197 DISCUSSION NOTE Prime Matter: a Rejoinder WILLIAM CHARLTON

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

197 DISCUSSION NOTE Prime Matter: a Rejoinder WILLIAM CHARLTON DISCUSSION NOTE Prime Matter: a Rejoinder WILLIAM CHARLTON I In 1956 Hugh R. King attacked the traditional view that Aristotle postulates what the tradition calls 'prime matter'. He drew replies from Friedrich Solmsen in 1958 and A. R. Lacey in 1965. In an appendix to my translation of Physics I-II in 1970 I offered independent arguments for a position similar to King's. My arguments were criticized by H. M. Robinson in 1974 and R. M. Dancy in 1978. Now C. J. F. Williams, in another appendix, though he thinks that Solmsen and Robinson have 'made out their case', makes it out afresh with special reference to the De Generatione et Corruptione. If Williams is to escape the charge of flogging a dead horse, I must attempt a rejoinder. What exactly is the doctrine which some of us deny, and others assert, that Aristotle held? Williams formulates it as follows (p. 211): When one element, e.g. water, changes into another, e.g. air, there is some under- lying matter which loses the quality of coldness and acquires its contrary, heat. This underlying matter, which persists through change, is not itself perceptible, nor is it anything in actuality ... although it is ... all things in potentiality. It is not body, but it is potentially so. At first that sounds plain enough. The friends of prime matter, however, do not pretend that it 'is anywhere in the physical world "actually" present' (Solmsen p. 245). It can exist 'only as actualized in some determinate matter - i.e. in one of the elements' (Robinson p. 168).That being so, there will be no empirically discoverable difference between a world which contains prime matter and a world such as King and I wish to impute to Aristotle, in which there is nothing more basic that the elements, and they change into one another without there being anything that remains. Is there even a conceptual difference? Or is the difference between saying that nothing remains and saying that prime matter remains, purely one of words? Recent friends of prime matter have concentrated on verbal evidence. They assemble texts in which they claim Aristotle speaks as if there were prime matter, and try to explain away texts in which other people claim he speaks as if there were not. In the next two sections I shall go through the texts which are deployed on either side. I may say here, however, that this microscopic approach can take us only a certain way. I shall argue that no passage is decisive in favour of the friends of prime matter, but they maintain that no passage is decisive against them. In the last section, therefore, I shall attempt more of an aerial view. Although there could be no physical evidence for or against prime matter, there are certain metaphysical principles which require it. I shall enquire whether Aristotle held any of these principles; the question whether or not he believed in prime matter really comes down to the question how far, if at all, it is demanded by his philosophy as a whole. 197 II Without necessarily proclaiming himself an out and out Popperian the proposer of an interpretation should say what he would consider proof that his interpretation was wrong. My view that Aristotle did not employ the notion of prime matter would be refuted by a text like: Of our predecessors, some say that all things come from one thing as matter, such as water or fire, others that things come from several. That all things come from one is true; but it is not water or fire or anything like that, but something undetermined and unlimited, like Anaximander's Unlimited except that that was separable and this is not. or When water comes to be out of air or air out of water, there is always something which remains and which was first water and then air; in itself this is neither a definite thing nor of a definite quality or amount. It would not be hard to translate these statements into Aristotelian-sounding Greek or to find places in Aristotle's works into which they might be inserted. That no such statement can be found it itself an indication that Aristotle did not believe in prime matter. The passages actually adduced by Solmsen, Robinson, Dancy and Williams, which I shall now run through, are considerably less explicit. (1) Phys. I 192a25-34.Robinson argues that since Aristotle says that if matter passed away it would ultimately arrive at itself, he must be talking about the lowest kind of matter. Either this is prime matter or it is the elements. If we say it is the elements, then since in a13-14 Aristotle speaks of matter as remaining, we must admit he thinks that when the elements change into one another, there is something which remains. But this will be prime matter. So either way Aristotle accepts prime matter (p. 175). To this argument I reply, first, that it is temerarious to apply what Aristotle says in a 1 3- 14,where he is trying to accommodate Plato's views to his, to the apparently separate discussion of a24-34. Secondly, the later passage need not be about the lowest sort of matter. To suppose it is does not help us to understand 'If it is destroyed, it is to this that it will arrive in the end'. The thought behind that is surely the simple one that since matter is what things arise out of and pass away into, it does not make sense to speak of matter itself as coming to be and passing away. It is not matter but 'composites' that do that. (2) Phys. IV 209b8-12, 211b29-36, 217a21-7. Dancy mentions these passages, though without putting them forward as formal evidence. I discussed 217a 21-7 in my appendix pp. 138-9,and I shall touch on 209b8-12 below. 211b31-6may be translated: Just as in alteration there is something which is now pale and again dark, and now hard and again soft, which is why we say that the matter is something real, so also place seems to exist through a similar appearance except that the former exists because what was air, that is now water [o fiv TovTOvvv `v8wp]whereas place exists because where was air, there is now water [o'vfiv ài¡p, Èv'Texù6'iaTt vvv In a different context, 8 fiv &Ap,To'vTO puf v8wp might be very strong evidence. I do not think it will bear much weight here. Aristotle is discussing place, not the transformation of the elements. He starts by talking about alteration. And he switches to the transformation 198 .
