Arithmetic of Logic*

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Arithmetic of Logic* ARITHMETIC OF LOGIC* BY E. T. BELL 1. Introduction. This is probably the first attempt to construct an arith- metic for an algebra of the non-numerical genus.f In his classic treatise, An Investigation of the Laws of Thought,J Boole developed the thesis that "Logic (is) • • • a system of processes carried on by the aid of symbols having a definite interpretation, and subject to laws founded on that interpretation alone. But at the same time they exhibit those laws as identical in form with the laws of the general symbols of Algebra, with this simple addition, viz., that the symbols of Logic are further subject to a special law, to which the symbols of quantity as such, are not subject." The special law is what Boole calls the law of duality, x(l—x)=0, or the excluded middle; here the indi- cated multiplication is logical, 1—a: is the supplement of x. Boole showed therefore that abstractly logic is contained in common algebra. Taking rational arithmetic Si ( = the theory of numbers in reference to the positive rational integers 0, 1, 2, 3, • • • , only) and certain parts of the theory of algebraic numbers, particularly the rudiments of Dedekind's theory of ideals and those of Kronecker's modular systems as our guides, we shall see to what extent Boole's algebra of logic may be arithmetized in a precise sense to be defined presently. Although it will be unnecessary to refer explicitly anywhere to the theory of algebraic numbers, it may be mentioned that this theory, which includes rational arithmetic, is a surer guide than the latter in problems of arithmetization. In rational arithmetic the essential abstract structure of the concepts to be extended beyond 0, 1, 2, • • • is often quite ingeniously concealed. This is true, for example, of the G.C.D., L.C.M., and residuation. The theory of ideals, on the other hand, often indicates immediately what transformations by formal equivalence must first be applied to operations or relations of rational arithmetic in order that they shall be significant for sets of elements for which order relations are either irrelevant or meaningless. * Presented to the Society, San Francisco Section, April 2, 1927; received by the editors Novem- ber 29, 1926. t For the meaning of this term, cf. Whitehead, Universal Algebra, p. 29. X London and Cambridge, 1854; reprinted, Chicago, Open Court, 1916, as vol. 2 of Boole's CollectedLogical Works. 597 License or copyright restrictions may apply to redistribution; see https://www.ams.org/journal-terms-of-use 598 E. T. BELL July We shall use a few of the commonest notations of algebraic logic ; thus PdQ for P implies Q; P: = :Q for P, Q, are formally equivalent, viz., Pz>Q. QdP, the dot in the last being the logical and; = signifies definitional identity, except where it occurs in conjunction with mod, when it indicates congruence, as in a=ß mod n; the special notation a\ß, borrowed from the theory of numbers, where a, ß are classes, signifies a contains ß, = each element of ß is in a. To avoid confusion we shall never use "contains" in relation to arith- metic; conflicting conventions in this respect have already introduced exasperating paradoxes of language into the theory of numbers. Small Greek letters a, ß, 7, • • • will always denote classes ; S is the set of classes discussed; the null class is denoted by a, the universal class by e, so that w, e are the zero, unity of the algebra of logic 8. Elements of © will be called elements of 8. Logical (but not arithmetical) addition, multiplication of classes a, ß are indicated as usual by a+ß, aß, and if a is any element of 8, the supplement of a is indicated by an accent, a' (instead of the customary bar which is awkward in monotype). Hence a' is the unique* solution of a-f-a' = e, aa' = w, where a is any given element of 8. We shall assume a given set 6 of classes and we postulate that if a, ß are any elements of (£, then a', a+ß, aß are in (5, and, as before, we refer to elements of S as ele- ments of 8. The letters s, p, l, g denote specific operations upon elements of 8, and they are such that (once for all, without further reference) atß for each of t = s,P, l, g is a uniquely determined element of 8 ; the letters c, d, r denote specific relations such that a t ß for each t = c, d, r is uniquely significant in 8. To assist the memory we remark that s, p, l, g, c, d, r may be read sum, product, least, greatest, congruent, divides, residual, terms to be defined in the arithmetic of logic as opposed to the algebra. The