A Kantian Reply to Meillassoux's Argument

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Kantian Reply to Meillassoux's Argument Back to the Great Outdoors? A Kantian Reply to Meillassoux’s Argument Toby Lovat A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements of the University of Brighton for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy November 2018 2 For Lucy and Ben 3 ABSTRACT In this thesis I develop both immanent and extrinsic critiques of Meillassoux’s argument, principally as it is developed and articulated in his book After Finitude. Meillassoux’s ambitious project is assessed in detail. While I concede that the anti-realism developed in the shadow of Kant’s legacy has a produced a profound rift between philosophical and scientific discourse, I contend that Meillassoux’s argument tacitly conflates epistemology with ontology. Most pressing, however, is that his central argument is predicated on a misreading of Kant’s idealism. I defend the epistemological interpretation of Kant’s idealism over the traditional metaphysical reading, and argue that Kant’s transcendental idealism and his empirical realism not only accommodates the ‘literal’ truth of ancestral claims but also demonstrates that what counts as real depends on an intuitive-epistemic framework: a standpoint. Moreover, I demonstrate that Meillassoux’s argument is predicated on, and permeated by, what Kant refers to as transcendental error, the upshot of which is a tacit adherence to dogmatism and the generation of antinomies. 4 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Without the support of family, friends and colleagues I could neither have started nor completed this thesis. My thanks go to the University of Brighton. The institution has not only made it financially possible for me to undertake this work, but the administrative and academic staff in the Doctoral College have been unfailingly supportive. Thanks also to my colleagues in the School of Humanities, all of whom have consistently encouraged my doctoral work and acknowledged its pressures and time demands. I thank my supervisors, Bob Brecher and Mark Devenney, for their steadfast commitment throughout. My deep gratitude to Bob cannot be expressed adequately here – or perhaps anywhere. Bob, without your patience, dedication and friendship, not to mention your fierce intellectual rigour, I would not have completed this work. Further thanks go to my PhD examiners, Alberto Toscano and Ray Brassier, for both reading my thesis and putting me through my paces in a highly stimulating viva. I am also grateful to my colleagues Clare Woodford, Andy Knott, Tom Hickey and Tom Bunyard for helping me to prepare for the viva. Further thanks go to attendees at the Kant, Sellars and Meillassoux conference at University College Dublin and the 2017 winter school at the University of Tübingen, as well as to colleagues in the Critical Studies Research Group at the University of Brighton. The ideas presented in this thesis are, in no small measure, the outcome of discussion with, and feedback from, these excellent people. Speaking of which; I wish to extend a special thanks to Nicola Clewer, Tom Bunyard, Doug Elsey, Rob Dunphy and Pete Wolfendale, whose intellectual support and stimulation have been instrumental in shaping my thinking. I am exceptionally fortunate to have a loving and understanding extended and immediate family, whose enduring moral and practical support, especially when they have been most needed, are the grounds upon which this thesis rests. I extend my deepest thanks to Trisha, Constantine, Hannah, Joe, Matthew, Emily, Mervyn and Linda; and above all to Lucy and Ben without whom neither joy nor perseverance would be possible. 5 CONTENTS Abstract 3 Acknowledgements 4 Contents 5 Declaration 6 Introduction: A Kantian Reply to Meillassoux’s Arguments 7 Chapter 1: Correlationism and the Challenge of the Ancestral 13 Chapter 2: Ground Clearing and the Road to Speculative Materialism 59 Chapter 3: The Trouble with Correlationism? 93 Chapter 4: Strong Correlationism and its Enemies 139 Chapter 5: Kant’s Transcendental Deduction 165 Chapter 6: The Illusion of Causal Necessity? Hume’s Problem and Meillassoux’s Solution 197 Chapter 7: Kant’s Empirical Realism and Meillassoux’s Transcendental Illusion 243 Conclusion: Speculative Guilt 267 Bibliography 273 6 AUTHOR’S DECLARATION I declare that the research contained in this thesis, unless otherwise formally indicated within the text, is the original work of the author. The thesis has not been previously submitted to this or any other university for a degree, and does not incorporate any material already submitted for a degree. Toby Lovat November 2018 7 INTRODUCTION: A KANTIAN REPLY TO MEILLASSOUX’S ARGUMENT Flammarion engraving, Paris 1888. Metaphysics means nothing but an unusually obstinate effort to think clearly.1 A slight change in the meaning of terms has caused all this commotion.2 Flammarion engraving, Paris 1888. It is not difficult to see why Quentin Meillassoux’s