Recommended publications
  • Philosophie Antique , Comptes Rendus Mathilde Brémond, Lectures De Mélissos
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Mathilde BRÉMOND, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation des témoignages sur Mélissos de Samos Citation for published version: Harriman, B 2019, 'Mathilde BRÉMOND, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation des témoignages sur Mélissos de Samos', Philosophie Antique. <https://journals.openedition.org/philosant/1944> Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Philosophie Antique General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 26. Sep. 2021 Philosophie antique Problèmes, Renaissances, Usages Comptes rendus Mathilde BRÉMOND, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation des témoignages sur Mélissos de Samos Berlin/Boston, Walter De Gruyter, 2019 (Studia Praesocratica), 595 p., ISBN : 978-3-11-054288-2. Benjamin Harriman Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosant/1944 ISSN: 2648-2789 Publisher Presses universitaires du Septentrion Brought to you by Ecole Normale Supérieure Paris This text was automatically generated on 10 May 2019. Mathilde Brémond, Lectures de Mélissos. Édition, traduction et interprétation..
    [Show full text]
  • Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy the Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of Its Impending End
    Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End A doctoral thesis by O. H. Linderborg Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Engelska Parken, 7-0042, Thunbergsvägen 3H, Uppsala, Monday, 3 September 2018 at 14:00 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Faculty examiner: Docent Elton Barker (Open University). Abstract Linderborg, O. H. 2018. Herodotus and the Origins of Political Philosophy. The Beginnings of Western Thought from the Viewpoint of its Impending End. 224 pp. Uppsala: Department of Linguistics and Philology, Uppsala University. ISBN 978-91-506-2703-9. This investigation proposes a historical theory of the origins of political philosophy. It is assumed that political philosophy was made possible by a new form of political thinking commencing with the inauguration of the first direct democracies in Ancient Greece. The pristine turn from elite rule to rule of the people – or to δημοκρατία, a term coined after the event – brought with it the first ever political theory, wherein fundamentally different societal orders, or different principles of societal rule, could be argumentatively compared. The inauguration of this alternative-envisioning “secular” political theory is equaled with the beginnings of classical political theory and explained as the outcome of the conjoining of a new form of constitutionalized political thought (cratistic thinking) and a new emphasis brought to the inner consistency of normative reasoning (‘internal critique’). The original form of political philosophy, Classical Political Philosophy, originated when a political thought launched, wherein non-divinely sanctioned visions of transcendence of the prevailing rule, as well as of the full range of alternatives disclosed by Classical Political Theory, first began to be envisioned.