least, greatest here are intended merely to recall classes having with respect to given classes properties abstractly identical with those of the G.C.D., L.C.M. with respect to division in 21; these classes g, I are not necessarily the "most" or the "least" inclusive—the rôles with respect to inclusion may be reversed, and g may be either the most or the least inclusive common class of a set, and similarly for I. Hence we shall not use here the names already familiar in Moore's general analysis. The zero, unity in the arithmetic of classes will always be denoted by f, v. It will avoid possible confusion if we add that (f, v) are not necessarily equal to (a, e) respectively. * For proof of unicity cf. Whitehead, Universal Algebra, p. 36. License or copyright restrictions may apply to redistribution; see https://www.ams.org/journal-terms-of-use 1927] ARITHMETIC OF LOGIC 599 Suppose all the elements, operations and signs of relations, other than the logical constants, are replaced in a set SEof propositions by marks without significance beyond that implied by the assertion of the propositions (which include the postulates of the set). Call the result, C(t), the content of SE. If in C(SE) it be possible to assign interpretations to the marks, giving SE,-, such that SE,-is self-consistent and uniquely significant in terms of the in- terpretation, we shall call SE,-an instance of C(SE). Sets X, (j = l, 2, ■ ■ • ) of propositions having the same content will be called abstractly identical. Our object is to find parts 21,of rational arithmetic 21abstractly identical with parts ?,- of the algebra of classes, hence also with the algebra of relations, and finally with 8. In such a project the following type of invariance under formal equivalence is extremely useful. Let P,- (j = l, 2, ■ ■ • ) be propositions of SEsuch that Pi: ■ :P2. Then the truth-values of Pi oPz, Pz sPi are identical with those of P2 3 Pz, Pz ^Ps- Thus : = : in propositions is abstractly identical with = in common algebra, and in implications a particular proposition may be replaced by any other which is formally equivalent to it. We shall meet several instances of such transformations which are considerably less obvious than the logic which justifies them. The identical transformation of a set of transformations by formal equivalence is that which replaces each proposition of a given set by itself; any set of transformed propositions (including the set transformed by the identical transformation) is called a transform of the original set. Let SE' be a transform of SE,and 21/ a transform of a part 21,-of 21. Then if SE', 21/ are abstractly identical, we shall say that SE is arithmetized with respect to 21,, or simply arithmetized. This kind of arithmetization can be carried much farther for 8 than is done here, but what is given will suffice to show its nature, and it will be evident that at nearly every stage there are alternative ways of proceeding. We shall exhibit arithmetizations of 8 with respect to congruences, the L.C.M., G.C.D., divisibility, primes, and the unique factorization law. Rational arithmetic 21 presupposes the existence of a special ring. In the whole discussion we shall ignore negative numbers, without loss of generality, as the arithmetic (properties of integers as such) which refers to these can always be thrown back to relations between positive integers only, e.g., as done by Kronecker. An abstract ring 3Í is a set © of elements x, y, z, ■ ■ • , u', z', ■ ■ • , and two operations S, P( = addition, multiplication) which may be performed upon any two equal or distinct elements x, y of 3î, in this order, to produce uniquely determined elements xSy, xPy such that the postulates 9Î,-(j=1,2, 3) are satisfied. Elements of © will be called elements of 9Î. License or copyright restrictions may apply to redistribution; see https://www.ams.org/journal-terms-of-use 600 E. T. BELL July 9îi. If x, y are any two elements of 3Î, xSy, xPy are uniquely determined elements of 9î, and ySx = xSy, yPx = xPy. 9Î2. If x, y, z are any three elements of 5R, (xSy)Sz = xS(ySz), (xPy)Pz = xP(yPz), xP(ySz) = (xPy)S(xPz). 5R3. There exist in 3Î two distinct* unique elements, denoted by «', z', and called the unity, zero of 9Î, such that if x is any element of 9Î, xSz' = x, xPu' = x. These may be compared with the first three postulates of Dicksont for a field, of which they are a transcription, except that the unicity of «', z' is here a postulate, not a theorem, also with Wedderburn'sJ for algebraic fields. In each comparison the omissions are to be particularly noticed.
