The Relationship Between the Chomsky Hierarchy and Automata

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Relationship Between the Chomsky Hierarchy and Automata THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE CHOMSKY HIERARCHY AND AUTOMATA GEORGE KIM Abstract. This paper will informally detail the hierarchy of classes in au- tomata theory. The concept and model of each automaton will be introduced, including a basic diagram and mathematical representation. In order to es- tablish the hierarchy, examples and theorems will be given, showing how some problems can be solved by one automaton but not by another. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Finite Automaton 2 2.1. Deterministic Finite Automata 2 2.2. Non-deterministic Finite Automaton 3 2.3. Epsilon Transitions 3 3. Pushdown Automata 5 4. Grammars 6 4.1. Production Rules 6 4.2. Pumping Lemmas 7 5. Turing Machines 8 5.1. The Limits of Turing Machines 9 Appendix A. The Chomsky Hierarchy 10 Acknowledgments 10 References 10 1. Introduction The field of automata theory focuses on the study of automata and abstract machines, which are essentially models of computation such that when enacted, certain computational problems can be solved. Automata are very simple in their workings, often taking in basic inputs and moving in defined ways, almost like a chess piece on a chessboard. As automata get more advanced in their models, they obtain the ability to solve a larger set of computational problems. In essence, the classes of automata and abstract machines follow a hierarchy, where machines of higher classes can solve the problems that machines of lower classes can, and more. It will be seen that automata are closely linked to formal languages and grammars, which have an organizational structure called the Chomsky Hierarchy. The rest of this paper will go through the hierarchy of automata, their associated grammars, Date: DEADLINES: Draft AUGUST 19 and Final version AUGUST 31, 2019. 1 2 GEORGE KIM and walk through examples of of problems that these machines can and cannot solve. 2. Finite Automaton The first type of model/machine encountered in automata theory are the finite automata, or finite state machines. Finite automata are well represented by the 5-tuple (Q; Σ; δ; q0;F ). Definition 2.1. Finite automata are defined by the 5-tuple (Q; Σ; δ; q0;F ), where:. • Q is the finite set of states • Σ is the alphabet (a finite set of symbols) • δ is the transition function, which defines which state the FA moves to when given an input • q0 2 Q is the initial or start state • F ⊆ Q is the set of accepting or final states In terms of finite automata, there are two subclasses of automata, the determin- istic finite automaton (DFA) and the non-deterministic finite automaton (NFA). 2.1. Deterministic Finite Automata. The deterministic finite automaton, re- ferred to as a DFA, is the simplest version of the finite automata. The machine accepts one simple input, such as a number, at which point the transition function defines a determined (hence deterministic) shift to a certain state. The transition function can be represented in several ways, but it is formally defined as a function: Definition 2.2. For a deterministic finite automaton, the transition function δ(q; a) takes in a state q 2 Q and input a 2 Σ and returns one state q∗ 2 Q that the DFA would enter. Typically, the user will feed the machine a list of these inputs, called a string. The machine will process these inputs individually in the order given, moving from state to state until it processes all of the string's contents. At the end of a string, if the machine ends up in one of its defined accepting or end states, the string is accepted, or deemed valid by the machine. Consider the following transition diagram of a DFA, another representation to the 5-tuple: 0 q1 0 1 start q0 q3 1 0 q2 1 The 5-tuple would be defined as follows: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE CHOMSKY HIERARCHY AND AUTOMATA 3 • Q = q0; q1; q2; q3 • Σ = 0; 1 • q0 = q0 • F = q3 • δ shown as a transition table: Present State Next State when 0 Inputted Next State when 1 Inputted q0 q1 q2 q1 q1 q3 q2 q3 q1 This particular DFA has an alphabet with two possible inputs: 0 or 1. Depending on which state (qn) the DFA is in, these inputs have a defined behavior, clearly shown by the diagram and table. In this particular DFA, q3 is the accepting state, signaling the end of the DFA's computation process. Through some simple test cases, one realizes that the DFA only reaches the end state once both the 0 and 1 inputs have been used. In essence, if the DFA