The Uneasy Case for Progressive Taxation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Uneasy Case for Progressive Taxation University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1952 The neU asy Case for Progressive Taxation Walter J. Blum Harry Kalven Jr. Follow this and additional works at: https://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/journal_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Walter J. Blum, Harry Kalven & Jr., "The neU asy Case for Progressive Taxation," 19 University of Chicago Law Review 417 (1952). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO LAW REVIEW VOLUME 19 SPRING 1952 NUMBER 3 THE UNEASY CASE FOR PROGRESSIVE TAXATION WALTER J. BLUM AND HARRY KALVEN, JR.* I. ROGRESSIVE TAXATION IS NOW REGARDED as one of the central ideas of modern democratic capitalism and is widely accepted as a secure policy commitment which does not require serious examination. The single topic of this essay is the extent to which progressive taxation can be justified. It may seem something of a luxury to indulge in an extensive investiga- tion of this question at the present time. There are, to be sure, some indica- tions that the subject is newsworthy. The State of Illinois is currently con- sidering an amendment to its constitution to permit the enactment of a state income tax. While there is considerable support for the adoption of an income tax, there is widespread insistence that the amendment contain an explicit prohibition against a progressive income tax.' On the national scene attention is finally being paid to the proposal to amend the Constitu- tion to limit the rates of federal income taxes by imposing a ceiling of twenty-five per cent.2 It is clear that the amendment has as one of its prin- * Associate Professors of Law, University of Chicago Law School. Both Houses of the Illinois legislature have approved a resolution calling for submitting to the electorate in November .952 a proposal to amend various sections of the revenue article of the Illinois Constitution. Proposed new Section 2 provides: "The General Assembly may levy or authorize the levy of such other kinds of taxes as it may deem necessary, which shall be uniform upon the same class of subjects within the territorial limits of the authority levying the tax, but shall not levy or authorize the levy of a graduated income tax." 7th General Assembly, Illinois, House Joint Resolution 40 (i95.). The wording of the amendment may conceal a serious ambiguity as to whether the prohibition extends to the kind of pro- gression that results from granting an exemption. See text, section 2o infra. The proposed amendment was discussed at the University of Chicago Law School Conference on Illinois Constitutional Amendments, Evening Session, May 15, i95i. zSee H.J. Res. 323, 82d Cong. ist Sess. (i9Mi); H.J. Res. 268, 82d Cong. ist Sess. (195'); S.J. Res. 108, 82d Cong. 1st Sess. (i95i). The proposed amendment is subjected to appropriate 417 THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO LAW REVIEW [Vol. x9 cipal purposes the curtailing of progression, at least during periods of peace. On the international level the progression issue has put in an ap- pearance in the discussions of how the costs of maintaining a common military organization are to be apportioned among the member nations of the North Atlantic Treaty Organization. The argument is repeatedly being advanced that the progressive principle in the tax systems of the individual countries offers strong precedent for adapting the principle to this new situation.3 Apart from these current developments, it is always true that every adjustment of federal tax rates necessarily calls into active question the principle of progression. Any change in the rates either re- affirms the existing degree of progression or alters it. The basic considera- tions advanced in every controversy about rate changes echo the argu- ments for and against the principle of progression itself.4 These current matters, however, are not the motivating force for this essay. It arises out of an attempt to satisfy our curiosity. Like most people today we found the notion of progression immediately congenial. Upon early analysis the notion retained its attractiveness, but our curiosity as to the source of its appeal increased. The somewhat paradoxical character we detected in the topic is suggested by certain aspects of its literature. A surprising number of serious writers note that progression seems to be in- stinctively correct, although they then go on to explore it on rational grounds. More striking is the fact that the most devastating critics of the defenses for progression