Perception and Persuasion in Legal Argumentation: Using Informal Fallacies and Cognitive Biases to Win the War of Words Cory S

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Perception and Persuasion in Legal Argumentation: Using Informal Fallacies and Cognitive Biases to Win the War of Words Cory S BYU Law Review Volume 2013 | Issue 2 Article 3 5-1-2013 Perception and Persuasion in Legal Argumentation: Using Informal Fallacies and Cognitive Biases to Win the War of Words Cory S. Clements Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/lawreview Part of the Litigation Commons Recommended Citation Cory S. Clements, Perception and Persuasion in Legal Argumentation: Using Informal Fallacies and Cognitive Biases to Win the War of Words, 2013 BYU L. Rev. 319 (2013). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/lawreview/vol2013/iss2/3 This Comment is brought to you for free and open access by the Brigham Young University Law Review at BYU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in BYU Law Review by an authorized editor of BYU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Perception and Persuasion in Legal Argumentation: Using Informal Fallacies and Cognitive Biases to Win the War of Words CONTENTS I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................ 320 II. KEY CONCEPTS AND HISTORICAL BACKGROUND ............... 325 A. Perception and Persuasion .................................................... 325 1. Perception ...................................................................... 325 2. Persuasion ..................................................................... 327 3. The interaction between perception and persuasion ............. 330 B. Informal Fallacies and Cognitive Biases ................................. 331 1. Informal fallacies ........................................................... 331 2. Cognitive biases ............................................................. 334 3. The connection between informal fallacies and cognitive biases ............................................................................ 336 C. Background and Context: Sophists, Philosophers, and Lawyers 33 7 III. EYEWITNESS TESTIMONY, WRONGFUL CONVICTION, AND THE COURTS ................. ············································· 341 A. Cognitive Psychologists and Legal Scholars on Eyewitness Testimony .......................................................................... 341 B. Courts' Limited Role in Excluding Unreliable Testimony ......... 343 1. Excluding opinion that lacks a rational connection to actual perception ............................................................ 343 2. Excluding unreliable identifications due to suggestive circumstances ................................................................ 344 IV. CONNECTING THE LINKS BETWEEN SPECIFIC INFORMAL FALLACIES AND SPECIFIC COGNITIVE BIASES ................ 349 A. Fallacy ofIrrelevant Thesis and Bounded Awareness ............... 349 B. Fallacy of Exclusion and Confirmation Bias ........................... 352 C. Fallacy of Style over Substance and the Framing Effect ............ 354 D. Fallacy of Emotive or Loaded Language and Suggestibility ....... 355 E. Poisoning the Well, the Straw Man, and Cognitive Dissonance 357 v. CONCLUSION·································································· 360 319 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW 2013 I. INTRODUCTION When zealously advocating a client's position, the lawyer's ulti­ mate goal is winning. To win, however, the lawyer must convince a judge or jury to accept the lawyer's (and reject opposing counsel's) position. The best type of advocate accomplishes this goal using var­ ious rhetorical techniques, attempting to manage other people's per­ ceptions of such things as the facts, the lawyer's own theory of the case, the credibility of eyewitness testimony, the weaknesses of op­ posing counsel's claims, and the praiseworthiness of the lawyer's own client. By design, we have an adversary system. Roberto Aron and his colleagues characterize litigation quite deftly. Litigation is not a philosophical discussion. Trial advocacy is always controversial. A trial is a judicial contest between lawyers where a given situation and set of facts are interpreted in various ways by the different parties' lawyers, each counsel trying to persuade the judge or jury that justice is on the side of the client for whom coun­ sel is arguing. 