receives 0 as the first input, it will not reach the accepting state until a 1 has been inputted, and vice versa. This can be signified by the notation 0n1 or 1n0. This DFA can thus detect whether a given string of inputs contains two different inputs or not. 2.2. Non-deterministic Finite Automaton. A non-deterministic finite automa- ton, shortened to NFA, is similar to the DFA, except that the transition function has a slightly altered definition: Definition 2.3. For a non-deterministic finite automaton, the transition function δ(q; a) takes in a state q 2 Q and input a 2 Σ and returns one or more states fq∗g ⊆ Q that the DFA would enter. Based on this definition, it is easy to see that all deterministic finite automata are non-deterministic finite automata, but not the other way around. In other words, the set of all DFAs is a subset of all the NFAs. To gain a greater familiarity with nondeterminism, observe the following transition diagram of an NFA: 0 0, 1 0, 1 start q0 q1 q2 1 0 At first glance, the transition diagrams of a NFA and DFA don't look glaringly different. In fact, the only difference between the two is that for a DFA, a given input can only appear on one path from a given state. The NFA can have one input appear on multiple paths from one state. For example, in the NFA above, when in the state q0, the input 0 can lead to either q0 or q1. A DFA cannot have multiple paths like these, hence why it is deterministic. Despite this difference, there is no further scope of computational power attained by the NFA over the DFA. In fact, the premise of the NFA is that it can be compiled into a DFA [1]. That is, there is an algorithm to convert a NFA to a DFA [6]. 2.3. Epsilon Transitions. There is a further abstraction of the finite automata with the introduction of -transitions. -transitions do not change the scope of 4 GEORGE KIM computational power, but provide a shorthand of sorts to draw an NFA without the potentially tenacious task of drawing every input transition possible [1]. The -transition allows the NFA to move to a state with no input, signified by , the empty string. This is certainly a peculiar idea at first. Here is an example for aid: 1 q1 0 1 1 start q0 q2 As like any NFA, when starting at q0, the start state, two inputs could occur, 0 or 1. Informally, the -transition allows the NFA to be in multiple states simulta- neously. Any state connected to the current state q via an -transition is said to be within ECLOSE(q). If 0 is the input, the NFA can stay in state q0, but it can also be in state q2 due to the -transition. If 1 is the input, the NFA can only be in state q1, since if we follow that the NFA had been in state q2 at the time as well, there is no transition defined for 1, so this path just dies. As such, a few mental test cases show that the NFA can accept zero or more 0s followed by either two or more 1s or just nothing. In other words, the NFA will accept the empty string (), 0∗, or 0∗11∗1, shortened to 0∗ + 0∗11∗1. Else, the machine runs into an undefined path, thus the string is not accepted. An -NFA certainly is more complicated than a normal NFA, but as previously mentioned, the introduction of the -transition does not actually grant further com- putational power. In essence, this means that all possible input strings accepted by an -NFA, called its language, is also accepted by some NFA, and as a result, a DFA as well [1]. The premise behind converting an -NFA to a DFA involves first removing the transitions to obtain a normal NFA, then converting that NFA to a DFA. Removing the transitions involves considering all possible inputs that lead to a certain state and then creating a new pathway with that input to all states within ECLOSE(q). A formal algorithm exists for this process [7], but for a simple example, observe the given -NFA: 1 q1 q3 1 start q0 q5 1 q2 q4 1 Since q1 and q2 are connected to q0 by an -transition, ECLOSE(q0)=fq1; q2g. Now, when starting at q0, the -transition makes us imagine that we are currently in all states of ECLOSE(q0) at the same time. Thus, when the input 1 is given, THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN THE CHOMSKY HIERARCHY AND AUTOMATA 5 the machine arrives in q3, q2, and q4. In fact, the machine also arrives in q5 since when arriving in q3, there is an -transition to q5, meaning we can reach that state without any input. Knowing this, the equivalent DFA is obtained: 1 start q0; q1; q2 q2; q3; q4; q5 Though a formal proof exists, intuition correctly asserts that the ability to con- vert -NFAs to DFAs means that these finite automata all accept the same languages [1].
