrates, who was “the first individual who could be termed a ‘writer’ in the modern sense of the term” (Lentz, 1989), logos and its community-building powers Isocrates & Europe - 2 traveled primarily orally: Cities, alliances, arts, and laws were built through face-to-face communication.
    [Show full text]
  • Textual Allusion As Rhetorical Argumentation: Gorgias, Plato and Isocrates
    Textual allusion as rhetorical argumentation: Gorgias, Plato and Isocrates Christopher W. Tindale Department of Philosophy University of Windsor [email protected] 1. Introduction: A central characteristic of rhetorical argumentation is the way in which it anticipates the responses of the audience in the structure of the argument, inviting a co-development through expressed and implicit commonalities. Strategies of invitation include ways to capture the audience’s prior beliefs and understandings, to expand the cognitive environment of the argumentation in relevant ways. One such strategy is allusion (Tindale, 2004, Ch.3) and a key variety of this is textual allusion, where an arguer uses intertextual references and imitations to evoke ideas in the minds of an audience and draw them toward a conclusion. Allusions convey an indirect reference in passing without making explicit mention. So for an arguer to employ this strategy she must be confident that the reference alluded to is sufficiently present in the cognitive environment (that is, the beliefs, knowledge and background information) of her audience in order for the association to be grasped and the further conclusion drawn. We see some vivid cases of this confidence in the textual allusions of early Greek practitioners of argument, Plato and Isocrates, as they try to win their audiences’ support for particular ways of conceiving the concept ‘philosopher’. Each reminds the audience of alternative ideas while at the same time gaining weight in the eyes of the audience by allusion to earlier texts with which they are familiar. In Plato’s case, he structures the Apology of Socrates so as it refers to the Defense of Palamedes by Gorgias (483-376 BC), a text with which his audience would be familiar.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle-Rhetoric.Pdf
    Rhetoric Aristotle (Translated by W. Rhys Roberts) Book I 1 Rhetoric is the counterpart of Dialectic. Both alike are con- cerned with such things as come, more or less, within the general ken of all men and belong to no definite science. Accordingly all men make use, more or less, of both; for to a certain extent all men attempt to discuss statements and to maintain them, to defend themselves and to attack others. Ordinary people do this either at random or through practice and from acquired habit. Both ways being possible, the subject can plainly be handled systematically, for it is possible to inquire the reason why some speakers succeed through practice and others spontaneously; and every one will at once agree that such an inquiry is the function of an art. Now, the framers of the current treatises on rhetoric have cons- tructed but a small portion of that art. The modes of persuasion are the only true constituents of the art: everything else is me- rely accessory. These writers, however, say nothing about en- thymemes, which are the substance of rhetorical persuasion, but deal mainly with non-essentials. The arousing of prejudice, pity, anger, and similar emotions has nothing to do with the essential facts, but is merely a personal appeal to the man who is judging the case. Consequently if the rules for trials which are now laid down some states-especially in well-governed states-were applied everywhere, such people would have nothing to say. All men, no doubt, think that the laws should prescribe such rules, but some, as in the court of Areopagus, give practical effect to their thoughts 4 Aristotle and forbid talk about non-essentials.
    [Show full text]
  • Isocrates and the Origin of Civic Education. Validity of a Classical Author
    Isocrates and the origin of civic education. Validity of a classical author José Fernández-Santillán /[email protected] Tecnológico de Monterrey, Mexico City Campus, Mexico Abstract: Isocrates has been neglected as one of the principal figures of the main political thought. This essay tries his philosophical legacy, particularly his work as a civic educator. Today this is necessary because it is indispensable to build citizenship. His method in order to promote democracy was public deliberation not only by means of verbal discussion, but also by disseminating his writings. Isocrates promoted the creation of public spaces in which deliberation was possible. That is why he is considered a contributor of “public spaces” as we know them today. What we underline is that Isocrates believed in the value of the word as the main transformation of men and political regimes. The idea of democracy was the regime established by Solon and Clisthenes. He always took into account this model in order to restore civic life in Athens and governance in City- states in Greece. Key words: civic education, policy, democracy, oligarchy, citizenship. Resumen: Isocrates ha sido descuidado como una figura señera entre los grandes pensadores políticos de la Grecia antigua. El presente ensayo rescata el legado de este filósofo, particularmente su trabajo como educador cívico, hoy tan necesario para construir ciudadanía. El método que utilizó para promover la democracia fue la deliberación pública, no solamente a través de la discusión verbal sino también de la difusión de escritos. En consecuencia, Isocrates contribuyó a crear espacios de discusión muy semejantes a lo que ahora conocemos como “esfera pública”.