After Finitude ‘provoked a genuine thunderstorm in the philosophical sky’.3 His ambitious crusade against what he takes to be the anti-realism stitched deep into the metaphysical backdrop of contemporary philosophy begins with a seductive philosophical provocation: if we cannot know reality as it exists independent of our minds, how do we explain the fact that we do?4 The interest in Meillassoux’s argument lies in both his diagnosis of this question, and in the striking originality of his approach to its resolution. He contends that although Kant’s idealist revolution laid the groundwork for a fundamental rift between the predominant position in philosophy – correlationism – and the clear success of science in grasping things as they are in themselves, this rift cannot be overcome by a simple rejection of the former. Instead, correlationism must be refuted by immanent critique; by accepting and clarifying its argumentative procedures and demonstrating that they lead to contradiction. To borrow a line Slavoj Žižek borrows from Richard Wagner’s 1 William James, The Principles of Psychology Vol 1 (New York: Dover, 1950), 145. 2 G. W. Leibniz, Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil, ed. Austin Farrer (Charleston, South Carolina: BiblioBazaar, 1985), 161. 3 Catherine Malabou, ‘Can We Relinquish the Transcendental?’ The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 28, no. 3 (2014), 242. 4 The ambiguities in this question are a central feature of this thesis. Although this anti-realist stance is especially characteristic of philosophers working within the so-called continental tradition – typically associated with phenomenological, postmodernist and hermeneutical approaches – because it emerges from the critique of traditional metaphysics and hence of metaphysical realism it is a fairly common current in the so-called analytic tradition. Thinkers as different as Carnap, Heidegger, Wittgenstein, Derrida, Rorty and Putnam argue for the elimination, rejection or deconstruction of metaphysical realism. 8 Parsifal – ‘The [correlationist] wound is healed only by the spear that smote’ it.5 This ‘critique of Critique’ serves as a proof of Meillassoux’s contention that the only non-dogmatic means by which to account for our capacity to know things in themselves is to transform the sceptical principle grounding the correlationist critique of metaphysics into a necessary truth about the universe, and the possibilities and actualities therein; namely, the necessity of everything’s contingency.6 Rendered ontological this is to say that reality is a ‘hyper-Chaos’ in which anything at all (except a contradictory entity or the existence of nothing) is possible. In his preface to After Finitude Alain Badiou conveys the courageous novelty of Meillassoux’s argument: ‘Quentin Meillassoux has opened up a new path in the history of philosophy …; a path that circumvents Kant’s canonical distinction between “dogmatism”, “skepticism” and “critique”.’ 7 In 140 pages of typically clear and concise argument Meillassoux attempts to overturn Kantian finitude and reconcile thought and being by demonstrating the necessity of everything’s contingency, while also studiously avoiding either naïve realism or dogmatic idealism. This is why Meillassoux’s ‘thunderbolt’ has generated considerable interest and why his argument calls for serious consideration.8 My critique of Meillassoux’s argument is developed along both immanent and extrinsic lines. I assess his chain of reasoning by means of explication and critique, analysing its details and the interpretations of the historical arguments upon which it is based. Accordingly, my critique ranges widely across the history of Western philosophy. I argue that despite their robust appearance Meillassoux’s central arguments fail to convince. At the heart of my critique, however, is the contention that his project is predicated on a fundamental misunderstanding of Kant’s transcendental idealism, and that it consists, therefore, in an effort to burn down a straw man. Indeed, I demonstrate that his failure to engage robustly with Kant’s Critique is evident throughout. I draw on and defend Henry Allison’s groundbreaking epistemological interpretation of Kant’s idealism to argue that Meillassoux has not only misunderstood Kant’s correlationism, but also that it provides a critical perspective through which to identify both 5 Slavoj Žižek, Tarrying with the Negative: Kant, Hegel, and the Critique of Ideology (Durham: Duke Unversity Press, 2004), 170. 6 Quentin Meillassoux, After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency, trans. Ray Brassier (London: Continuum, 2008), VII. Hereafter abbreviated as AF. 7
Recommended publications
  • Ray Brassier: Nihil Unbound: Enlightenment and Extinction Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2007, 296 Pp, ISBN 9780230522046, US $84.95 (Cloth)