1 But how does the lawyer successfully convince the fact finder that the lawyer's (and not opposing counsel's) position is aligned with justice? Success inevitably boils down to persuasive legal argu­ mentation.2 This is because "the advocate's [only] weapons in the courtroom battle are methods, tactics, and strategies, all of which have in common the ultimate goal of persuasion." 3 When lawyers do battle in the courtroom, whichever warrior wages war while wisely wielding wittier words without waning will win. Thus, if the lawyer's ultimate goal is winning, the lawyer must master the art of persua­ sion. For the art of persuasion4 is intimately connected with the psy- l. See ROBERTO ARON ET AL., TRIAL COMMUNICATION SKILLS§ 1.14 (2d ed. 2011). 2. BRYAN A. GARNER, GARNER'S DICTIONARY OF LEGAL USAGE 672 (3d ed. 2011) (defining argumentation as "the art of logically setting forth premises and drawing conclusions from them"). 3. ARON ET AL., supra note 1 (emphasis added). 4. RONALD WAICUKAUSKI, PAUL MARK SANDLER & jOANNE EPPS, THE 12 SECRETS OF PERSUASIVE ARGUMENT, at v (2009) ("The art of persuasion is at the heart of the successful ad­ vocate's skill set.... The essence that the great advocate adds to fact and law is an assessment of their implications for her client's case, and an understanding of the way that the facts and law support her overall rationale. It is equally important to explain and refute the opposing facts and law. That approach is essential to being an effective lawyer-advocate and to the art of persua- 320 319 Perception and Persuasion in Legal Argumentation chological process of perception. And perception is what convinces people whether to accept or reject the lawyer's argument. In this Comment, I propose an account of legal argumentation that explains the relationship between mental processes that psy­ chologists label cognitive biases 5 and legal arguments that philoso­ phers label informal fallacies. 6 Cognitive biases are errors in our thinking and reasoning, which alter our perceptions. Informal fal­ lacies are verbal or written arguments containing material flaws, which enhance their persuasiveness. 7 I also describe the process of persuasion at play when the lawyer uses legal arguments that con­ tain informal (material) fallacies. By using legal arguments that con­ tain informal fallacies, the lawyer can play upon the listener's inher­ ent cognitive biases to persuade the listener to see things the same way the lawyer does. When lawyers use these rhetorical tech­ niques-whether before or during trial proceedings-they induce8 in most listeners erroneous perceptions that can, and often do, power­ fully alter their listeners' beliefs. sian."). 5. Cognitive bias generally describes numerous "observer effects" in the mind, which are "desires and expectations people possess [that] influence their perceptions and interpretations of what they observe." D. Michael Risinger et al., The Daubert/Kumho Implications of Observer Effects in Forensic Science: Hidden Problems of Expectation and Suggestion, 90 CALIF. L. REV. I, 6 (2002). 6. Throughout this Comment, I predominantly use the term informal fallacy instead of the three-extra-syllable term informal logical fallacy. In legal circles, informal fallacies might also be familiarly known as "material fallacies." E.g., Hernandez v. Denton, 861 F.2d 1421, 1439 (9th Cir. 1988) (Aldisert, )., concurring and dissenting) ("The arguments contain material fallacies, that is, errors or evasions that appear only through an analysis of the meaning of the terms, ra­ ther than an analysis of the logical form." (emphasis added)), vacated, 493 U.S. 801 (1989); see also RUGGEROj. ALDISERT, THE jUDICIAL PROCESS 635-44 (1976). 7. See RUGGERO]. ALDISERT, LOGIC FOR LAWYERS: A GUIDE TO CLEAR LEGAL THINKING 141 (3d ed. 1997). Judge Aldisert defines informal (material) fallacies as follows: An informal fallacy is one that cannot be detected merely by examining the form of the argument but must be detected in some other way. It is any other argument that does not properly establish the supported conclusion. An argument contains an in­ formal fallacy when at least one of its premises is not true, or when the rules of infer­ ence are not properly respected. I d. 8. W AICUKAUSKI ET AL., supra note 4, at 1 ("As a lawyer, your goal is to make the argu­ ment that not merely impresses but ... induces the desired action. Everything you say or do in making an argument should be determined on the basis of whether it will help to induce the de­ sired outcome." (emphasis added)). 