are almost invariably its friends. It is close to the truth to say that only those who ultimately favor progression on some ground have been its effective critics on other grounds.5 It is as though scrutiny in 29 Taxes (July i95i). If additional literature on the subject is desired, it can be obtained all too easily from the Committee for Constitutional Government, 2o5 East 42d St., New York 17, N.Y. 3 "Now this principle [of proportion] may be fair. If so, we must not shirk the obvious implications; and it is certain that some countries of continental Europe are not pulling their weight. But in fact the full proportional principle is not in line with modem ideas about the equity of tax burdens. All civilized countries now operate on the progressive and not on the proportionate principle, namely, the principle that persons with a higher real income should contribute a larger proportion of their income in taxation. It would, on this principle, be fair that the United States, with its higher real income per head, should contribute a higher pro- portion of its national income to the common defence. Indeed, it is inevitable that the pro- gressive principle should be adopted. But if it is adopted, it does, of course, greatly complicate the problem of equitable burden-sharing." Mead, Some Economic Problems of Atlantic Union Rearmament, Lloyds Bank Rev. 35, 40 (Oct. 195'). 4 See Blough, The Argument Phase of Taxpayer Politics, 17 Univ. Chi. L. Rev. 604 (1950). s Sufficient evidence for this point may be found in the writings of Seligman, Edgeworth, Chapman, Fagan and Simons which are discussed in some detail in the course of the essay. This is not to deny that there are some competent critics who in the end rejected progression, such as Adams and Bastable. 1952] THE UNEASY CASE FOR PROGRESSIVE TAXATION 419 those who have most clearly detected the weaknesses of various lines of analysis previously offered to support progression were under a compul- sion to find some new way to justify it rather than give it up. The hunch that there must be some basis on which an idea as initially attrac- tive as progression can be justified is stubborn indeed. 2. It is probable that many do not reach the issues of progression because they tend to regard as decisive the fact that the rich pay more in taxes than the poor. But this is an attribute of both proportionate and progres- sive taxes and overlooks the real difference between the two. A proportion- ate tax, for example on income, is one which taxes each dollar of income at the same rate regardless of the total income of the taxpayer; under it a taxpayer with ten times the total income of another would pay ten times as much tax. A progressive tax on income is one whose rate increases as the income of the taxpayer increases; under it a taxpayer with ten times the total income of another would pay something more than ten times-as much tax. There is another basic rate pattern for a tax. The rate of tax, again using a tax on income as an illustration, may be graduated downward with income and thus be regressive; under this pattern a man with ten times the income of another would pay something less than ten times as much tax. It is so clear no one today favors any tax because it is regressive that the term itself has become colored. Since a regressive tax on income is not a serious alternative the question of this essay can be narrowed and restated: On what grounds is a progressive tax on income to be preferred to a proportionate tax on income? The question requires further qualification. It assumes that the rate of the tax is being measured against income. Income is not the only possible base against which to classify rate patterns; either capital or expenditures could be used.6 The income base, however, appears to offer the best frame- work for analysis of the case for progression, and therefore discussion will be focussed on it, although from time to time reference will be made to wealth as a base., 6 Not every tax base would be equally meaningful for progression; thus a "progressive" tax on the consumption of milk would almost certainly be regressive as measured by income or wealth. "Progressive taxes may be divided into two general types: one type of tax is based on a flow of money or goods and services during a given period of time, the other on a stock of capital or goods belonging to a taxpayer at a given point in time. The principal exemplars of the 'flow' type of tax are the income tax and the spendings tax; the 'stock of goods' type of tax includes property taxes, net worth taxes, capital levies, and succession taxes." Vickrey, Agenda for Progressive Taxation 4 (1947).