    Cont Philos Rev (2010) 42:583–589 DOI 10.1007/s11007-009-9127-8 Ray Brassier: Nihil unbound: enlightenment and extinction Palgrave MacMillan, Basingstoke, UK, 2007, 296 pp, ISBN 9780230522046, US $84.95 (cloth) Knox Peden Published online: 12 January 2010 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010 Punctuated by paeans to ‘‘the coruscating potency of reason’’ and the ‘‘dissociative virulence of…non-dialectical negativity,’’ Ray Brassier’s Nihil Unbound: Enlight- enment and Extinction is a work of philosophy committed to the ‘‘labor of disenchantment initiated by Galileo in the physical realm, continued by Darwin in the biological sphere, and currently being extended by cognitive science to the domain of mind’’ (xi, 45, 40). The defacement of the ‘‘book of the world’’ accomplished during the Enlightenment beckons ‘‘an invigorating vector of intellectual discovery, rather than a calamitous diminishment’’ (xi). This is because ‘‘[t]hinking has interests that do not coincide with those of living; indeed, they can and have been pitted against the latter’’ (xi). Pursuing these interests, Brassier develops a concept of the ‘‘will to know’’ congruent with a ‘‘will to nothingness’’ impervious to the countervailing force of the ‘‘will to live.’’ It is not the least of the ironies of Nihil Unbound that a work committed to marshalling the rigorous stringency of reason against the affective finesse of interpretation often produces claims that connect with the gut as much as the mind. Committed though he is to the notion that words are categorically weak objects for philosophical thought, Brassier nonetheless gets a lot of mileage out of them.
    [Show full text]
  • Avanessian – Xenoarchitecture (Draft) 1 Introduction Armen Avanessian
    avanessian – xenoarchitecture (draft) Introduction Armen Avanessian “Man’s desire is the desire of the Other,” Lacan, Seminar XI, p. 235 Following Lacan’s infamous dictum, according to which desire is defined as the desire of the Other, we could ask ourselves what a correlate methodology would look like for the humanities (or should we say “the inhumanities”?). Obviously, the structure of the phrase is ambiguous, or even tautological if taken as a predicative proposition. Instead, I propose to read it as a speculative proposition: we do not simply desire what the other has or hasn’t got, but we desire the state of being an Other, an othering, becoming a stranger to oneself and others—literally alienating them as well as “ourselves.” A desire for the xeno? This transformation has at least three central aspects: alienation (the negative mirroring of a given reality), negation (the construction of an asymmetry that initiates an annihilation of the positively given), and a recursion of alienation and negation through speculation.1 It is a poietic qua productive and creative transformation in the sense that it increases the scope of navigation and liberation by means of manipulation. Together with others, I have thought, experimented, and written a lot about questions of othering and “matching” experimental settings2 for the production of knowledge, tactical spaces in the sense of Michel de Certeau, xeno-spaces that are defined by “a calculated action determined by the absence of a proper locus. No delimitation of an exteriority, then, provides it with the condition necessary for autonomy. The space of a tactic is the space of the Other.
    [Show full text]
  • Mallarmé and the Politics of Literature Sartre, Kristeva, Badiou, Rancière
    Mallarmé and the Politics of Literature Sartre, Kristeva, Badiou, Rancière ROBERT BONCARDO Edinburgh University Press is one of the leading university presses in the UK. We publish academic books and journals in our selected subject areas across the humanities and social sciences, combining cutting-edge scholarship with high editorial and production values to produce academic works of lasting importance. For more information visit our website: edinburghuniversitypress.com © Robert Boncardo, 2018 Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun – Holyrood Road 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry Edinburgh EH8 8PJ Typeset in 10.5/13 Sabon by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 1 4744 2952 8 (hardback) ISBN 978 1 4744 2954 2 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 1 4744 2955 9 (epub) The right of Robert Boncardo to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). Contents Acknowledgements vi Abbreviations vii Series Editor’s Preface ix Introduction: Comrade Mallarmé 1 1 Jean-Paul Sartre’s Mallarmé: Hero of an Ontological Drama, Agent of the Counter-revolution 22 2 Julia Kristeva’s Mallarmé: From Fetishism to the Theatre-Book 79 3 Alain Badiou’s Mallarmé: From the Structural Dialectic to the Poetry of the Event 122 4 Jean-Claude Milner’s Mallarmé: Nothing Has Taken Place 175 5
    [Show full text]
  • New Books Catalogue 2017-18