Recommended publications
  • What Is Abstract Algebraic Logic?
    What is Abstract Algebraic Logic? Umberto Rivieccio University of Genoa Department of Philosophy Via Balbi 4 - Genoa, Italy email [email protected] Abstract Our aim is to answer the question of the title, explaining which kind of problems form the nucleus of the branch of algebraic logic that has come to be known as Abstract Algebraic Logic. We give a concise account of the birth and evolution of the field, that led from the discovery of the connections between certain logical systems and certain algebraic structures to a general theory of algebraization of logics. We consider first the so-called algebraizable logics, which may be regarded as a paradigmatic case in Abstract Algebraic Logic; then we shift our attention to some wider classes of logics and to the more general framework in which they are studied. Finally, we review some other topics in Abstract Algebraic Logic that, though equally interesting and promising for future research, could not be treated here in detail. 1 Introduction Algebraic logic can be described in very general terms as the study of the relations between algebra and logic. One of the main reasons that motivate such a study is the possibility to treat logical problems with algebraic methods. This means that, in order to solve a logical problem, we may try to translate it into algebraic terms, find the solution using algebraic techniques, and then translate back the result into logic. This strategy proved to be fruitful, since algebra is an old and well{established field of mathematics, that offers powerful tools to treat problems that would possibly be much harder to solve using the logical machinery alone.
    [Show full text]
  • Explanations
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. CHAPTER 1 Explanations 1.1 SALLIES Language is an instrument of Logic, but not an indispensable instrument. Boole 1847a, 118 We know that mathematicians care no more for logic than logicians for mathematics. The two eyes of exact science are mathematics and logic; the mathematical sect puts out the logical eye, the logical sect puts out the mathematical eye; each believing that it sees better with one eye than with two. De Morgan 1868a,71 That which is provable, ought not to be believed in science without proof. Dedekind 1888a, preface If I compare arithmetic with a tree that unfolds upwards in a multitude of techniques and theorems whilst the root drives into the depthswx . Frege 1893a, xiii Arithmetic must be discovered in just the same sense in which Columbus discovered the West Indies, and we no more create numbers than he created the Indians. Russell 1903a, 451 1.2 SCOPE AND LIMITS OF THE BOOK 1.2.1 An outline history. The story told here from §3 onwards is re- garded as well known. It begins with the emergence of set theory in the 1870s under the inspiration of Georg Cantor, and the contemporary development of mathematical logic by Gottlob Frege andŽ. especially Giuseppe Peano. A cumulation of these and some related movements was achieved in the 1900s with the philosophy of mathematics proposed by Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell.
    [Show full text]
  • How Peircean Was the “'Fregean' Revolution” in Logic?
    HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? Irving H. Anellis Peirce Edition, Institute for American Thought Indiana University – Purdue University at Indianapolis Indianapolis, IN, USA [email protected] Abstract. The historiography of logic conceives of a Fregean revolution in which modern mathematical logic (also called symbolic logic) has replaced Aristotelian logic. The preeminent expositors of this conception are Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) and Don- ald Angus Gillies. The innovations and characteristics that comprise mathematical logic and distinguish it from Aristotelian logic, according to this conception, created ex nihlo by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) in his Begriffsschrift of 1879, and with Bertrand Rus- sell (1872–1970) as its chief This position likewise understands the algebraic logic of Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), Charles Sanders Peirce (1838–1914), and Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) as belonging to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. The “Booleans” are understood, from this vantage point, to merely have rewritten Aristotelian syllogistic in algebraic guise. The most detailed listing and elaboration of Frege’s innovations, and the characteristics that distinguish mathematical logic from Aristotelian logic, were set forth by van Heijenoort. I consider each of the elements of van Heijenoort’s list and note the extent to which Peirce had also developed each of these aspects of logic. I also consider the extent to which Peirce and Frege were aware of, and may have influenced, one another’s logical writings. AMS (MOS) 2010 subject classifications: Primary: 03-03, 03A05, 03C05, 03C10, 03G27, 01A55; secondary: 03B05, 03B10, 03E30, 08A20; Key words and phrases: Peirce, abstract algebraic logic; propositional logic; first-order logic; quantifier elimina- tion, equational classes, relational systems §0.