    [Show full text]
  • David Sansone: Curriculum Vitae
    DAVID SANSONE Curriculum Vitae (tantulum si “vita” adpellandum est) • Education Hamilton College, A.B. (1968) The University of Wisconsin, M.A. (1969) The University of Wisconsin, Ph.D. (1972) Dissertation title: “Aeschylean Metaphors for Intellectual Activity” (directed by Friedrich Solmsen) • Employment The University of Hawaii Assistant Professor (1972-1974) The University of Illinois Assistant Professor (1974-1980) Associate Professor (1980-1988) Professor (1988-2010) Professor emeritus (2011- ) Chair, Department of the Classics (1996-1999) Head, Department of the Classics (2008-2010) • Membership in Professional Organizations The American Philological Association Member, Board of Directors (1998-2001) The Cambridge Philological Society The Classical Association The International Plutarch Society The Society for the Promotion of Hellenic Studies Archaeological Institute of America • Editorial Positions Editorial Board for Monographs, The American Philological Association (1986-1988) Editorial Board of Classical Philology (1988-present) Editorial Board of Illinois Classical Studies (1984, 1987-present) Associate Editor, Illinois Classical Studies (1989-1992) Editor, Illinois Classical Studies (1993-2000) Editorial Board, Bryn Mawr Classical Review (1994-2004) refereed manuscripts for Illinois Classical Studies, Classical Philology, Transactions of the American Philological Association, Phoenix, Classical World, The Classical Journal, Papers on Language and Literature, Cambridge University Press, Oxford University Press, Harvard University
    [Show full text]
  • Homer and Hesiod
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Departmental Papers (Classical Studies) Classical Studies at Penn 1-1-1997 Homer and Hesiod Ralph M. Rosen University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Rosen, R. M. (1997). Homer and Hesiod. Retrieved from https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers/7 Postprint version. Published in A New Companion to Homer, edited by Barry Powell and Ian Morris, Mnemosyne: Bibliotheca classica Batava, Supplementum 163 (New York: Brill, 1997), pages 463-488. The author has asserted his right to include this material in ScholarlyCommons@Penn. This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/classics_papers/7 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Homer and Hesiod Abstract One of the most frustrating aspects of Homeric studies is that so little literary material outside the Homeric corpus itself survives to enhance our understanding of the cultural landscape of the period. Recent scholarship suggests that a large and diverse poetic tradition lay behind the figure we refer to as "Homer," but little of it survives. Indeed we have little continuous written Greek for another century. The one exception is Hesiod, who composed two extant poems, the Theogony and Works and Days, and possibly several others, including the Shield of Heracles and the Catalogue of Women. As we shall see, while Hesiodic poetry was not occupied specifically with heroic themes, it was part of the same formal tradition of epic, sharing with Homer key metrical, dialectal, and dictional features.
    [Show full text]
  • Professor of Classics and Comparative Literature ADDRESS
    1 CURRICULUM VITAE: JOSEPH DUFFIELD REED 8 February 2018 POSITION: Professor of Classics and Comparative Literature ADDRESS: Department of Classics [email protected] Brown University [email protected] Macfarlane House 48 College Street Providence, RI 02912 EDUCATION: B.A. magna cum laude, Classics (Greek and Latin), May 1987, Yale College A.M., Classics, June 1991, Stanford University Non-degree, Keble College, Oxford, Fall 1991 Ph.D., Classics, June 1993, Stanford University FIELDS OF SCHOLARLY INTEREST: Special fields: Augustan poetry, Greek bucolic poetry, Adonis myth and cult General fields: Roman poetry, Hellenistic poetry, early modern Latin poetry ACADEMIC HONORS AND AWARDS: Friedrich Solmsen Fellow, Institute for Research in the Humanities, University of Wisconsin at Madison (1996-97) Mellon Postdoctoral Teaching-Research Fellow, Andrew D. White Center for the Humanities, Cornell University (1997-98) Fellow of the Fondazione Lorenzo Valla (since 2007) Director’s Guest, Civitella Ranieri (June 2016) TEACHING: Stanford University Teaching Fellow, Classics, 1991-93 The Ohio State University Instructor, Classics, 1993-96 Cornell University Mellon Teaching-Research Fellow, 1997-98 Hutton Assistant Professor, Classics, 1998-2001 2 The University of Michigan Assistant Professor of Greek and Latin, 2001-07 Associate Professor of Greek and Latin, 2007-09 Brown University Professor of Classics, from 2009 Professor of Comparative Literature, from 2010 Undergraduate teaching includes intermediate and advanced courses on Herodotus, Greek bucolic, Lucretius, Cicero, Catullus, Virgil, Horace, Ovid, Seneca; lecture courses on Roman Civilization, Greek and Roman literature, mythology, ancient epic, ancient novel; beginning Greek and Latin (including intensive courses) Graduate teaching includes seminars on Catullus, Virgil, Ovid, Latin Love Elegy, Hellenistic poetry, Bucolic poetry, the epyllion; Latin literature survey; Greek and Latin prose composition Dissertation Committees (Chair): K.