    PHILOSOPHY, PAGE 2 THEOLOGY, BIBLICAL STUDIES& PAGE 29 RELIGIOUS STUDIES PAGE 41 NEW BOOKS CATALOGUE 2017-18 PAGE 50 9 781350 057005 PhilTheoBib_FINAL.indd 1-2 03/08/2017 11:19 TM Instant digital access to more than 6,000 eBooks across the social sciences and humanities, including titles from The Arden Shakespeare, Continuum, Bristol Classical Press, and Berg. Subjects covered include: Anthropology • Biblical Studies • Classical Studies & Archaeology • Education • Film & Media • History • Law • Linguistics • Literary Studies • Philosophy • Religious Studies • Theology CONTENT HIGHLIGHTS FEATURES • 125 Collections, expanded annually by subject discipline • Advanced and full text search across all content. • Archive Collections in key subject areas such as ancient • Filter results by subject, series, or collection history, Christology, continental philosophy, and more • Pagination matches print exactly • Special Collections such as International Critical • Personalization features: save searches, export citations Commentary, Ancient Commentators on Aristotle, and and favorite, download, or print documents Education Around the World series • Footnotes, endnotes, and bibliographic references are hyperlinked To register your interest for a free institutional trial, or for further information email: Americas: [email protected] UK, Europe, Middle East, Africa, Asia: [email protected] Australia and New Zealand: [email protected] www.bloomsburycollections.com Collections_advert_2.indd 1 19/07/2017 08:52 Contents
    [Show full text]
  • The Regulation of the Subject by the Technology of Time Maxwell Kennel [1]
    Rhizomes: Cultural Studies in Emerging Knowledge: Issue 34 (2018) The Regulation of the Subject by the Technology of Time Maxwell Kennel [1] Abstract: Beginning from the entangled categories of the human and the technological, this exploration surveys thinkers who concern themselves with problems of technology and time, seeking to examine how the confluence of technology and time regulate and condition the formation of subjectivity. Drawing on Bernard Stiegler's work in Technics and Time, Augustine's Confessions, and the myth of Prometheus, the following draws out the technological character of time and makes suggestions about how to reconceptualize these different temporalizing technologies after the critique of capitalism. Surely technology, in its ever-changing form and forms, is a pharmakon that has been with us from the start. Regardless of whether we speak of technology or technologies or the broader field of techne (a practice or craft), it remains that the term ‘technology’ refers to something that, like a double-edged sword, helps us and harms us, something that we use and that uses us, and something that is at once politically charged (often subtly oriented toward particular interests and ends with particular benefactors), yet ambivalent, taking different sides at different times (and therefore available for us to use as means for our own ends).[2] Although it is at our disposal and supposedly outside of ourselves, some have argued that technology is not in fact something extra that is added onto our human nature and experience, but instead something inextricably related to both humanity and history, and indeed something that challenges the legitimacy of these categories.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 33, Numbers 1-2, Fall 2019-Spring 2020 • Realism Published Twice Yearly, Mediations Is the Journal of the Marxist Literary Group
    Volume 33, Numbers 1-2, Fall 2019-Spring 2020 • Realism Published twice yearly, Mediations is the journal of the Marxist Literary Group. We publish dossiers of translated material on special topics and peer-reviewed general issues, usually in alternation. General inquiries and submissions should be directed to [email protected]. We invite scholarly contributions across disciplines on any topic that engages seriously with the Marxist tradition. Manuscripts received will be taken to be original, unpublished work not under consideration elsewhere. Articles should be submitted electronically in a widely-used format. Manuscripts should not exceed reasonable article length, and should be accompanied by an abstract of up to 300 words, including six keywords. Articles will be published in MLA endnote format, and should be submitted with the author’s name and affiliation on a separate cover page to facilitate blind peer review. Photographs, tables, and figures should be sent as separate files in a widely- used format. Written permission to reproduce copyright-protected material must be obtained by the author before submission. Books for review should be sent to: Mediations Department of English (MC 162) 601 South Morgan Street University of Illinois at Chicago Chicago IL 60607-7120 USA Articles published in Mediations may be reproduced for scholarly purposes without express permission, provided the reproduction is accompanied by full citation information. For archives and further information, visit http://www.mediationsjournal.org Cover
    [Show full text]
  • Against 'Flat Ontologies'