    [Show full text]
  • Abstract Algebraic Logic an Introductory Chapter
    Abstract Algebraic Logic An Introductory Chapter Josep Maria Font 1 Introduction . 1 2 Some preliminary issues . 5 3 Bare algebraizability . 10 3.1 The equational consequence relative to a class of algebras . 11 3.2 Translating formulas into equations . 13 3.3 Translating equations into formulas . 15 3.4 Putting it all together . 15 4 The origins of algebraizability: the Lindenbaum-Tarski process . 18 4.1 The process for classical logic . 18 4.2 The process for algebraizable logics . 20 4.3 The universal Lindenbaum-Tarski process: matrix semantics . 23 4.4 Algebraizability and matrix semantics: definability . 27 4.5 Implicative logics . 29 5 Modes of algebraizability, and non-algebraizability . 32 6 Beyond algebraizability . 37 6.1 The Leibniz hierarchy . 37 6.2 The general definition of the algebraic counterpart of a logic . 45 6.3 The Frege hierarchy . 49 7 Exploiting algebraizability: bridge theorems and transfer theorems . 55 8 Algebraizability at a more abstract level . 65 References . 69 1 Introduction This chapter has been conceived as a brief introduction to (my personal view of) abstract algebraic logic. It is organized around the central notion of algebraizabil- ity, with particular emphasis on its connections with the techniques of traditional algebraic logic and especially with the so-called Lindenbaum-Tarski process. It Josep Maria Font Departament of Mathematics and Computer Engineering, Universitat de Barcelona (UB), Gran Via de les Corts Catalanes 585, E-08007 Barcelona, Spain. e-mail: [email protected] 1 2 Josep Maria Font goes beyond algebraizability to offer a general overview of several classifications of (sentential) logics—basically, the Leibniz hierarchy and the Frege hierarchy— which have emerged in recent decades, and to show how the classification of a logic into any of them provides some knowledge regarding its algebraic or its metalogical properties.
    [Show full text]
  • Algebraic Logic, Where Does It Stand Today? Part 2: Algebraic Logic; Counting Varieties and Models, Vaught’S Conjecture and New Physics
    1 What happened since ’ Algebraic Logic, where does it stand today? Part 2: Algebraic logic; Counting varieties and models, Vaught’s conjecture and new physics Tarek Sayed Ahmed Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science, Cairo University, Giza, Egypt. Dedicated to my mentors Andreka´ and Nemeti´ No Institute Given Summary. * In the article ’Algebraic logic, where does it stand today?’ published in the Bulletin of Symbolic logic in 2005 logic, we gave a fairly comprehensive review of Tarskian algebraic logic reaching the boundaries of current research back then. In this paper we take it from there, giving the reader more than a glimpse of the recent develoments till the present day. In the process, we take a magical tour in algebraic logic, starting from classical results on neat embeddings due to Henkin, Monk and Tarski, all the way to recent results in algebraic logic using so–called rainbow constructions. Highlighting the connections with graph theory, model theory, and finite combinatorics, this article aspires to present topics of broad interest in a way that is hopefully accessible to a large audience. Other topics dealt with include the inter- action of algebraic and modal logic, the so–called (central still active) finitizability problem, Godels’s¨ incompleteness Theorem in guarded fragments, counting the number of subvarieties of RCAw which is reminiscent of Shelah’s stability theory and the interaction of algebraic logic and descriptive set theory as means to approach Vaught’s conjecture in model theory. Rainbow constructions conjuncted with variations on Andreka’s´ methods of splitting (atoms) are used to solve problems adressing classes of cylindric–like algebras consisting of algebras having a neat embedding property.