Recommended publications
  • The Mathematics of Syntactic Structure: Trees and Their Logics
    Computational Linguistics Volume 26, Number 2 The Mathematics of Syntactic Structure: Trees and their Logics Hans-Peter Kolb and Uwe MÈonnich (editors) (Eberhard-Karls-UniversitÈat Tubingen) È Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter (Studies in Generative Grammar, edited by Jan Koster and Henk van Riemsdijk, volume 44), 1999, 347 pp; hardbound, ISBN 3-11-016273-3, $127.75, DM 198.00 Reviewed by Gerald Penn Bell Laboratories, Lucent Technologies Regular languages correspond exactly to those languages that can be recognized by a ®nite-state automaton. Add a stack to that automaton, and one obtains the context- free languages, and so on. Probably all of us learned at some point in our univer- sity studies about the Chomsky hierarchy of formal languages and the duality be- tween the form of their rewriting systems and the automata or computational re- sources necessary to recognize them. What is perhaps less well known is that yet another way of characterizing formal languages is provided by mathematical logic, namely in terms of the kind and number of variables, quanti®ers, and operators that a logical language requires in order to de®ne another formal language. This mode of characterization, which is subsumed by an area of research called descrip- tive complexity theory, is at once more declarative than an automaton or rewriting system, more ¯exible in terms of the primitive relations or concepts that it can pro- vide resort to, and less wedded to the tacit, not at all unproblematic, assumption that the right way to view any language, including natural language, is as a set of strings.
    [Show full text]
  • Hierarchy and Interpretability in Neural Models of Language Processing ILLC Dissertation Series DS-2020-06
    Hierarchy and interpretability in neural models of language processing ILLC Dissertation Series DS-2020-06 For further information about ILLC-publications, please contact Institute for Logic, Language and Computation Universiteit van Amsterdam Science Park 107 1098 XG Amsterdam phone: +31-20-525 6051 e-mail: [email protected] homepage: http://www.illc.uva.nl/ The investigations were supported by the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO), through a Gravitation Grant 024.001.006 to the Language in Interaction Consortium. Copyright © 2019 by Dieuwke Hupkes Publisher: Boekengilde Printed and bound by printenbind.nl ISBN: 90{6402{222-1 Hierarchy and interpretability in neural models of language processing Academisch Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Universiteit van Amsterdam op gezag van de Rector Magnificus prof. dr. ir. K.I.J. Maex ten overstaan van een door het College voor Promoties ingestelde commissie, in het openbaar te verdedigen op woensdag 17 juni 2020, te 13 uur door Dieuwke Hupkes geboren te Wageningen Promotiecommisie Promotores: Dr. W.H. Zuidema Universiteit van Amsterdam Prof. Dr. L.W.M. Bod Universiteit van Amsterdam Overige leden: Dr. A. Bisazza Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Dr. R. Fern´andezRovira Universiteit van Amsterdam Prof. Dr. M. van Lambalgen Universiteit van Amsterdam Prof. Dr. P. Monaghan Lancaster University Prof. Dr. K. Sima'an Universiteit van Amsterdam Faculteit der Natuurwetenschappen, Wiskunde en Informatica to my parents Aukje and Michiel v Contents Acknowledgments xiii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 My original plan . .1 1.2 Neural networks as explanatory models . .2 1.2.1 Architectural similarity . .3 1.2.2 Behavioural similarity .