    [Show full text]
  • Charis and Philia in Plato's Gorgias Jan Marie Christiansen Beane Iowa State University
    Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Retrospective Theses and Dissertations Dissertations 1996 Charis and philia in Plato's Gorgias Jan Marie Christiansen Beane Iowa State University Follow this and additional works at: https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/rtd Part of the English Language and Literature Commons, and the Rhetoric and Composition Commons Recommended Citation Beane, Jan Marie Christiansen, "Charis and philia in Plato's Gorgias " (1996). Retrospective Theses and Dissertations. 7083. https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/rtd/7083 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Dissertations at Iowa State University Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Retrospective Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Iowa State University Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Charis and philia in Plato's Gorgias by Jan Marie Christiansen Beane A thesis submitted to the graduate faculty in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Major: English (Rhetoric, Composition, and Professional Commurucation) Major Professor: Scott P. Consigny Iowa State University Ames, Iowa 1996 11 Graduate College Iowa State University This is to certify that the Master's thesis of Jan Marie Christiansen Beane has met the thesis requirements of Iowa State University Signatures have been redacted for privacy Ill TABLE OF CONTENTS NOTE ON TRANSLATIONS AND TRANSLITERATIONS iv LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS vi CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION CHAPTER 2. INTERPRETIVE STRATEGY CHAPTERS. CHi4il?S IN GREEK CULTURE AND LITERATURE 15 CHAPTER 4. THE RHETORICAL SITUATION OF THE GORGIAS 26 CHAPTER 5.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Gorgias Reloaded: a New-Found Dialogue Between Gorgias And
    1. Gorgias Reloaded: A New-Found Dialogue between Gorgias and Socrates In the Elysian Fields, Socrates to his surprise meets his old rhetorical adversary Gorgias—who has, in the meantime, come to think twice about some of the alleged errors that Socrates made him admit to in the Platonic dialogue about their original encounter. Among other things, Gorgias has had the advantage of gathering a few points from a certain young thinker hailing “from up North” (he presumably means Stagira). Thus equipped, he takes Socrates to task about several of his anti-rhetorical pronouncements from back then that Gorgias now feels he is in a position to challenge. SOCRATES Well, if that isn’t—you can call me a sophist if that isn’t— Gorgias! Old boy! Fancy meeting you here—in the Elysian Fields! The Island of the Blessed! The very man who brought that awful nuisance, rhetoric, to Athens! I’d never have thought I’d live to see that. In fact, I didn’t. GORGIAS No, you didn’t see that one coming, did you, Socrates? And you know, it was only recently that they let us in, me and my gang—you know, the other sophists, Protagoras and Prodicus and Antisthenes and those guys. And why do think that is? You did that to us. You did such a great job dragging our names through the mud, smearing me and the other sophists or rhetoricians, as you call us, and thanks to you most philosophers until this day have detested us. Take a philosopher like John Locke, one of the bright lights who started the so-called Enlightenment—he said this in An Essay on Human Understanding
    [Show full text]
  • The Modes of Classical Athenian Justice
    Articles "Verdict Most Just": The Modes of Classical Athenian Justice Adriaan Lanni* I. INTRODUCTION Most comparative lawyers know a great deal about Roman law but almost nothing about the courts of classical Athens. This is no mystery: unlike Roman law, Athenian law produced no jurisprudence and very little legal doctrine, and contributed nothing to the courts of Europe, England, or any other modem legal system. For the most part, Athenians decided legal disputes by empowering juries to apply statutes that were hopelessly broad. Juries could give weight to any sort of fact or plea that a litigant * Harvard University, Society of Fellows. J.D. Yale Law School, Ph.D. (Ancient History) University of Michigan. I would like to thank Oren Bar-Gill, Victor Bers, Sara Forsdyke, Bruce Frier, Michael Gagarin, Michael Gordin, Robert Gordon, Thomas Green, Wesley Kelman, Eric Miller, James Whitman, and James Boyd White for their comments. Amanda Holm provided excellent research assistance. Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities Yale Journal of Law & the Humanities, Vol. 16, Iss. 2 [2004], Art.[Vol 1 16:277 cared to bring before them. To us, this looks like lawlessness. Did the Athenians simply fail to grasp the value of the rule of law as we know it? Were legal disputes fundamentally contests for status decided without any pretence to justice? These are the explanations ancient historians commonly give. In my view, the Athenian legal system was more complex than is generally thought. The Athenians made a conscious decision to reject the rule of law in most cases, and they did so because they thought giving juries unlimited discretion to reach verdicts based on the particular circumstances of each case was the most just way to resolve disputes.
    [Show full text]
  • Common Sense in the Basic Public Speaking Course Calvin L
    Basic Communication Course Annual Volume 14 Article 7 2002 Common Sense in the Basic Public Speaking Course Calvin L. Troup Dusquesne University Follow this and additional works at: http://ecommons.udayton.edu/bcca Part of the Higher Education Commons, Interpersonal and Small Group Communication Commons, Mass Communication Commons, Other Communication Commons, and the Speech and Rhetorical Studies Commons Recommended Citation Troup, Calvin L. (2002) "Common Sense in the Basic Public Speaking Course," Basic Communication Course Annual: Vol. 14 , Article 7. Available at: http://ecommons.udayton.edu/bcca/vol14/iss1/7 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Communication at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Basic Communication Course Annual by an authorized editor of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Troup: Common Sense in the Basic Public Speaking Course 39 Common Sense in the Basic Public Speaking Course Calvin L. Troup The foundation of the basic public speaking course is not widely questioned today. As a public speaking course director, I have become well acquainted with sales representatives from many publishers. All of them want me to switch to their text for the coming se­ mester, except for one. I routinely tell the representa­ tives that any of the top ten public speaking textbook authors could probably teach an excellent version of the course from any of the top ten public speaking texts on the market. The shared foundation is so secure, and the emphases that distinguish these texts are so slight, that good teachers can comfortably employ any of them.
