Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Adam Smith on Freedom and Futurity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Adam Smith on Freedom and Futurity City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 6-2016 Claiming Time: Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Adam Smith on Freedom and Futurity Jennifer Corby Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/1276 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] CLAIMING TIME: THOMAS HOBBES, JOHN LOCKE, AND ADAM SMITH ON FUTURITY AND FREEDOM by JENNIFER CORBY A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Political Science in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, The City University of New York 2016 © 2016 JENNIFER CORBY All Rights Reserved ii Claiming Time: Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Adam Smith on Freedom and Futurity by Jennifer Corby This manuscript has been read and accepted by the Graduate Faculty in Political Science in satisfaction of the dissertation requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Susan Buck-Morss Date Chair of Examining Committee (Print) Chair of Examining Committee (Signature) Alyson Cole Date Executive Officer (Print) Executive Officer (Signature) Supervisory Committee Susan Buck-Morss Gary Wilder Uday Mehta THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii Abstract Claiming Time: Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Adam Smith on Freedom and Futurity by Jennifer Corby Advisor: Susan Buck-Morss This dissertation engages the philosophy of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Adam Smith through the lens of time. By first analyzing their earlier works on the nature of self- consciousness, it demonstrates that each offers a theory of subjectivity that, despite important differences, shares a singular point of distinction from those that typified early modern thought. Against the predominant view that human freedom necessitates immaterial agency, each theorizes a materialist agent that is able to overcome the determinism of the material world by way of the temporal nature of subjectivity. Each understands self-consciousness to be constituted by an extension of memory into the past and imagination into the future, which, they argue, allows humans to act beyond, or in spite of, the present that would otherwise determine behavior. In conceiving subjectivity materially and temporally, their theories of freedom center equally on the futurity that makes freedom possible and the social context of its expression. As such, rather than simply being the implicit foundations for political thought, this dissertation demonstrates that their theories of subjectivity are necessarily political concepts—political concepts that are foundational to liberal thought. Through analyzing the particular methods each employs in theorizing the relationship between freedom and futurity, this dissertation offers new interpretations of their work, while charting movements between their ideas in the interest of opening the historical, neoliberal present to temporal analysis. iv Acknowledgements In the process of writing this dissertation, I learned a great deal about Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Adam Smith. But I also learned a good deal about the generosity of the human spirit. Without the time and support of my colleagues, family, and friends, this project would not be what it is. I would like to thank, first and foremost, my committee, each of whom spent hours helping me to rethink, revise, reframe my work. I would particularly like to thank my chair and mentor, Susan Buck-Morss, who is a continual source of personal, professional, and intellectual inspiration. Her perceptive questions and keen ability to synthesize my work, regularly allows me to see new possibilities within it, and to become a better mentor to my own students. Gary Wilder also deserves special thanks, as I could not have asked for a better reader. If you ever have the opportunity to have Gary read your material, take it. His ability to hone in on key insights lurking within broad themes has played no small role in the structuring of this work. I am also incredibly grateful to have had Uday Mehta on my committee, as his forceful criticisms and words of encouragement are always delivered at just the right time. Collectively, I have Susan, Gary, and Uday to thank for making me a braver, bolder writer. Writing this dissertation was also made possible by the financial support and academic opportunities I received from the CUNY Graduate Center. In my first years of study, I was awarded a Graduate Teaching Fellowship, and placed at City College. It was there that I met John Krinsky, then chair of the political science department. My years at City College were wonderful, in no small part because of John’s support. He granted me the freedom to develop new courses, including one focusing on my dissertation research, The Politics of Time. I also have to thank my City College students; in working through this material with them, I likely learned as much from them as they learned from me. City College also holds a special place in v my heart, because that is where my friendship with Marshall Berman also developed. Marshall was an enduring source of patience, sensitivity, and kindness, and I like to think that a small part of him lives on in the impact he has had on my own teaching and writing. It was through my friendship with Marshall that I was introduced to Michael Sorkin, of Terreform. A small portion of the research in this dissertation has been published with Terreform’s Urban Research imprint, in Adventures in Modernism: Thinking with Marshall Berman, a book which I also edited. My research also benefited from the Mellon Foundation Dissertation Fellowship I was awarded with the Committee on Globalization and Social Change at the Graduate Center. The annual theme during my fellowship was temporality, and the opportunity to meet weekly with an international, transdisciplinary cohort to share and discuss ideas about time was singularly enriching. I am truly grateful to each of the committee members, who generously shared their own work and helped me to develop my own. My work was further facilitated by the Instructional Technology Fellowship which I was awarded with the Macaulay Honors College. In addition to providing generous funding, this fellowship also introduced me to a cohort of amazing and dedicated colleagues. Our fearless leader, Joe