    [Show full text]
  • The Complexity of Narrow Syntax : Minimalism, Representational
    Erschienen in: Measuring Grammatical Complexity / Frederick J. Newmeyer ... (Hrsg.). - Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2014. - S. 128-147. - ISBN 978-0-19-968530-1 The complexity of narrow syntax: Minimalism, representational economy, and simplest Merge ANDREAS TROTZKE AND JAN-WOUTER ZWART 7.1 Introduction The issue of linguistic complexity has recently received much attention by linguists working within typological-functional frameworks (e.g. Miestamo, Sinnemäki, and Karlsson 2008; Sampson, Gil, and Trudgill 2009). In formal linguistics, the most prominent measure of linguistic complexity is the Chomsky hierarchy of formal languages (Chomsky 1956), including the distinction between a finite-state grammar (FSG) and more complicated types of phrase-structure grammar (PSG). This dis- tinction has played a crucial role in the recent biolinguistic literature on recursive complexity (Sauerland and Trotzke 2011). In this chapter, we consider the question of formal complexity measurement within linguistic minimalism (cf. also Biberauer et al., this volume, chapter 6; Progovac, this volume, chapter 5) and argue that our minimalist approach to complexity of derivations and representations shows simi- larities with that of alternative theoretical perspectives represented in this volume (Culicover, this volume, chapter 8; Jackendoff and Wittenberg, this volume, chapter 4). In particular, we agree that information structure properties should not be encoded in narrow syntax as features triggering movement, suggesting that the relevant information is established at the interfaces. Also, we argue for a minimalist model of grammar in which complexity arises out of the cyclic interaction of subderivations, a model we take to be compatible with Construction Grammar approaches. We claim that this model allows one to revisit the question of the formal complexity of a generative grammar, rephrasing it such that a different answer to the question of formal complexity is forthcoming depending on whether we consider the grammar as a whole, or just narrow syntax.
    [Show full text]
  • What Was Wrong with the Chomsky Hierarchy?
    What Was Wrong with the Chomsky Hierarchy? Makoto Kanazawa Hosei University Chomsky Hierarchy of Formal Languages recursively enumerable context- sensitive context- free regular Enduring impact of Chomsky’s work on theoretical computer science. 15 pages devoted to the Chomsky hierarchy. Hopcroft and Ullman 1979 No mention of the Chomsky hierarchy. 450 INDEX The same with the latest edition of Carmichael, R. D., 444 CNF-formula, 302 Cartesian product, 6, 46 Co-Turing-recognizableHopcroft, language, 209 Motwani, and Ullman (2006). CD-ROM, 349 Cobham, Alan, 444 Certificate, 293 Coefficient, 183 CFG, see Context-free grammar Coin-flip step, 396 CFL, see Context-free language Complement operation, 4 Chaitin, Gregory J., 264 Completed rule, 140 Chandra, Ashok, 444 Complexity class Characteristic sequence, 206 ASPACE(f(n)),410 Checkers, game of, 348 ATIME(t(n)),410 Chernoff bound, 398 BPP,397 Chess, game of, 348 coNL,354 Chinese remainder theorem, 401 coNP,297 Chomsky normal form, 108–111, 158, EXPSPACE,368 198, 291 EXPTIME,336 Chomsky, Noam, 444 IP,417 Church, Alonzo, 3, 183, 255 L,349 Church–Turing thesis, 183–184, 281 NC,430 CIRCUIT-SAT,386 NL,349 Circuit-satisfiability problem, 386 NP,292–298 CIRCUIT-VALUE,432 NPSPACE,336 Circular definition, 65 NSPACE(f(n)),332 Clause, 302 NTIME(f(n)),295 Clique, 28, 296 P,284–291,297–298 CLIQUE,296 PH,414 Sipser 2013Closed under, 45 PSPACE,336 Closure under complementation RP,403 context-free languages, non-, 154 SPACE(f(n)),332 deterministic context-free TIME(f(n)),279 languages, 133 ZPP,439 P,322 Complexity
    [Show full text]
  • Reflection in the Chomsky Hierarchy
    Journal of Automata, Languages and Combinatorics 18 (2013) 1, 53–60 c Otto-von-Guericke-Universit¨at Magdeburg REFLECTION IN THE CHOMSKY HIERARCHY Henk Barendregt Institute of Computing and Information Science, Radboud University, Nijmegen, The Netherlands e-mail: [email protected] Venanzio Capretta School of Computer Science, University of Nottingham, United Kingdom e-mail: [email protected] and Dexter Kozen Computer Science Department, Cornell University, Ithaca, New York 14853, USA e-mail: [email protected] ABSTRACT The class of regular languages can be generated from the regular expressions. These regular expressions, however, do not themselves form a regular language, as can be seen using the pumping lemma. On the other hand, the class of enumerable languages can be enumerated by a universal language that is one of its elements. We say that the enumerable languages are reflexive. In this paper we investigate what other classes of the Chomsky Hierarchy are re- flexive in this sense. To make this precise we require that the decoding function is itself specified by a member of the same class. Could it be that the regular languages are reflexive, by using a different collection of codes? It turns out that this is impossi- ble: the collection of regular languages is not reflexive. Similarly the collections of the context-free, context-sensitive, and computable languages are not reflexive. Therefore the class of enumerable languages is the only reflexive one in the Chomsky Hierarchy. In honor of Roel de Vrijer on the occasion of his sixtieth birthday 1. Introduction Let (Σ∗) be a class of languages over an alphabet Σ.