321 BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY LAW REVIEW 2013 I also analyze specific informal fallacies and specific cognitive bi­ ases as well as their potential to improve or undermine the legal sys­ tem. I focus on cognitive biases that affect how we understand, wit­ ness, remember, and investigate things in our world. I also concen­ concentrate on informal fallacies of presumption, 9 which argue from unwarranted assumptions and fail to establish their conclusion. By analyzing the relationship between several cognitive biases and in­ formal fallacies, I hope to show how both types of errors influence the reliability of eyewitness testimony. My first general purpose is to explain what lawyers and judges can learn from psychologists' and philosophers' insights on legal ar­ gumentation.10
Recommended publications
  • Argumentation and Fallacies in Creationist Writings Against Evolutionary Theory Petteri Nieminen1,2* and Anne-Mari Mustonen1
    Nieminen and Mustonen Evolution: Education and Outreach 2014, 7:11 http://www.evolution-outreach.com/content/7/1/11 RESEARCH ARTICLE Open Access Argumentation and fallacies in creationist writings against evolutionary theory Petteri Nieminen1,2* and Anne-Mari Mustonen1 Abstract Background: The creationist–evolutionist conflict is perhaps the most significant example of a debate about a well-supported scientific theory not readily accepted by the public. Methods: We analyzed creationist texts according to type (young earth creationism, old earth creationism or intelligent design) and context (with or without discussion of “scientific” data). Results: The analysis revealed numerous fallacies including the direct ad hominem—portraying evolutionists as racists, unreliable or gullible—and the indirect ad hominem, where evolutionists are accused of breaking the rules of debate that they themselves have dictated. Poisoning the well fallacy stated that evolutionists would not consider supernatural explanations in any situation due to their pre-existing refusal of theism. Appeals to consequences and guilt by association linked evolutionary theory to atrocities, and slippery slopes to abortion, euthanasia and genocide. False dilemmas, hasty generalizations and straw man fallacies were also common. The prevalence of these fallacies was equal in young earth creationism and intelligent design/old earth creationism. The direct and indirect ad hominem were also prevalent in pro-evolutionary texts. Conclusions: While the fallacious arguments are irrelevant when discussing evolutionary theory from the scientific point of view, they can be effective for the reception of creationist claims, especially if the audience has biases. Thus, the recognition of these fallacies and their dismissal as irrelevant should be accompanied by attempts to avoid counter-fallacies and by the recognition of the context, in which the fallacies are presented.
    [Show full text]
  • There Is No Fallacy of Arguing from Authority
    There is no Fallacy ofArguing from Authority EDWIN COLEMAN University ofMelbourne Keywords: fallacy, argument, authority, speech act. Abstract: I argue that there is no fallacy of argument from authority. I first show the weakness of the case for there being such a fallacy: text-book presentations are confused, alleged examples are not genuinely exemplary, reasons given for its alleged fallaciousness are not convincing. Then I analyse arguing from authority as a complex speech act. R~iecting the popular but unjustified category of the "part-time fallacy", I show that bad arguments which appeal to authority are defective through breach of some felicity condition on argument as a speech act, not through employing a bad principle of inference. 1. Introduction/Summary There's never been a satisfactory theory of fallacy, as Hamblin pointed out in his book of 1970, in what is still the least unsatisfactory discussion. Things have not much improved in the last 25 years, despite fallacies getting more attention as interest in informal logic has grown. We still lack good answers to simple questions like what is a fallacy?, what fallacies are there? and how should we classifY fallacies? The idea that argument from authority (argumentum ad verecundiam) is a fallacy, is well-established in logical tradition. I argue that it is no such thing. The second main part of the paper is negative: I show the weakness of the case made in the literature for there being such a fallacy as argument from authority. First, text-book presentation of the fallacy is confused, second, the examples given are not genuinely exemplary and third, reasons given for its alleged fallaciousness are not convincing.