Ugoretz, will forever be the standard bearer for what a supportive and trusting professional mentor should be. And though I have learned much from each of the ITFs, I am especially thankful for Gwen Shaw, whose interruptions into my late night writing were always a welcome reprieve. Beyond financial and professional support, the Graduate Center has also been a wonderful place for finding a supportive network of friends. I am incredibly grateful to Dr. Daniel Rothenberg and the students of the dissertation completion seminar. Their patience, generosity, and insights were an unparalleled source of support. I have to thank Alec Magnet, in vi particular, for helping me to see my work and my life through new (and kinder) eyes. My time at the Graduate Center also brought me to my life gurus, Shawna Brandle, Janet Reilly, and Tricia Stapleton, each of whom are rock stars, professionally and personally. I am also thankful for my family, which has been an incredible and abiding source of love and support. My mother, Susan Seymour, has been a lifelong source of encouragement, not only in words, but in deeds. Her entrepreneurship, ingenuity, devotion, and determination, have taught me to be independent, creative, and caring. I also have to thank her husband, Jim Seymour, for bravely diving in to the cacophony and chaos that is the “Corby Clan,” and for his kindness, patience, and humor. I am also grateful to my brother Chris Corby, not only because he is the great diplomat of the family, but because playing hours of Dr. Mario with him is a lifelong outlet for stress relief. And I am thankful for my youngest brother, Tyler Corby, who has grown into an amazing, adventurous, thoughtful young adult, and who now mentors me just as much as I mentor him (#truecorbs). I am also incredibly grateful to my husband’s family, who have become my own in the truest sense. Dan and Susan Aroosi have shown me the power of patience, compassion, and perseverance. My sisters-in-law, Lauren and Mallory, have taught me the importance of laughing, loyalty, and a stash of good candy. And last, but only because she is not least, I want to thank my best friend, Melanie Cassels. Through teenage shenanigans, cross-country moves, crises, and conquests, she has been a constant source of advice, comfort, companionship, and when I need it, a good push. We have often been told that each of us are fuel to the other’s flame. And it’s true—together we burn bright. vii For Jamie. This leap of faith is for, and because of, you. viii Table of Contents Introduction 1 Project Inspiration 1 The Materialist Turn of the Early Modern Moment 2 Chapter Outline 8 Paradoxes of Possibility: Empowerment and Anxiety in Thomas Hobbes’s Materialist Subject 14 Introduction 14 Hobbes’s Break with the Past: The Annihilation Hypothesis 21 Finding Common Ground 25 Hobbes’s Modern Mechanism 31 Materialist Subjectivity: The Temporal Subject 34 Locating Materialist Agency: Supplanting the Will with Imagination 39 Of Futures Insecure:
Recommended publications
  • The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume
    The British Empiricism Locke, Berkeley and Hume copyleft: nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 1 The problem of knowledge • Please, look out of the window (or into the box, or just in front of you…) and answer the following questions: ‣ What do you see? ‣ Are you sure that what you see is what truly exists out there? ‣ What do you know about it? ‣ How do you know it? ‣ What make you sure of it? • Here you are: this is the problem of knowledge! • Now try to formalise it in a single question or definition. copyleft:nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 1 A long way behind In a certain way, we could say that the problem of knowledge is the problem of philosophy itself, since its birth. • Think for example on this quotations: Parmenides: «the same thing is for thinking as is for being” Eraclitus: «The things of which there is sight, hearing, experience, I prefer». (But he also says: «Poor witnesses for men are their eyes and ears if they have barbarian souls» Gorgia: «Nothing exists; Even if something exists, nothing can be known about it; and Even if something can be known about it, knowledge about it can't be communicated to others. Even if it can be communicated, it cannot be understood». • Or try to imagine the discussion between Plato and Aristotle in the famous Raffaello’s School of Athens. • Now try to build a mind-map of all the different answers to the problem of knowledge given by the philosophers you already know copyleft:nicolazuin.2018 | nowxhere.wordpress.com 2 The terrible heritage of Descartes: The modern problem of knowledge originates from the conclusions of Descartes’s research, which was inspired by the successful advancement of geometry and natural sciences and was aimed to find a certain knowledge for philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Essential ADAM SMITH ADAM SMITH the Essential
    The Essential The Essential ADAM SMITH ADAM SMITH The Essential Udetiort elintrem popteride fac re nostemusa porae tem in te iaes moves- cid nequastil viliu menatiae te pris. Ips, quiusus er que fuidemquon supica; novero etidemusque cae, Cationsus ad Caticatus opultilius et; nes mante nonsulo sultilina comnitem praveriae fore cla nihi, Ti. Em tem inam num, nes SMITH ADAM conte curnit? Mulus. Evitem sis? Opiordica dit. Go es voltum omanunc iam nox maximil conduconiam. Quo voludem iam dientru ntuscru deperfe rcereo, quideme catiam tem potala restra? Quiderniu conem cone cones nonsum optis conorbit. Nem hostiquo elicon ac mored ina, pracia vitra prariciam Romnora torum, me etres hoca in rehenih iliemus rendam quam ret; Cupionf erorunum opublie ndemus erferfex none curem denatanum is cripio conem et, con dem tabenat icerei consilius, untem morit, paturaetrum te periosti publicus praecero ius fecte consis, que iae nos esse consustrunt. James Otteson by James Otteson Copyright © by the Fraser Institute. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical articles and reviews. Th e author of this publication has worked independently and opinions expressed by him are, therefore, his own, and do not necessarily refl ect the opinions of the Fraser Institute or its supporters, directors, or staff . Th is publication in no way implies that the Fraser Institute, its directors, or staff are in favour of, or oppose the passage of, any bill; or that they support or oppose any particular political party or candidate.