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Logic and the Geography of Thought – Reflections on Logical
    Universal Logic and the Geography of Thought – Reflections on logical pluralism in the light of culture Tzu-Keng Fu Dissertation zur Erlangung des Grades eines Doktors der Ingenieurwissenschaften –Dr.-Ing.– Vorgelegt im Fachbereich 3 (Mathematik und Informatik) der Universit¨at Bremen Bremen, Dezember, 2012 PhD Committee Supervisor: Dr. Oliver Kutz (Spatial Cognition Re- search Center (SFB/TR 8), University of Bremen, Germany) External Referee : Prof. Dr. Jean-Yves B´eziau (Depart- ment of Philosophy, University of Rio de Janeiro, Brazil) Committee Member : Prof. Dr. Till Mossakowski (German re- search center for artificial intelligence (DFKI), Germany) Committee Member : Prof. Dr. Frieder Nake (Fachbereich 3, Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics, the University of Bremen, Germany) Committee Member : Dr. Mehul Bhatt (Cognitive Systems (CoSy) group, Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics, University of Bremen, Germany) Committee Member : Minqian Huang (Cognitive Systems (CoSy) group, Faculty of Mathematics and Informatics, University of Bremen, Germany) Sponsoring Institution The Chiang Ching-kuo Foundation for International Scholarly Exchange, Taipei, Taiwan. To my Parents. 獻給我的 父母。 Acknowledgment I owe many thanks to many people for their help and encouragement, without which I may never have finished this dissertation, and their constructive criticism, without which I would certainly have finished too soon. I would like to thank Dr. Oliver Kutz, Prof. Dr. Till Mossakowski, and Prof. Dr. Jean- Yves B´eziau for assisting me with this dissertation. Warmest and sincere thanks are also due to Prof. Dale Jacquette of the Philosophy Department, the University of Bern, Switzerland, and to Prof. Dr. Stephen Bloom of the Computer Science Department, Stevens Institute of Technology, Hoboken, New Jersey, USA, who provided me with valuable original typescripts on abstract logic.
    [Show full text]
  • In Quantum Logics. an Algebraic Approach
    Model-Theoretic Investigations into Consequence Operation ( Cn ) in Quantum Logics. An Algebraic Approach. Piotr Wilczek, Department of Algebra and Combinatorics, Warsaw University of Technology, Address for correspondence: os. Piastowskie 99/ 24, 61-163 Pozna, POLAND, e-mail [email protected] Abstract In this paper we present the fundamentals of the so-called algebraic approach to propositional quantum logics. We define the set of formulas describing quantum reality as a free algebra freely generated by the set of quantum propostional variables. We define the general notion of logic as a structural consequence operation. Next we introduce the concept of logical matrices understood as a models of quantum logics. We give the definitions of two quantum consequence operations defined in these models. Key words: algebraic logic; consequence operation; logical matrices; models of qunatum logics 1. Introduction Historically speaking we can distinguish two different and competitive ways of understanding of the concept of “logic”. An approach considering the logic as a set of logically valid sentences was the first manner of understanding logic. In this approach one can perceive a logical system as a set of sentences closed under substitutions and some rules of inference. A paradigmatic example is a set of tautologies of classical propositional calculus. Second and more general approach enables one to comprehend a logic as a logical consequence operation (or relation). This approach formalizes the most general principles of reasoning and not a set of logically valid sentences. Following the second approach one will uniquely obtain a set of logically valid sentences as a set of consequences of an empty set of premises.