    [Show full text]
  • Common Reasoning Mistakes
    Common Fallacies (mistakes of reasoning) The fallacy fallacy • There is danger even in the study of fallacies. This study involves identifying certain patterns of reasoning as fallacies. Each pattern has a name. E.g. an argument that attacks a person is ad hominem. But ad hominem arguments are not always fallacies! • Rejecting an argument as a (named) fallacy, based on its pattern alone, is a fallacy that we might call the fallacy fallacy. • In general, an ad hominem is only legitimate when attacking an argument from authority. • But not all such attacks on authority are legitimate. They can be made on irrelevant grounds. Irrelevant ad hominem E.g. Einstein’s physics was attacked on the basis of Einstein being Jewish. Thomas Powers, Heisenberg’s War, p. 41 Fallacy? • Alliance leader Stockwell Day argues that Canada should increase its military expenditure now, by at least 20%, in order to continue to meet our NATO obligations five years from now. But Day is a fundamentalist who thinks the universe is only 6,000 years old! Clearly his view can be dismissed. • Mr. Wilson, in his letter of January 16, argues that it would be counter-productive to yield to the demands of the hostage takers. He does not, I take it, have a son or daughter among the hostages. As such a parent, I am repelled by his callous attitude. My daughter could well be the next innocent victim of these terrorists, but Wilson apparently doesn’t give a damn about this. 1. Comment on the following ad hominem (to the person) arguments, explaining why they are, or are not, reasonable.
    [Show full text]
  • Explicit Examples of Logical Fallacies in Love Is a Fallacy by Max Shulman Foundations – Part of the Easy Peasy All-In-One Homeschool
    Explicit examples of logical fallacies in Love is a Fallacy by Max Shulman Foundations – Part of the Easy Peasy All-in-One Homeschool A dicto simpliciter ("an argument based on an unqualified generalization") - the example given in the story is: Exercise is good. Therefore everybody should exercise. Hasty generalization (or "fallacy of insufficient sample") - example given in the story is “You can speak French, I can't speak French, Petey Burch can't speak French. I must therefore conclude that nobody at the University of Minnesota can speak French.” If most of the people the author (Dobie Gillis) knows cannot speak French he concludes that no one at the college can speak French. OR "My dear," I said, favoring her with a smile, "we have now spent five evenings together. We have gotten along, splendidly. It is clear that we are well matched." Post hoc ergo propter hoc ("after it, therefore because of it", or "confusing coincidental relationships with cause") - from the story: “Let's not take Bill on our picnic. Every time we take him out with us, it rains.” Contradictory Premises ("self-contradiction") - from the story: I do not see the contradictory premise in this story. The main contradiction would be that the author (Dobie Gillis) begins the story believing that love is logical and can be won through logic. However, the end of the story proves that love is not logical and Dobie’s original belief was a fallacy. Ad Misericordiam ("appeal to pity") - example given in the story: "A man applies for a job. When the boss asks him what his qualifications are, he replies the he has wife and six children at home, the wife is a helpless cripple, the children have nothing to eat, no clothes to wear, no shoes on their feet, there are no beds in the house, no coal in the cellar, and winter is coming." OR “Polly, I love you.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Review All While Still Others Are Characterized Inadequately Or Incompletely
    12 Some should not be classified as fallacies of relevance at critical review all while still others are characterized inadequately or incompletely. Copi maintains that in all fallacies of rele­ vance "their premisses are logically irrelevant to, and therefore incapable of establishing the truth of their conclusions" (pp. 9S-99). But this definition does not apply to the most important of the fallacies of relevance, the irrelevant conclusion (ignoratio elenchi). According to Copi, this fallacy is committed "when an argument sup­ Copi's Sixth Edition posedly intended to establish a particular conclusion is directed to proving a different conclusion" (p. 110). Copi even allows that the fallacy can be committed by one who may" succeed in proving his (irrelevant) conclusion" (my italics). The fault then is not that the premisses of such Ronald Roblin arguments are logically