Recommended publications
  • Rent-Seeking Behaviour and Ẓulm (Injustice/ Exploitation) Beyond Ribā-Interest Equation
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Farooq, Mohammad O. Article Rent-seeking behaviour and ẓulm (injustice/ exploitation) beyond ribā-interest equation ISRA International Journal of Islamic Finance Provided in Cooperation with: International Shari'ah Research Academy for Islamic Finance (ISRA), Kuala Lumpur Suggested Citation: Farooq, Mohammad O. (2019) : Rent-seeking behaviour and ẓulm (injustice/exploitation) beyond ribā-interest equation, ISRA International Journal of Islamic Finance, ISSN 2289-4365, Emerald, Bingley, Vol. 11, Iss. 1, pp. 110-123, http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/IJIF-07-2018-0073 This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/236941 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Economy, Unearned Income, and Legalized Corruption
    Moral Economy, Unearned Income, and Legalized Corruption To be published in Neoliberalism and the Moral Economy of Fraud, 2016, ed. by D. Whyte and J. Wiegratz, Routledge ISBN: 9781138930377 Andrew Sayer, Lancaster University June 2015 ‘When plunder becomes a way of life for a group of men living in society, they create for themselves, in the course of time, a legal system that authorizes it and a moral code that glorifies it.’ (Frédéric Bastiat) Introduction: Moral Economy As French political economist Frédéric Bastiat appreciated, the origins of our contemporary economy had little to do with deliberations on what might be fair and morally justified and a lot to do with power. Yet our basic economic institutions are generally portrayed as legitimate and as accepted as such, though more as ‘facts of life’ than as rationally justified, and this acceptance is important for their continued existence. It would be a mistake to assume that because our political economic architecture is largely a product of power that there is no point in considering it in terms of moral and ethical questions of justice, fairness and human well-being. Unless we consider these things, we have little basis for criticising anything. Amartya Sen once drew a distinction between the ‘engineering’ and the ‘ethical’ approaches to economics (Sen, 1991). The former treats economies as machines that work in various ways that need to be described and explained, and which economists can fix if they work badly. The ethical approach treats economies as sets of social relations and practices that may be good or bad on moral and ethical grounds and need to be assessed in those terms.
    [Show full text]
  • Marx and Keynes: from Exploitation to Employment
    Institute for International Political Economy Berlin Marx and Keynes: from exploitation to employment Author: Fritz Helmedag Working Paper, No. 113/2019 Editors: Sigrid Betzelt, Eckhard Hein (lead editor), Martina Metzger, Jennifer Pedussel Wu, Martina Sproll, Christina Teipen, Achim Truger, Markus Wissen, Reingard Zimmer Marx and Keynes: from exploitation to employment Fritz Helmedag* Abstract Marx’s and Keynes’s analyses of capitalism complement each other well. In a rather general model including the public sector and international trade it is shown that the labour theory of value provides a sound foundation to reveal the factors influencing employment. Workers buy ‘necessaries’ out of their disposa- ble wages from an integrated basic sector, whereas the ‘luxury’ department’s revenues spring from other sources of income. In order to maximize profits, the wage good industry controls the level of unit labour costs. After all, effective demand governs the volume of work. On this basis, implications for economic policy are outlined. JEL-classification: E11, E12, E24 Keywords: Employment, Marx, Keynes, Surplus value * Chemnitz University of Technology, Economics Department, Thüringer Weg 7, D-09107 Chemnitz, Germany. Email: [email protected] Paper presented at the IPE 10th Anniversary Conference: Studying Modern Capi- talism – The Relevance of Marx Today, Berlin, 12-13 July 2018. 2 Fritz Helmedag 1. Surplus value and the rate of profit The essence of this article is that the great economic thinkers mentioned in the title make a good couple not only regarding their exposure of capitalism’s mal- functions but also, and more importantly, from an analytical point of view.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpretations of Mill's Harm Principle and the Economic Implications Therein
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Political Science Theses Department of Political Science Fall 11-16-2012 Beyond Libertarianism: Interpretations of Mill's Harm Principle and the Economic Implications Therein Matthew A. Towery Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/political_science_theses Recommended Citation Towery, Matthew A., "Beyond Libertarianism: Interpretations of Mill's Harm Principle and the Economic Implications Therein." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2012. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/political_science_theses/45 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Political Science at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BEYOND LIBERTARIANISM: INTERPRETATIONS OF MILL’S HARM PRINCIPLE AND THE ECONOMIC IMPLICATIONS THEREIN by MATTHEW TOWERY Under the Direction of Mario Feit ABSTRACT The thesis will examine the harm principle, as originally described by John Stuart Mill. In doing so, it will defend that, though unintended, the harm principle may justify several principles of distributive justice. To augment this analysis, the paper will examine several secondary au- thors’ interpretations of the harm principle, including potential critiques of the thesis itself. INDEX WORDS: Mill, Harm principle, Libertarianism, Redistribution,