    [Show full text]
  • Algebraic Logic and Topoi; a Philosophical Holistic Approach
    International Journal of Algebra, Vol. 14, 2020, no. 2, 43 - 137 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com https://doi.org/10.12988/ija.2020.91249 Algebraic Logic and Topoi; a Philosophical Holistic Approach Tarek Sayed Ahmed Department of Mathematics, Faculty of Science Cairo University, Giza, Egypt This article is distributed under the Creative Commons by-nc-nd Attribution License. Copyright c 2020 Hikari Ltd. Abstract We take a magical tour in algebraic logic and its most novel applica- tions. In algebraic logic we start from classical results on neat embed- dings due to Andreka,´ Henkin, N´emeti, Monk and Tarski, all the way to recent results in algebraic logic using so{called rainbow construc- tions. Highlighting the connections with graph theory, model theory, finite combinatorics, and in the last decade with the theory of general relativity and hypercomputation, this article aspires to present topics of broad interest in a way that is hopefully accessible to a large audience. Other topics deallt with include the interaction of algebraic and modal logic, the so{called (central still active) finitizability problem, G¨odels's incompleteness Theorem in guarded fragments, counting the number of subvarieties of RCA! which is reminiscent of Shelah's stability theory and the interaction of algebraic logic and descriptive set theory as means to approach Vaught's conjecture in model theory. The interconections between algebraic geometry and cylindric algebra theory is surveyed and elaborated upon as a Sheaf theoretc duality. This article is not purely expository; far from it. It contains new results and new approaches to old paradigms. Furthermore, various scattered results in the literature are presented from a holistic perspective highlighting similarities be- tween seemingly remote areas in the literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on Logic, Language and Signs: a Bibliography (A- K)
    Leibniz on Logic, Language and Signs: a Bibliography (A- K) https://www.historyoflogic.com/biblio/leibniz-logic-biblio-one.htm History of Logic from Aristotle to Gödel by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Leibniz on Logic, Language and Semiotics. Annotated bibliography (First Part: A - K) BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. Aarsleff, Hans. 1964. "Leibniz on Locke on Language." American Philosophical Quarterly no. 1:165-188. Reprinted in: H. Aarsleff - From Locke to Saussure. Essays on the study of language and intellectual history - London, Athlone Press, 1982 pp. 42-83 and in: R. S. Woolhouse - Leibniz. Critical assessments - Vol. III - New York, Routledge, 1994, pp. 452-495 2. ———. 1975. "The Eighteenth Century Including Leibniz." In Current Trends in Linguistics, edited by Sebeok, Thomas A., 383-479. The Hague: Mouton. 3. Abraham, William E. 1969. "Complete Concepts and Leibniz's Distinction between Necessary and Contingent Propositions." Studia Leibnitiana no. 1:263-279. 4. Aguado, Javier. 1997. "Analisis De Las Relaciones En La Gramatica Logica De Leibniz. Historia De Un Conflicto Hermeneutico." Revista de Filosofia (Spain) no. 10:223-263. 5. Andrews, F.E. 1983. "Leibniz's Logic within His Philosophical System." Dionysius no. 7:73-128. "The work purports to provide a philosophical history of Leibniz's logical works. The principal conclusion is that Leibniz's work on logical calculi, the modifications in it coinciding with the three periods identified by Couturat, rest upon refinements in the expression of his philosophical system, and end when his philosophical thought reached that point at which it is manifest that a logical calculus such as he had envisaged is not competent to his philosophical standpoint." 6.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Was One of the Most Prolific Thinkers
    Chapter 1: Introduction “Theoria cum praxi [Theory with practice]”—Leibniz’s motto for the Berlin Society of Sciences. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was one of the most prolific thinkers of all time. “Often in the morning when I am still in bed,” he wrote, “so many thoughts occur to me in a single hour that sometimes it takes me a whole day or more to write them out” (LH 338; quoted from Mates 1986, 34). These thoughts might have included designs for a new wind pump to drain the mines of the Harz mountains or for a calculating machine based on binary arithmetic, sketches for a treatise on geology or etymology, another draft of a logical calculus that was two hundred years ahead of its time, or a new derivation of Newton’s law of gravitation on strictly mechanical principles. Even before getting up, Leibniz would usually have written lengthy letters on such subjects to one or two learned correspondents, and perhaps a proposal to Peter the Great for a scientific academy, or to his employer the Duke of Hanover for a universally accessible state medical system. He might have penned a legal brief in support of the Duke’s electoral claim to certain territories, a deposition aimed at church reunification, or tried to mediate in the dispute among the Jesuits over the interpretation of Chinese religious rites. In short, Leibniz was an indefatigable one-man industry. Yet all this worldly activity seems at odds with the usual understanding of Leibniz as a philosopher. He is well known for his claim that the world is constituted by what he calls monads (or unities), which he characterizes as substances consisting in perceptions (representations of the whole of the rest of the universe) and appetitions (tendencies toward future states), governed by a law specific to each individual.