    [Show full text]
  • Noam Chomsky
    Noam Chomsky “If you’re teaching today what you were teaching five years ago, either the field is dead or you are.” Background ▪ Jewish American born to Ukranian and Belarussian immigrants. ▪ Attended a non-competitive elementary school. ▪ Considered dropping out of UPenn and moving to British Palestine. ▪ Life changed when introduced to linguist Zellig Harris. Contributions to Cognitive Science • Deemed the “father of modern linguistics” • One of the founders of Cognitive Science o Linguistics: Syntactic Structures (1957) o Universal Grammar Theory o Generative Grammar Theory o Minimalist Program o Computer Science: Chomsky Hierarchy o Philosophy: Philosophy of Mind; Philosophy of Language o Psychology: Critical of Behaviorism Transformational Grammar – 1955 Syntactic Structures - 1957 ▪ Made him well-known within the ▪ Big Idea: Given the grammar, linguistics community you should be able to construct various expressions in the ▪ Revolutionized the study of natural language with prior language knowledge. ▪ Describes generative grammars – an explicit statement of what the classes of linguistic expressions in a language are and what kind of structures they have. Universal Grammar Theory ▪ Credited with uncovering ▪ Every sentence has a deep structure universal properties of natural that is mapped onto the surface human languages. structure according to rules. ▪ Key ideas: Humans have an ▪ Language similarities: innate neural capacity for – Deep Structure: Pattern in the mind generating a system of rules. – Surface Structure: Spoken utterances – There is a universal grammar that – Rules: Transformations underlies ALL languages Chomsky Hierarchy ▪ Hierarchy of classes of formal grammars ▪ Focuses on structure of classes and relationship between grammars ▪ Typically used in Computer Science and Linguistics Minimalist Program – 1993 ▪ Program NOT theory ▪ Provides conceptual framework to guide development of linguistic theory.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of the Faculty of Language from a Chomskyan Perspective: Bridging Linguistics and Biology
    doi 10.4436/JASS.91011 JASs Invited Reviews e-pub ahead of print Journal of Anthropological Sciences Vol. 91 (2013), pp. 1-48 The evolution of the Faculty of Language from a Chomskyan perspective: bridging linguistics and biology Víctor M. Longa Area of General Linguistics, Faculty of Philology, University of Santiago de Compostela, 15782 Santiago de Compostela, Spain e-mail: [email protected] Summary - While language was traditionally considered a purely cultural trait, the advent of Noam Chomsky’s Generative Grammar in the second half of the twentieth century dramatically challenged that view. According to that theory, language is an innate feature, part of the human biological endowment. If language is indeed innate, it had to biologically evolve. This review has two main objectives: firstly, it characterizes from a Chomskyan perspective the evolutionary processes by which language could have come into being. Secondly, it proposes a new method for interpreting the archaeological record that radically differs from the usual types of evidence Paleoanthropology has concentrated on when dealing with language evolution: while archaeological remains have usually been regarded from the view of the behavior they could be associated with, the paper will consider archaeological remains from the view of the computational processes and capabilities at work for their production. This computational approach, illustrated with a computational analysis of prehistoric geometric engravings, will be used to challenge the usual generative thinking on language evolution, based on the high specificity of language. The paper argues that the biological machinery of language is neither specifically linguistic nor specifically human, although language itself can still be considered a species-specific innate trait.