    [Show full text]
  • The Morality of Money: American Attitudes Toward Wealth and the Income Tax
    Indiana Law Journal Volume 70 Issue 1 Article 5 Winter 1994 The Morality Of Money: American Attitudes Toward Wealth and the Income Tax Marjorie E. Kornhauser Tulane Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj Part of the Taxation-Federal Commons, and the Tax Law Commons Recommended Citation Kornhauser, Marjorie E. (1994) "The Morality Of Money: American Attitudes Toward Wealth and the Income Tax," Indiana Law Journal: Vol. 70 : Iss. 1 , Article 5. Available at: https://www.repository.law.indiana.edu/ilj/vol70/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Journals at Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Indiana Law Journal by an authorized editor of Digital Repository @ Maurer Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Morality Of Money: American Attitudes Toward Wealth and the Income Taxt MARJORIE E. KORNHAUSER* Wealth fascinates Americans. Alexis de Tocqueville said in 1835: "'The love of wealth is... at the bottom of all that the Americans do. "" In reality, American feelings about wealth are much more complex and ambiguous than Tocqueville claims. Americans fear and disdain wealth as well as love it.' We differentiate types of money and wealth, despite the economists' claims that all money is fungible. In particular, Americans imbue earned income with an aura of morality and virtuousness that unearned income, particularly inherited income, does not have.' Consequently, we Americans admire the person who acquires her wealth by means of her own talent and industry, while at the t Q 1993 by Marjorie E.
    [Show full text]
  • Theorising and Mapping Modern Economic Rents
    Theorising and mapping modern economic rents Mariana Mazzucato Professor in the Economics of Innovation and Public Value, Director, UCL Institute for Innovation and Public Purpose Josh Ryan-Collins Head of Finance and Macroeconomics, Senior Research Fellow, UCL Institute of Innovation and Public Purpose Giorgos Gouzoulis Reseach Fellow, UCL Institute of Innovation and Public Purpose UCL Institute for Innovation and WORKING PAPER Public Purpose WP 2020—13 About the Institute for Innovation and Public Purpose The UCL Institute for Innovation and Public Purpose (IIPP) aims to develop a new framework for creating, nurturing and evaluating public value in order to achieve economic growth that is more innovation-led, inclusive and sustainable. We intend this framework to inform the debate about the direction of economic growth and the use of mission-oriented policies to confront social and technological problems. Our work will feed into innovation and industrial policy, financial reform, institutional change, and sustainable development. A key pillar of IIPP's research is its understanding of markets as outcomes of the interactions between different actors. In this context, public policy should not be seen as simply fixing market failures but also as actively shaping and co-creating markets. Re-focusing and designing public organisations around mission-led, public purpose aims will help tackle the grand challenges facing the 21st century. IIPP is housed in The Bartlett, a leading global Faculty of the Built Environment at University College London (UCL), with its radical thinking about space, design and sustainability. This IIPP Working Paper Series is published electronically at https://www.ucl.ac.uk/bartlett/public-purpose/publications/working-papers.
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Basic Income and Inclusive Capitalism: Consequences for Sustainability
    sustainability Article Universal Basic Income and Inclusive Capitalism: Consequences for Sustainability Ralph P. Hall 1,* , Robert Ashford 2, Nicholas A. Ashford 3 and Johan Arango-Quiroga 4 1 School of Public and International Affairs, Virginia Tech, Blacksburg, VA 24061, USA 2 College of Law, Syracuse University, Syracuse, NY 13244, USA 3 Technology and Law Program, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge, MA 02139, USA 4 Sustainability Program, Harvard University, Extension School, Cambridge, MA 02138, USA * Correspondence: [email protected] Received: 20 June 2019; Accepted: 12 August 2019; Published: 19 August 2019 Abstract: Over the past forty years, income growth for the middle and lower classes has stagnated, while the economy (and with it, economic inequality) has grown significantly. Early automation, the decline of labor unions, changes in corporate taxation, the financialization and globalization of the economy, deindustrialization in the U.S. and many OECD countries, and trade have contributed to these trends. However, the transformative roles of more recent automation and digital technologies/artificial intelligence (AI) are now considered by many as additional and potentially more potent forces undermining the ability of workers to maintain their foothold in the economy. These drivers of change are intensifying the extent to which advancing technology imbedded in increasingly productive real capital is driving productivity. To compound the problem, many solutions presented by industrialized nations to environmental problems rely on hyper-efficient technologies, which if fully implemented, could further advance the displacement of well-paid job opportunities for many. While there are numerous ways to address economic inequality, there is growing interest in using some form of universal basic income (UBI) to enhance income and provide economic stability.