irrelevant to the conclusion drawn State University College at Buffalo from them, but that the conclusion drawn is insufficient to justify the conclusion called for by the context. If a prosecutor, purporting to prove the defendant guilty of murder, shows on Iy that he had sufficient opportunity and Copi, Irving. Introduction to l~gic. 6th edition. New motive to commit the crime, he (the prosecutor) commits York: Macmillan, 19S2. x. 604 pp.ISBN o-02-324920-X the fallacy of insufficient conclusion. If, on the other hand, he succeeds only in "proving" that murder is a horrible crime, he is guilty of an ignoratio elenchi. In effect, then, The sixth edition of this widely used and influential text Copi does not distinguish between two different fal­ is worth reviewing, first.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantifying Aristotle's Fallacies
    mathematics Article Quantifying Aristotle’s Fallacies Evangelos Athanassopoulos 1,* and Michael Gr. Voskoglou 2 1 Independent Researcher, Giannakopoulou 39, 27300 Gastouni, Greece 2 Department of Applied Mathematics, Graduate Technological Educational Institute of Western Greece, 22334 Patras, Greece; [email protected] or [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 20 July 2020; Accepted: 18 August 2020; Published: 21 August 2020 Abstract: Fallacies are logically false statements which are often considered to be true. In the “Sophistical Refutations”, the last of his six works on Logic, Aristotle identified the first thirteen of today’s many known fallacies and divided them into linguistic and non-linguistic ones. A serious problem with fallacies is that, due to their bivalent texture, they can under certain conditions disorient the nonexpert. It is, therefore, very useful to quantify each fallacy by determining the “gravity” of its consequences. This is the target of the present work, where for historical and practical reasons—the fallacies are too many to deal with all of them—our attention is restricted to Aristotle’s fallacies only. However, the tools (Probability, Statistics and Fuzzy Logic) and the methods that we use for quantifying Aristotle’s fallacies could be also used for quantifying any other fallacy, which gives the required generality to our study. Keywords: logical fallacies; Aristotle’s fallacies; probability; statistical literacy; critical thinking; fuzzy logic (FL) 1. Introduction Fallacies are logically false statements that are often considered to be true. The first fallacies appeared in the literature simultaneously with the generation of Aristotle’s bivalent Logic. In the “Sophistical Refutations” (Sophistici Elenchi), the last chapter of the collection of his six works on logic—which was named by his followers, the Peripatetics, as “Organon” (Instrument)—the great ancient Greek philosopher identified thirteen fallacies and divided them in two categories, the linguistic and non-linguistic fallacies [1].
    [Show full text]
  • Selections from Sophistical Refutations
    Material and Formal Fallacies from Aristotle’s On Sophistical Refutations Part 1 Let us now discuss sophistic refutations, i.e. what appear to be refutations but are really fallacies instead. We will begin in the natural order with the first. That some reasonings are genuine, while others seem to be so but are not, is evident. This happens with arguments, as also elsewhere, through a certain likeness between the genuine and the sham. For physically some people are in a vigorous condition, while others merely seem to be so by blowing and rigging themselves out as the tribesmen do their victims for sacrifice; and some people are beautiful thanks to their beauty, while others seem to be so, by dint of embellishing themselves. So it is, too, with inanimate things; for of these, too, some are really silver and others gold, while others are not and merely seem to be such to our sense; e.g. things made of litharge and tin seem to be of silver, while those made of yellow metal look golden. In the same way both reasoning and refutation are sometimes genuine, sometimes not, though inexperience may make them appear so: for inexperienced people obtain only, as it were, a distant view of these things. For reasoning rests on certain statements such that they involve necessarily the assertion of something other than what has been stated, through what has been stated: refutation is reasoning involving the contradictory of the given conclusion. Now some of them do not really achieve this, though they seem to do so for a number of reasons; and of these the most prolific and usual domain is the argument that turns upon names only.