    [Show full text]
  • Complexity of Natural Languages
    Complexity of natural languages Computational complexity: the expressive power of (and the resources needed in order to process) classes of languages Linguistic complexity: what makes individual constructions or sentences more difficult to understand This is the dog, that worried the cat, that killed the rat, that ate the malt, that lay in the house that Jack built. This is the malt that the rat that the cat that the dog worried killed ate. The Chomsky hierarchy of languages A hierarchy of classes of languages, viewed as sets of strings, ordered by their “complexity”. The higher the language is in the hierarchy, the more “complex” it is. In particular, the class of languages in one class properly includes the languages in lower classes. There exists a correspondence between the class of languages and the format of phrase-structure rules necessary for generating all its languages. The more restricted the rules are, the lower in the hierarchy the languages they generate are. The Chomsky hierarchy of languages Recursively enumerable languages Context-sensitive languages Context-free languages Regular languages The Chomsky hierarchy of languages Regular (type-3) languages: Grammar: right-linear or left-linear grammars Rule form: A → α where A ∈ V and α ∈ Σ∗ · V ∪ {}. Computational device: finite-state automata The Chomsky hierarchy of languages Context-free (type-2) languages: Grammar: context-free grammars Rule form: A → α where A ∈ V and α ∈ (V ∪ Σ)∗ Computational device: push-down automata The Chomsky hierarchy of languages Context-sensitive
    [Show full text]
  • Representations and Characterizations of Languages in Chomsky Hierarchy by Means of Insertion-Deletion Systems
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by idUS. Depósito de Investigación Universidad de Sevilla Representations and Characterizations of Languages in Chomsky Hierarchy by Means of Insertion-Deletion Systems Gheorghe P˘aun(A,B) Mario J. P´erez-Jim´enez(B,C) Takashi Yokomori(D) (A)Institute of Mathematics of the Romanian Academy PO Box 1-764 – 014700 Bucharest – Romania [email protected], [email protected] (B)Department of Computer Science and Artificial Intelligence Univ. of Sevilla – Avda Reina Mercedes s/n – 41012 Sevilla – Spain [email protected] (D)Department of Mathematics Faculty of Education and Integrated Arts and Sciences Waseda University – 1-6-1 Nishiwaseda – Shinjyuku-ku Tokyo 169-8050 – Japan [email protected] Abstract. Insertion-deletion operations are much investigated in lin- guistics and in DNA computing and several characterizations of Turing computability were obtained in this framework. In this note we contribute to this research direction with a new characterization of this type, as well as with representations of regular and context-free languages, mainly starting from context-free insertion systems of as small as possible complexity. For instance, each recur- sively enumerable language L can be represented in a way similar to the celebrated Chomsky-Sch¨utzenberger representation of context-free lan- guages, i.e., in the form L = h(L(γ) ∩ D), where γ is an insertion system of weight (3, 0) (at most three symbols are inserted in a context of length zero), h is a projection, and D is a Dyck language. A similar represen- tation can be obtained for regular languages, involving insertion systems of weight (2,0) and star languages, as well as for context-free languages – this time using insertion systems of weight (3, 0) and star languages.