    [Show full text]
  • The Abduction of Adam Smith How a Brilliant Observer and Kindly Egalitarian Became the Symbol of Greed Polly Cleveland, 2013
    The Abduction of Adam Smith How a Brilliant Observer and Kindly Egalitarian Became the Symbol of Greed Polly Cleveland, 2013 1776 was a banner year for liberty. In Philadelphia, the ragtag Continental Congress sweltered and argued in the summer heat while drafting the Declaration of Independence. Across the Atlantic, Scotsman Adam Smith (1723-1790) published the world’s most famous treatise on economics, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations1. A coincidence? No. Both sprang from the Enlightenment, or Age of Reason, a seventeenth and eighteenth century reaction against narrow church dogma and for science and humanism. While writing the book, Smith met and corresponded with Benjamin Franklin. Thomas Jefferson left us a précis of Enlightenment values: “We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness.” Were Adam Smith to return to earth today, allowing for differences between the eighteenth and twenty-first centuries, he’d probably fit somewhere out in the far political left, but without the anger. Smith and subsequent “classical” economists addressed inequality head on, asking what determines the distribution of income. They supported free markets and free trade, not as ends in themselves, but as means to create broad prosperity and to curb monopoly. They also supported taxing the rich and privileged. So how come today so many of us imagine Smith a heartless avatar of “greed is good”, a saint of the money-changers? What transformed Smith and the classical tradition into the “neoclassical” tradition we live with today—a tradition that exalts the “free market” and leaves no room for equality or fairness? It’s a complex story, one that hinges ultimately on changing the meaning of words.
    [Show full text]
  • New Rents Economy – U.S
    Revista de Economia Contemporânea (2016) 20(3): p. 391-404 (Journal of Contemporary Economics) ISSN 1980-5527 http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/198055272031 www.ie.ufrj.br/revista www.scielo.br/rec NEW RENTS ECONOMY – U.S. INEQUALITY IN THE 21ST CENTURY Pari Kasliwala aCalifornia State University, Long Beach, CA / USA. Manuscript received on 2015/10/23 and accepted for publication on 2016/11/21. ABSTRACT: Rents in the U.S. economy now constitute a significant and growing fraction of national income. In effect, the post-industrial U.S. is becoming more like Saudi Arabia as these new rents arise in very concentrated form. Thus, policy is now obliged to focus more on distribution rather than the traditional emphasis on production and efficiency. The expanding impacts of trade and technology now combine with the increased production of ‘knowledge goods’ to sharply increase income inequality. The paper argues that the root cause of the inequality surge is the proliferation of new rents in sharp contrast to the Piketty’s focus on capital accumulation in a neoclassical context. Once rents exceed a certain threshold (share of national income), then it is no longer permissible to maintain the neoclassical presumption that it can be neglected. Then the policy implications are completely revered – even revolutionary – with regard to the stance on redistributions, higher education, incentives and capital taxation, etc. JEL CODES: D24; D31; O51; P16; P17. KEYWORDS: US rents economy; income distribution. Corresponding author: Pari Kasliwal E-mail address: [email protected] 392 Rev. Econ. Contemp., Rio de Janeiro, v. 20, n. 3, p.
    [Show full text]
  • Neutral Taxation of Capital Income: an Achievable Goal?