    [Show full text]
  • Alabama State University Department of Languages and Literatures
    ALABAMA STATE UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF LANGUAGES AND LITERATURES COURSE SYLLABUS PHILOSOPHY 201 LOGICAL REASONING (PHL 201) (Revised 10/20/04 – Dr. Daniel Keller.) I. Faculty Listing: PHL 201: Logical Reasoning (3 credit hours) II. Description: To satisfactorily complete the course, a student must earn a grade of “C.” The course is designed to help students assess information and arguments and to improve their ability to reason in a clear and logical way. The course concentrates specifically on helping students learn some of the various uses of languages, understand how different kinds of inferences are drawn, and learn to recognize fallacies of ambiguity, presumption, and relevance. III. Purpose: Many students do not reason soundly and do not distinguish correct from incorrect reasoning. Hence, the aim of this course is to give students experience in learning to recognize and evaluate arguments; it also aims at teaching them to construct arguments that are reasonable and defensible. It is designed as a basic course to improve the reasoning skills of students. After completing this course successfully, students should show improvements in reading comprehension, writing, and test- taking skills. IV. Course Objectives: 1. Comprehend concepts 1-9 on the attached list. a) Define each concept b) Identify the meaning of each concept as it applies to logic. 2. Comprehend how these concepts function in logical reasoning. a) Given examples from the text of each concept, correctly identify the concept. b) Given new examples of each concept, correctly identify the concept. 3. Comprehend concepts 10-16 on the attached list. a) Define the concepts b) Identify the meaning of the concept as it applies to logic.
    [Show full text]
  • Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation
    South Carolina Law Review Volume 44 Issue 2 Article 4 Winter 1993 Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation Kevin W. Saunders University of Oklahoma Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/sclr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Kevin W. Saunders, Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation, 44 S. C. L. Rev. 343 (1993). This Article is brought to you by the Law Reviews and Journals at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in South Carolina Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Saunders: Informal Fallacies in Legal Argumentation INFORMAL FALLACIES IN LEGAL ARGUMENTATION KEVIN W. SAUNDERS" I. INTRODUCTION ............................ 344 II. VARIETIES OF INFORMAL FALLACIES ............... 345 A. Argumentum ad Hominem .... ............ B. Argumentum ad Misericordiam . ............ C. Argumentum ad Populum ..... ............ D. Argumentum ad Vericundiam .. ............ E. Ignoratio Elenchi .......... ............ F. Petitio Principii ........... ............ G. Post Hoc Ergo Propter Hoc ... ............ H. Argumentum ad Ignorantiam ... ............ L Argumentum ad Terrorem .... ............ J. Argumentum ad Antiquitam ... ............ K. Accident and Hasty Generalization ........... L. Composition ............. ............ M. Division ............... ° . o ..° ° . N. Complex Question ......... ............° ° 0. Tu Quoque .............. ............° ° P. Ambiguity .............. ............ 1. Equivocation .........
    [Show full text]
  • Should Climate Scientists Fly? a Case Study of Arguments at the System Level Jean Goodwin
    Document generated on 09/26/2021 2:33 a.m. Informal Logic Should Climate Scientists Fly? A Case Study of Arguments at the System Level Jean Goodwin Volume 40, Number 2, 2020 Article abstract I inquire into argument at the system level, exploring the controversy over URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1070883ar whether climate scientists should fly. I document participants’ knowledge of a DOI: https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i2.6327 skeptical argument that because scientists fly, they cannot testify credibly about the climate emergency. I show how this argument has been managed by See table of contents pro-climate action arguers, and how some climate scientists have developed parallel reasoning, articulating a sophisticated case why they will be more effective in the controversy if they fly less. Finally, I review some strategies Publisher(s) arguers deploy to use the arguments of others against them. I argue that only by attending to argument-making at the system level can we understand how Informal Logic arguers come to know the resources for argument available in a controversy and to think strategically about how to use them. I call for more work on ISSN argument at the system level. 0824-2577 (print) 2293-734X (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Goodwin, J. (2020). Should Climate Scientists Fly? A Case Study of Arguments at the System Level. Informal Logic, 40(2), 157–203. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v40i2.6327 Copyright (c), 2020 Jean Goodwin This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online.