    [Show full text]
  • The Relationship Between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium Lorelle D
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Love's Lack: The Relationship between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium Lorelle D. Lamascus Marquette University Recommended Citation Lamascus, Lorelle D., "Love's Lack: The Relationship between Poverty and Eros in Plato's Symposium" (2010). Dissertations (2009 -). Paper 71. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/71 LOVE’S LACK: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN POVERTY AND EROS IN PLATO’S SYMPOSIUM By Lorelle D. Lamascus A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, In partial fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy Milwaukee, Wisconsin December 2010 ABSTRACT LOVE’S LACK: THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN EROS AND POVERTY IN PLATO’S SYMPOSIUM Lorelle D. Lamascus Marquette University, 2010 This dissertation responds to a long-standing debate among scholars regarding the nature of Platonic Eros and its relation to lack. The more prominent account of Platonic Eros presents the lack of Eros as a deficiency or need experienced by the lover with respect to the object needed, lacked, or desired, so that the nature of Eros is construed as self-interested or acquisitive, subsisting only so long as the lover lacks the beloved object. This dissertation argues that such an interpretation neglects the different senses of lack present in the Symposium and presents an alternative interpretation of Eros based on the Symposium ’s presentation of Eros as the child of Poverty and Resource. Chapter one examines the origin and development of the position that Platonic Eros is acquisitive or egocentric and the influence this has had on subsequent interpretations of Plato’s thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Sorabji-1974-Body-And-Soul-In-Aristotle.Pdf
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Body and Soul in Aristotle Author(s): Richard Sorabji Source: Philosophy, Vol. 49, No. 187 (Jan., 1974), pp. 63-89 Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of Royal Institute of Philosophy Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3749985 Accessed: 22/10/2010 05:45 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Cambridge University Press and Royal Institute of Philosophy are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org Body and Soul in Aristotle Richard Sorabji PART I : Aristotle's View (i) Interpretations of Aristotle's account of the relation between body and soul have been widely divergent.
    [Show full text]
  • The Tradition About Zeno of Elea Re-Examined
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The ocS iety for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1969 The rT adition about Zeno of Elea Re-Examined Friedrich Solmsen University of Wisconsin-Madison Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Solmsen, Friedrich, "The rT adition about Zeno of Elea Re-Examined" (1969). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 88. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/88 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. •. Q ••, _ _(tpf, ,) MMJQ!fi¢9\U)P ..,"4_¥ s Ar;..P- \qt,� .F·•. Friedrich Sol:msen The Tradition about Zeno of Elea Re-examined Among students of Greek philosophy there is al.most complete unanimity· regarding the tenets upheld by Zeno of' Elea and the purpose of his treatise as a whole. Although by no means abundant, the verbatim fragments, the second-hand reports about his arguments, and the statements defining his philosophical intention are considered an adequate basis for definite conclusions. The paper hereby submitted does not aim at replacing one theory by another but has the more modest objective of examining the eVidence on which the communis opinio so confidently rests and to show how .much has been too readily accepted as certain .
    [Show full text]
  • The Tradition About Zeno of Elea Re-Examined
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1969 The Tradition about Zeno of Elea Re-Examined Friedrich Solmsen University of Wisconsin-Madison Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Solmsen, Friedrich, "The Tradition about Zeno of Elea Re-Examined" (1969). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 88. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/88 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. •. Q ••, _ _(tpf, ,) MMJQ!fi¢9\U)P ..,"4_¥ s Ar;..P- \qt,� .F·•. Friedrich Sol:msen The Tradition about Zeno of Elea Re-examined Among students of Greek philosophy there is al.most complete unanimity· regarding the tenets upheld by Zeno of' Elea and the purpose of his treatise as a whole. Although by no means abundant, the verbatim fragments, the second-hand reports about his arguments, and the statements defining his philosophical intention are considered an adequate basis for definite conclusions. The paper hereby submitted does not aim at replacing one theory by another but has the more modest objective of examining the eVidence on which the communis opinio so confidently rests and to show how .much has been too readily accepted as certain .