    [Show full text]
  • Bounded Languages Described by GF(2)-Grammars
    Bounded languages described by GF(2)-grammars Vladislav Makarov∗ February 17, 2021 Abstract GF(2)-grammars are a recently introduced grammar family that have some un- usual algebraic properties and are closely connected to unambiguous grammars. By using the method of formal power series, we establish strong conditions that are nec- essary for subsets of a∗b∗ and a∗b∗c∗ to be described by some GF(2)-grammar. By further applying the established results, we settle the long-standing open question of proving the inherent ambiguity of the language f anbmc` j n 6= m or m 6= ` g, as well as give a new, purely algebraic, proof of the inherent ambiguity of the language f anbmc` j n = m or m = ` g. Keywords: Formal grammars, finite fields, bounded languages, unambiguous grammars, inherent ambiguity. 1 Introduction GF(2)-grammars, recently introduced by Bakinova et al. [3], and further studied by Makarov and Okhotin [15], are a variant of ordinary context-free grammars, in which the disjunction is replaced by exclusive OR, whereas the classical concatenation is replaced by a new operation called GF(2)-concatenation: K L is the set of all strings with an odd number of partitions into a concatenation of a string in K and a string in L. There are several motivating reasons behind studying GF(2)-grammars. The first of them they are a class of grammars with better algebraic properties, compared to ordinary grammars and similar grammar families, because the underlying boolean semiring logic was replaced by a logic of a field with two elements.
    [Show full text]
  • Calibrating Generative Models: the Probabilistic Chomsky-Schutzenberger¨ Hierarchy∗
    Calibrating Generative Models: The Probabilistic Chomsky-Schutzenberger¨ Hierarchy∗ Thomas F. Icard Stanford University [email protected] December 14, 2019 1 Introduction and Motivation Probabilistic computation enjoys a central place in psychological modeling and theory, ranging in application from perception (Knill and Pouget, 2004; Orban´ et al., 2016), at- tention (Vul et al., 2009), and decision making (Busemeyer and Diederich, 2002; Wilson et al., 2014) to the analysis of memory (Ratcliff, 1978; Abbott et al., 2015), categorization (Nosofsky and Palmeri, 1997; Sanborn et al., 2010), causal inference (Denison et al., 2013), and various aspects of language processing (Chater and Manning, 2006). Indeed, much of cognition and behavior is usefully modeled as stochastic, whether this is ultimately due to indeterminacy at the neural level or at some higher level (see, e.g., Glimcher 2005). Ran- dom behavior may even enhance an agent’s cognitive efficiency (see, e.g., Icard 2019). A probabilistic process can be described in two ways. On one hand we can specify a stochastic procedure, which may only implicitly define a distribution on possible out- puts of the process. Familiar examples include well known classes of generative mod- els such as finite Markov processes and probabilistic automata (Miller, 1952; Paz, 1971), Boltzmann machines (Hinton and Sejnowski, 1983), Bayesian networks (Pearl, 1988), topic models (Griffiths et al., 2007), and probabilistic programming languages (Tenenbaum et al., 2011; Goodman and Tenenbaum, 2016). On the other hand we can specify an analytical ex- pression explicitly describing the distribution over outputs. Both styles of description are commonly employed, and it is natural to ask about the relationship between them.
    [Show full text]
  • Learnability and Language Acquisition
    The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion Expressive power Learnability and Language Acquisition Alexander Clark Department of Computer Science Royal Holloway, University of London Tuesday The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion Outline The data Chomsky hierarchy Swiss German Bottom up Problems Conclusion (Ed Stabler, Greg Kobele, Makoto Kanazawa) The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion Outline The data Chomsky hierarchy Swiss German Bottom up Problems Conclusion More precisely, we observe sounds/gestures. • We don’t observe the meanings, but we are aware of • entailment relations between propositions. (or something similar) The sound/meaning relation is not one-to-one, but there is • a lot of structure. (knowing what was said tells you a lot about the meaning!) The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion What are the linguistic data? We observe sound/meaning pairs. • The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion What are the linguistic data? We observe sound/meaning pairs. • More precisely, we observe sounds/gestures. • We don’t observe the meanings, but we are aware of • entailment relations between propositions. (or something similar) The sound/meaning relation is not one-to-one, but there is • a lot of structure. (knowing what was said tells you a lot about the meaning!) The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion Sound/meaning pairs s5 m5 s4 m4 s3 m3 s2 m2 s1 m1 The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion Structural descriptions Traditional view grammar g SD φ sound/SM meaning/CI The data Chomsky hierarchy Bottom up Problems Conclusion Example Grammar might be a context-free grammar, augmented • with some compositional semantics.
    [Show full text]