    [Show full text]
  • Americans Profoundly Distrust Language: an Essay on Rhetoric And
    Antidosis1: An Apology for the Art of Rhetoric Thomas M. Rivers Because there has been implanted in us the power to persuade each other and to make clear to each other whatever we desire, not only have we escaped the life of wild beasts, but we have come together and founded cities and made laws and invented arts; and, generally speaking, there is no institution devised by man which the power of speech has not helped us to establish (from Isocrates’ Antidosis) The O.J. Simpson trial confirmed for a majority of Americans their low opinion of lawyers and revealed their low opinion of rhetoric, especially the rhetoric of public discourse. For over thirty years I have taught the art of rhetoric to many students who initially, at least, have shared this majority view. I believe that more than anything else that it is the mistrust and misunderstanding of this art that accounts for our despising lawyers, politicians, public relations professionals, and advertising executives.2 Persuasion depends on language, and the defining attitude of too many Americans toward language is a profound distrust. What 1 The title for this piece comes from the work of the same name written by Isocrates of Athens (436-338 B.C.E.). This work is one of the most famous defenses of the art of rhetoric. 2 A more recent telling example involves the demonizing of Kenneth Starr by a majority of Americans. This example is interesting since Starr was a prosecutor, not a defense attorney, and the case itself was political, if not Starr’s motives as well.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Norms in the Courts of Ancient Athens
    SOCIAL NORMS IN THE COURTS OF ANCIENT ATHENS Adriaan Lanni1 ABSTRACT Ancient Athens was a remarkably peaceful and well-ordered society by both an- cient and contemporary standards. Scholars typically attribute Athens’ success to internalized norms and purely informal enforcement mechanisms. This article ar- gues that the formal Athenian court system played a vital role in maintaining order by enforcing informal norms. This peculiar approach to norm enforcement com- pensated for apparent weaknesses in the state system of coercion. It mitigated the effects of under-enforcement in a private prosecution system by encouraging litigants to uncover and punish their opponents’ past violations. Court enforce- ment of extra-statutory norms also permitted the Athenians to enforce a variety of social norms while maintaining the fictions of voluntary devotion to military and public service and of limited state interference in private conduct. Informal norms have lately been celebrated as an important adjunct to for- 1 mal law in regulating behavior (e.g., Ellickson 1991). There is a rich academ- ic literature examining the relationship between social norms and informal sanctions (such as gossip or private dispute resolution) on the one hand, and formal legal rules and institutions on the other (e.g., Law and Society Review 2000; Journal of Legal Studies 1998; University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1996). Scholars have explored these issues in various social settings: the in- ternational diamond trade (Bernstein 1992), the cotton industry (Bernstein 2001),
    [Show full text]
  • The Social Structure of Democratic Athens’, in Morte E Vida Na Grécia Antiga: Olhares Interdisciplinares, Eds
    D. M. Pritchard 2020 (in press). ‘The social structure of democratic Athens’, in Morte e Vida na Grécia Antiga: Olhares interdisciplinares, eds. M. A. de Oliveira Silva and C. D. de Souza. Teresina (Editora da UFPI). THE SOCIAL STRUCTURE OF DEMOCRATIC ATHENS David M. Pritchard 1. Introduction: Three Distinct Groups Classical Athens had three distinct groups. 1 The largest, by far, was the Athenian descent group, whose members were the offspring of Athenian fathers and Attic women. The second largest group consisted of metics. It included resident aliens who had registered as such with the Athenian state, as well as their dependants. The smallest group were the slaves. Within the Athenian descent group, gender dictated radically different statuses. Athenian males enjoyed the highest status of Attica’s residents. As classical Athens was a democracy, male citizens equally enjoyed extensive legal and political rights, as well as the obligation to fight in the armed forces. Athenian men had the right to own land and became, usually after their marriages, the masters of households. Their female relatives had a much lower status. As a woman had no share in Athenian democracy, she was never considered ‘a citizen’ or, for that matter, ‘an Athenian’. Instead, she was called an ast ē (‘a woman belonging to the city’) or an Attik ē gun ē (‘an Attic woman’). Free males believed that their female relatives should concentrate on being homemakers. Nevertheless, even within her household an Attic woman was treated as a perpetual minor and was always subordinated to her master, whether he be her father, husband or adult son.
    [Show full text]