    [Show full text]
  • A BIBLIOGRAPHICAL and PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY Infinity in the Presocratics: a Bmliographical and PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY
    INFINITY IN THE PRESOCRA TICS: A BIBLIOGRAPHICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY Infinity in the Presocratics: A BmLIOGRAPHICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL STUDY by LEO SWEENEY, S. J. The Catholic University of America Foreword by JOSEPH OWENS, C. S8. R. Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies II MARTINUS NIJHOFF / THE HAGUE /1972 @ 1972 by Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands All rights reserved, including the right to translate or to reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form ISBN-13:978-90-247-1170-3 e-1SBN-13:978-94-010-2729-8 DOl: 10.1007/978-94-010-2729-8 To Lee and Adrian Powell, James, John, Jeffrey, Jean, Jay, Jane, Jerry and Mary Ann TABLE OF CONTENTS Abbreviations IX Permissions XIV Foreword by Joseph Owens xvn Introduction xx Mondolfo XXIII Sinnige xxvn Methodology and acknowledgements XXXI CHAPTER ONE: SECONDARY LITERATURE ON ANAXIMANDER 1 Ancient Sources 2 Recent Studies on Anaximander 5 Vlastos, Jaeger, Burch, Kraus 5 Cherniss, Cornford, Matson, McDiarmid 8 HOlscher, Kirk 14 Wisniewski, Kahn 20 Guazzoni Foa, Solmsen, Classen 26 Paul Seligman 29 Guthrie, Gottschalk 33 F. M. Cleve 39 Stokes, Bicknell 41 Other Studies? 49 CHAPTER Two: ANAXIMANDER AND OTHER IONIANS 55 Anaximander 55 Anaximenes, Xenophanes, Heraclitus 65 Conclusion 73 CHAPTER THREE: PYTHAGORAS 74 J. E. Raven 75 vm TABLE OF CONTENTS J. A. Philip 84 Conclusions 91 CHAPTER FOUR: THE ELEATICS 93 Parmenides 93 Burnet, Raven and Guthrie 94 Joseph Owens 97 Loenen 99 Taran 102 Conclusions 105 Zeno 110 Jesse De Boer 112 H. N. Lee 117 Conclusions 119 Melissus 124 Fragment 9
    [Show full text]
  • Christianity's Pre-Constantine Survival
    Xavier University Exhibit Honors Bachelor of Arts Undergraduate 2020-5 A Living Faith: Christianity’s Pre-Constantine Survival Derek Allen Seifert Xavier University, Cincinnati, OH Follow this and additional works at: https://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, Classical Archaeology and Art History Commons, Classical Literature and Philology Commons, and the Other Classics Commons Recommended Citation Seifert, Derek Allen, "A Living Faith: Christianity’s Pre-Constantine Survival" (2020). Honors Bachelor of Arts. 42. https://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab/42 This Capstone/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate at Exhibit. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Bachelor of Arts by an authorized administrator of Exhibit. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Living Faith: Christianity’s Pre-Constantine Survival Derek Seifert CLAS 399 Father Norton, Doctor Byrne, Doctor Dewey Table of Contents Précis Page 1 Author's Note Page 2 Introduction Page 4 Chapter 1: The Cults of Contemporaries Page 6 Chapter 1.1: The Cult of Eleusis Page 7 Chapter 1.2: The Cult of Isis Page 13 Chapter 1.3: The Cult of Mithras Page 18 Chapter 2: Christianity Page 23 Chapter 2.1: Political Aggression and Social Exclusion Page 23 Chapter 2.2: What Purpose Did They Have? Page 26 Chapter 2.2a: The Theological Ideas Page 27 Chapter 2.2b: Testimonies Page 31 Conclusion Page 37 Works Cited Page 38 Précis In my thesis, I argue that the beliefs and practices of Christianity helped it to not only coexist with but survive beyond the cults that were prevalent and more established.
    [Show full text]
  • Emendations in Cosmological Texts
    EMENDATIONS IN COSMOLOGICAL TEXTS PI., Tim. 46 c 7: The mechanism of vision has been ex­ plained and Plato now points out that what he has set forth is avvaina, secondary causes unrelated to mind and soul. The philosopher prefers the purpose cause which is a manifestation of intelligent order in the physical world. d7ff.: rov bi voil "ai buaT17fJ:YJ~ eeaarr}v avay"'YJ ra~ r* lJflgJeovo~ rpVasw~ alria~ newra~ flsra&w"stv, öaat bi vn'aJtJtwv p,& "tvOVflBVWV, ercea b' e~ avay,,'YJ~ "tvovvrwv yiyvovrat, bsvdea~. The second half of the sentence öaat bi... bBVdea~ must contain a description of the mechanical causes and we understand that they take the form of some ob­ jects (b) moved by others (vn'aJtJtwv, a) and in turn moving a third group (BrSea, c). To the one genitive rfj~ lJflgJeovo~ rpVasw~ corresponds the other ..."tvOVflBVWV, BrSea bi . .. "tvovvrwv; and in both instances the genitives determine a type of alriat, since clearly ra~ rfj~ lJflgJeovo~ rpVasw~ alria~ (c8) is taken up by öaat bi (seil. alrim) in the second half of the sentence. This symmetry is disturbed by yiyvovrat (12) whose presence seems due to a mis­ understanding of vn' which is to be taken with aJtJtwv but could easily be misunderstood as introducing everything that follows down to and including "tvovvrwv. In Soph. 265 c, a passage ad­ duced by Cornford (Plato's Cosmology 157, n. I) as support for alriat yiyvovrat the genitive forms apart of a quite different con­ struction. It seems necessary to excise y{yvovrat. Tim. 52 b 6: The existence of xwea and the fact that sense perceived objects move into and out oE a place (rono~, 52a 5-7) causes serious errors concerfling the true realities.
    [Show full text]