    64 Ray Brassier Deleveling: Against ‘Flat Ontologies’ Ray Brassier is associate professor of philosophy at the American University of Beirut. What I am going to present today is a critical discussion of the 65 tenets of so-called ‘flat ontology’. The expression ‘flat onto- logy’ has a complicated genealogy. It was originally coined as a pejorative term for empiricist philosophies of science by Roy Bhaskar in his 1975 book, A Realist Theory of Science. By the late 1990s, it had begun to acquire a positive sense in discus- sions of the work of Deleuze and Guattari. But it only achieved widespread currency in the wake of Manual De Landa’s 2002 book about Deleuze, Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy. More recently, it has been championed by proponents of ‘ob- ject-oriented ontology’ and ‘new materialism’. It is its use by these theorists that I will be discussing today. I will begin by explaining the ‘four theses’ of flat onto- logy, as formulated by Levi Bryant. Bryant is a proponent of ‘object-oriented ontology’, a school of thought founded by Graham Harman. In his 2010 work The Democracy of Objects, Bryant encapsulates flat ontology in the following four theses: Thesis 1: “First, due to the split characteristic of all ob- jects, flat ontology rejects any ontology of transcendence or presence that privileges one sort of entity as the origin of all others and as fully present to itself.” Thesis 2: “Second, […] the world or the universe does not exist. […] [T]here is no super-object that gathers all other ob- jects together in a single, harmonious
    [Show full text]
  • Language After Philosophy of Nature: Schelling’S Geology of Divine Names
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Liverpool Repository LANGUAGE AFTER PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE: SCHELLING’S GEOLOGY OF DIVINE NAMES DANIEL WHISTLER Each mineral is a real philological problem.1 Future commentary on Dante belongs to the natural sciences… No one has yet approached Dante with a geologist’s hammer, in order to ascertain the crystalline structure of his rock, in order to study the particles of other minerals in it, to study its smoky colour, its garish patterning, to judge it as a mineral crystal which has been subjected to the most varied series of accidents.2 What happens to language after the post-linguistic turn? In what does a speculative approach to religion consist? Such are the two questions around which this essay is structured. It is not my purpose to give a comprehensive answer to either question; rather, I am concerned with one very specific approach that could be taken, and this is the approach of F.W.J. Schelling. Schelling has never been so relevant, and this is in no small part thanks to Iain Hamilton Grant’s Philosophies of Nature after Schelling. Grant’s work–part of the recent resurgence in speculative philosophies—has been instrumental in presenting Schelling’s Naturphilosophie as a viable pursuit for philosophy in the wake of Deleuze. This chapter is intended as a “regional application” of Grant’s presentation of Schelling onto philosophy of language and religion. It is important to stress straight-off that, while language and the numinous may well be two of the deconstructionist’s favourite tools for undermining theoretical discourse, this chapter has no such aim.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Marx and Poetic Form in the Communist Manifesto
    FILOZOFIA ___________________________________________________________________________Roč. 71, 2016, č. 4 EPIC OR TRAGEDY? KARL MARX AND POETIC FORM IN THE COMMUNIST MANIFESTO JASON BARKER, Department of British and American Language and Culture, Kyung Hee University, South Korea BARKER, J.: Epic or Tragedy? Karl Marx and Poetic Form in The Communist Mani- festo FILOZOFIA 71, 2016, No. 4, pp. 316-327 Although The Communist Manifesto of 1848 was clearly not intended as a work of poetry, this article considers the merits of reading it according to the aesthetic criteria of epic poetry and of tragedy respectively. Following a brief treatment of the role of poetry in Karl Marx’s evolution as a philosopher and critic, the article then specu- lates that the identification of certain poetic themes in the text can aid our under- standing of the Manifesto’s political meaning, particularly in light of the “dialectical Prometheanism” that played such a defining role in Marx’s intellectual and political universe. Keywords: Dialectics − Epic − Odyssey − Prometheus − Prometheanism − Marx Introduction: Prometheus Bound and Unbound. Karl Marx’s favorite poet was Aeschylus and many personal episodes suggest the former’s incarnation as a modern Prometheus. In March 1843 the Rheinische Zeitung – which at the time was one of the largest subscription newspapers in Germany – was suppressed by the Prussian authorities and Marx resigned as its editor. A political cartoon of the period, now famous, was pub- lished depicting Marx bound to a printing press with a Prussian eagle biting out his liver. The final issue of the Rheinische Zeitung carried the following short poem: Our mast blew down, but we were not affrighted, The angry gods could never make us bend.