    [Show full text]
  • Propositional Logics and Their Algebraic Equivalents
    Propositional Logics and their Algebraic Equivalents Kyle Brooks April 18, 2012 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Formal Logic Systems 1 2.1 Consequence Relations . 2 3 Propositional Logic Systems 3 3.1 The axiomatic approach to proof . 3 4 The Algebraic Structure of Logic Systems 4 4.1 Boolean Algebra . 7 4.2 Heyting Algebras . 8 5 Closing Remarks 9 1 Introduction This paper is meant as an introduction to the study of logic for undergraduate mathematicians having completed a year-long course in abstract algebra. It is possible to investigate a logic as an algebraic structure, the properties of that structure giving insight in to the logic itself. We will discuss that connection between Boolean algebras and the system of classical propositional logic. We will also introduce the idea of different logical systems, and investigate their algebraic equivalents as well. 1 2 Formal Logic Systems Before we can discuss the algebraic representations of formal logics, we must first define the semantics and syntax of a formal logic system. Definition 2.1. A formal logic system S is comprised of the following objects: 1. A language L, which is generated by: (a) A finite set of symbols; sequences of these symbols are called words. (b) A set of formulas, which are special cases of words. (c) A set of rules for creating formulas called the syntax of L. 2. A deductive system H, which consists of: (a) A set of formulas called the axioms of H. (b) A set of rules called the rules of inference on S. These rules along with the axioms are used to generate new formulas, which are called the theorems of S.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiomatic Method and Ernst Schröder's Algebraic Approach to Logic
    PHILOSOPHIA SCIENTIÆ VOLKER PECKHAUS The axiomatic method and Ernst Schröder’s algebraic approach to logic Philosophia Scientiæ, tome 1, no 3 (1996), p. 1-15 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=PHSC_1996__1_3_1_0> © Éditions Kimé, 1996, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Philosophia Scientiæ » (http://poincare.univ-nancy2.fr/PhilosophiaScientiae/) implique l’accord avec les conditions générales d’utilisation (http://www. numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisation commerciale ou im- pression systématique est constitutive d’une infraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit contenir la pré- sente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ The Àxiomatic Method and Ernst Schrôder's Algebraic Àpproach to Logic Volker Peckhaus Universitàt Erlangen-Nurnberg Institut fur Philosophie Philosophia Scientiœ, 1 (3), 1996, 1-15. Volker Peckhaus Abstract. Poincaré* s scepticism towards attempts to found geometry axiomatically, i.e. on self-evident truths which are in no need resp. incapable of proof, can be seen as the symptom of an epistemological crisis of traditional axiomatics. This crisis is illustrated by discussing the various attempts of Ernst Schrôder (1841-1902) to found his abstract algebra and his algebra of logic on 'axioms'. In the course of his studies the terminological inexactness brought Schrôder to abandon the notion of 'axiom' from his theory. In the last stage of development he founded his algebra and logic of binary relatives on a set of 29 'conventional stipulations*. In Schrôder's opinion, however, geometry neededreal axioms, contrary to logic and arithmetic. In his architecture of science geometry is more than a mère branch of logic but the most elementary member in the séries of physical sciences.
    [Show full text]