    [Show full text]
  • TOOLKIT Exchanges of Practices
    “Exchange of learning and teaching strategies: media literacy in adult education” Erasmus+ Strategic Partnerships for adult education (2016-2018) Project number: 2016-1-FR01-KA204-024220 TOOLKIT Exchanges of Practices This project has been funded with support from the European Commission. This publication reflects the views only of the author and the Commission cannot be held responsible for any use, which may be made of the information contained therein. Content Introduction……………………………………………………………………………………….3 “Media bias, fallacies and social representations definitions” workshop…………….4 Social representation……………………………………………………………………………7 “Recognizing Fallacies” workshop…………………………………………………………..9 “Recognizing Appeals to Emotion” workshop……………………………………………21 ”Text analysis” workshop………………………………………………………………….....25 Text for analysis………………………………………………………………………………...30 Critical Thinking workshop "The Logical Fallacies of Nationalism"………………….33 Workshop on writing: “Traditional and inverted pyramids”……………………………36 Deconstructing image………………………………………………………………………....40 Project poster…………………………………………………………………………………...44 Introduction "Exchange of learning and teaching strategies: media literacy in adult education" is an Erasmus+ Strategic Partnerships project for six partners from France, Estonia, Italy, Malta, Spain and Sweden. The coordinator of this project is MITRA FRANCE non-governmental organization from France. The project is funded by the Erasmus+ Programme of the European Commission. It seeks to develop initiatives addressing spheres of adult education, gathering and exchanges of experience and best practices in media literacy. This initiative contributes to strengthening media literacy as a mean of countering online and ordinary radicalisation and stigmatisation. As one of the results of this partnership the consortium has compiled a Toolkit with several good practices exchanged and tested during this project. This Toolkit is designed for adult educators, trainers and support staff who are interested in using media literacy in their daily work.
    [Show full text]
  • Classification of Fallacies of Relevance!
    Classification of Fallacies of Relevance! DOUGLAS WALTON University of Winnipeg Abstract: Fallacies of relevance, a major Resume: Les sophismes qui enfreignent la category of informal fallacies, include two pertinence constituent une classe importante that could be called pure fallacies of des sophismes non formels. Les sophismes relevance-the wrong conclusion (ignoratio de conclusion erronee (ignoratio elenchi) et elenchi, wrong conclusion, missing the point) de digression (ou de diversion) transgressent fallacy and the red herring (digression, si evidemment la pertinence qu' on pourrait diversion) fallacy. The problem is how to les nommer des purs sophismes de classify examples of these fallacies so that pertinence. Le defi est de determiner they clearly fall into the one category or the comment classer des exemples dans I'une other, on some rational system of classifica­ ou l'autre de ces categories. J'emploie Ie tion. In this paper, the argument diagram­ logiciel Araucaria pour representer en ming software system, Araucaria. is used diagramme la structure d' exemples de purs to analyze the argumentation in some sophismes qu' on trouve dans certains selected textbook examples of pure fallacies manuels, et propose des criteres pour relever of relevance. A system of classification of ce defi. Une difference principale entre ces these fallacies is proposed, and criteria for deux sophismes est que pour imputer Ie determining whether an example should be sophisme de digression a une personne il classified as wrong conclusion or red herring faut des preuves qu'elle a deliberement are formulated. A key difference cited is that employe des tactiques trompeuses ou des in a case where the red herring fallacy has controverses pour derouter son auditoire du been committed, even if the argument may vrai sujet en question.
    [Show full text]