    [Show full text]
  • HISTORY and EVENT in ALAIN BADIOU Quentin Meillassoux, Translated by Thomas Nail1
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 12 • 2011 • 1 - 11 HISTORY AND EVENT IN ALAIN BADIOU Quentin Meillassoux, translated by Thomas Nail1 I would like to lay out for you the main theoretical decisions in the philosophy of Alain Badiou concerning the themes of today’s seminar: history and event.2 I do not speak as a disciple of Alain Badiou, because I develop philosophical positions distinct from his: but it seems important to me, that if one seeks to enter into a conceptual contemporaneity with the Marxist and Post-Marxist demands of politics and history, that one do so with the full scope of Badiou’s system in view, a system, now built around his two principle books Being and Event (BE) and Logics of Worlds (LW). This philosophy is particularly complex, but it seems to me that one can bring it into view through the two notions of history and event. I will thus attempt to explain a nodal and seemingly paradoxical thesis of Badiou’s: that there is only a history of the eternal, because only the eternal proceeds from the event. In other words: there is only a history of truths insofar as all truth is strictly eternal and impossible to reduce to any relativism. Badiou refuses therefore two antithetical positions: on the one hand that there can be eternal truths deprived as such of their historicity—a position proper to classical metaphysics—and on the other hand conversely that there can be no eternal truth, all discursive statements being irremediably inscribed in a historico-cultural context that strictly delimits the scope of truth to the particular instance that it supports.
    [Show full text]
  • Quentin Meillassoux and Florian Hecker Talk Hyperchaos
    DOCUMENT UFD001 Florian Hecker Quentin Meillassoux Robin Mackay Speculative Solution: Quentin Meillassoux and Florian Hecker Talk Hyperchaos This conversation took place during the development of Florian Hecker’s piece Speculative Solution, an Urbanomic commission that explored Quentin Meillassoux’s concept URBANOMIC / DOCUMENTS of ‘Hyperchaos’ URBANOMIC.COM Chez Meillassoux, Paris, 22 July 2010 certain sounds. And rather than the idea of making a sound directly ‘out of’ chaos, I was interested in how it could be used to explore this notion of sur- prise and abrupt change: to bring this extreme dy- namic form into the piece. This object or artifact we end up with will not represent something—it wouldn’t be a recording of an instal- lation, it wouldn’t be a sonification or illustration of your concepts FLORIAN HECKER: I’m very interested in this notion of Then as I looked into the book more, this is some- surprise and sudden change in sound; so that one thing that to me seemed to have a certain feed- state of something could change into something to- back with what you’re writing, when you talk about tally different at times during the piece, and there Hume’s billiard table: that the absence of constant would be no apparent connection from the process laws would change the conditions outside the ta- that manifests one sonic structure to the next one. ble, and not only the actions happening between When Robin pointed out your book [After Finitude1] the billiard balls. And what Robin and I spoke about to me, at the time I was working on Acid in the Style this morning was how something like this possibility of David Tudor, which had this very direct, maybe of constant change could manifest itself in a piece literal, idea of a quasi-sonification of chaotic equa- that would not be merely a sonification of the idea, tions as the source of sound.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Christoph Cox, Jenny Jaskey, and Suhail Malik
    Introduction Christoph Cox, Jenny Jaskey, and Suhail Malik Realism and materialism have become important watchwords in intellectual and cultural discourse today. Despite their di!erences, these philosophical stances propose that thought can think outside itself, that reality can be known without its being shaped by and for human comprehension. This position sharply contrasts with the philosophical and cultural view dominant over the last half century, a view that a"rms the indispensability of interpretation, discourse, textuality, signi#cation, ideology, and power. Diverse as they are, the theoretical pro- grams that constitute this latter orthodoxy (notably phenomenology, hermeneu- tics, post- structuralism, deconstruction, and psychoanalysis) maintain that our apprehension of the natural and social worlds is either constituted or mediated by a discursive #eld or a cognitive subject, and that nothing—or nothing mean- ingful—exists outside of discourse or its socially- organized construction. In short, this orthodoxy has been staunchly anti-realist. Today’s realism and materialism explicitly challenge many of these now prevalent assumptions of cultural practice and theoretical inquiry. Realism Materialism Art (RMA) presents a snapshot of the emerging and rapidly changing set of ideas, practices, and challenges proposed by contemporary realisms and materialisms, re$ecting their nascent reworking of art, philosophy, culture, theory, and science, among other #elds. Further, RMA strives to expand the hori- zons and terms of engagement with
    [Show full text]