    NEUTRAL TAXATION OF CAPITAL INCOME: AN ACHIEVABLE GOAL? PAMELA B. GANN* The U.S. government is expected to provide macroeconomic management to minimize unemployment and inflation and to maintain productivity growth. This management function did not appear to be performed adequately during the late 1970's or early 1980's since the United States experienced unemployment, inflation, and a decline in productivity growth.' During this period, critics (often referred to as "supply-siders") of government economic management focused on issues of capital formation. They argued that the Copyright © 1985 by Law and Contemporary Problems * Professor of Law, Duke University, Durham, North Carolina. While writing this article, the author was an International Affairs Fellow of the Council on Foreign Relations and a guest-in- residence of the Fiscal Affairs Department of the International Monetary Fund. The author thanks the Council and, in particular, Vito Tanzi, Director, and Leif Muten, Senior Advisor, of the Fiscal Affairs Department for their excellent colleagueship during her visit with the Fund. 1. This footnote summarizes relevant economic data. TABLE 2 GNP GROWrH RATES (1972 CONSTANT DOLLARS) TABLE 1 (PERCENTAGE CHANGE FROM PRECEDING GNP IMPLICIT PRICE DEFLATOR YEAR) Year Deflator Year Percentage 1977 5.8 1978 5.0 1978 7.4 1979 2.8 1979 8.6 1980 - 0.3 1980 9.2 1981 2.6 1981 9.4 1982 - 1.9 1982 6.0 1983 3.3 1983 4.2 Source: COUNCIL OF ECONOMIC ADVI- Source: ECONOMIC REPORT OF THE PRESI- SORS, ECONOMIC REPORT OF THE PRESI- DENT 1984, at 223 (Table B-2). DENT 225 (Table B-3) (1984) [hereinafter cited as ECONOMIC REPORT OF THE PRESI- DENT 1984].
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter M08 Abd Income Subchapter 10
    CHAPTER M08 ABD INCOME Manual Title Chapter Page Revision Date Virginia Medical Assistance Eligibility M08 October 1996 Chapter Subject Page ending with Page ABD INCOME TOC i CHAPTER M08 TABLE OF CONTENTS ABD INCOME SUBCHAPTER Page GENERAL–ABD INCOME RULES......................M810.000 General .......................................................................... S0810.001 ................................... 1 Whose Income Is It? .................................................... S0810.120 ................................... 9 Computing Countable Income .................................... S0810.300 ................................. 14 Income Exclusions Which Apply To Both Earned and Unearned Income ........................ S0810.400. ................................ 16 Verifying and Estimation Income ............................ S0810.500 ................................. 25 Income of Members of Religious Orders Who Take a Vow of Poverty .................... S0810.700 ................................. 29 WHAT IS NOT INCOME ...................................... M0815.000 EARNED INCOME ................................................ M0820.000 General ......................................................................... M0820.001 ................................... 1 Wages ............................................................................. S0820.100 ................................... 5 Net Earnings From Self-Employment ........................ S0820.200 ................................. 15 Sheltered Income Tax Credits
    [Show full text]
  • Earned and Unearned Income by WILLFORD I
    251 Certain of the independent establish- partisanship can never fail to be above ments should be incorporated into suspicion. existing or new departments. Others These changes in administrative or- must remain wholly or in part outside ganization would probably save the the framework of departmental or- Federal Government little, if any, ganization, but, where necessary, should money. On the other hand, they would be resolved into their several elements. certainly improve the efficiency of the Quasi-legislative functions should be services concerned. But most impor- assigned to agencies organized for the tant of all, they would greatly performance of such functions. Quasi- strengthen the government in the con- judicial functions should be assigned to fidence of the people. For the moment, agencies organized for the performance public opinion seems disposed to make .of such functions. The Interstate fewer demands upon the government Commerce Commission, for example, for the increase of administrative activ- and the Federal Trade Commission, ities than for a long time past. The perform certain duties which might opportunity should be seized to intro- not improperly be transferred to the duce sound methods of administration, Department of Justice. Others may to strengthen the administrative ma- be vested in any suitable partisan or chinery, and to accumulate a stock of administrative agency. The purely public confidence in the administrative executive duties of the Interstate capacity of the government which will Commerce Commission alone would stand it in good stead when opinion furnish ample employment for a large presently demands the assumption of bureau in the Department of Com- new responsibilities towards the pub- merce.
    [Show full text]