    [Show full text]
  • Experience and the Passage of Time∗
    Experience and the Passage of Time∗ Bradford Skow 1 Introduction Some philosophers believe that the passage of time is a real phenomenon. And some of them find a reason to believe this when they attend to features of their conscious experience. In fact this “argument from experience” is supposed to be one of the main arguments for passage. What exactly does this argument look like? Is it any good? There are in fact many different arguments from experience. I am not sure I understand them all. In this paper I want to talk about the three most interesting arguments that I do understand.1 I am going to argue that all three of them fail. ∗Published in Philosophical Perspectives 25: Metaphysics (2011), pp.359-387. 1I will not say anything about A. N. Prior’s “Thank Goodness That’s Over” argument (Prior 1959) because it is not an argument from experience (even though it is often said to be). Here is Prior’s argument: I can be glad that my ordeal is over without being glad that my ordeal is earlier than this thought or that my ordeal is earlier than 12 noon. But the latter two propositions are the propositions that some opponents of passage (the ones Prior knew) identified with the proposition that my ordeal is over. Prior concluded that the object of my propositional attitude is a proposition that only proponents of passage believe in. Phenomenal experience does not play an important role in this argument. True, there is some distinctive phenomenal “feel” that (sometimes? usually? always?) occurs when I am glad about something.
    [Show full text]
  • Time, Metaphysics Of
    Time, metaphysics of Keywords: Time, Presentism, Eternalism, Moving Spotlight View, A-theory, B-theory, Growing Block View, Temporal Experience, J. M. E. McTaggart Article Summary Metaphysics is the part of philosophy that asks questions about the nature of reality – about what there is, and what it is like. The metaphysics of time is the part of the philosophy of time that asks questions about the nature of temporal reality. One central such question is that of whether time passes or flows, or whether it has a dynamic aspect. By this metaphysicians mean something very specific: is one time metaphysically privileged in some way, and does this metaphysical privilege move on from time to time? A-theorists answer in the affirmative, and different A-theorists offer different ways of thinking about the metaphysical privilege involved. Some say the privilege consists in being the only time that exists (presentism). On presentism, only the present exists, but which time that is changes as time passes. Other A-theorists, known as growing block theorists, say the metaphysical privilege consists in being the latest time that exists. On the growing block view, the past and the present exist, but the future does not. As time passes, new times comes into existence. Yet another version of the A-theory says that all times exist, but that one time is metaphysically privileged because it is present in an absolute sense. This version of the A-theory is known as the moving spotlight theory. Different times gain the privilege in turn by becoming the one time that is present in an absolute sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & The
    Xavier University Exhibit Honors Bachelor of Arts Undergraduate 2015-4 Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime Andrew John Del Bene Xavier University - Cincinnati Follow this and additional works at: http://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, and the Ancient Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Del Bene, Andrew John, "Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime" (2015). Honors Bachelor of Arts. Paper 9. http://www.exhibit.xavier.edu/hab/9 This Capstone/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Undergraduate at Exhibit. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Bachelor of Arts by an authorized administrator of Exhibit. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Aristotle & Locke: Ancients and Moderns on Economic Theory & the Best Regime Andrew John Del Bene Honors Bachelor of Arts – Senior Thesis Project Director: Dr. Timothy Quinn Readers: Dr. Amit Sen & Dr. E. Paul Colella Course Director: Dr. Shannon Hogue I respectfully submit this thesis project as partial fulfillment for the Honors Bachelor of Arts Degree. I dedicate this project, and my last four years as an HAB at Xavier University, to my grandfather, John Francis Del Bene, who taught me that in life, you get out what you put in. Del Bene 1 Table of Contents Introduction — Philosophy and Economics, Ancients and Moderns 2 Chapter One — Aristotle: Politics 5 Community: the Household and the Πόλις 9 State: Economics and Education 16 Analytic Synthesis: Aristotle 26 Chapter Two — John Locke: The Two Treatises of Government 27 Community: the State of Nature and Civil Society 30 State: Economics and Education 40 Analytic Synthesis: Locke 48 Chapter Three — Aristotle v.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Hutcheson and Kant: Moral Sense and Moral Feeling Published In
    1 Hutcheson and Kant: Moral Sense and Moral Feeling Michael Walschots Published in Kant and the Scottish Enlightenment. Edited by Elizabeth Robinson and Chris W. Surprenant. London: Routledge, 2017. pg. 36 – 54. The eighteenth century is a rich and fascinating period in the history of Germany philosophy for a variety of reasons. Not least among these is the fact that German authors of the period somewhat extensively engaged with the writings of those in other European countries and beyond. The extent to which German philosophers engaged with eighteenth century British philosophy is an excellent example. Describing the reception of British philosophy in eighteenth century Germany, Manfred Kuehn writes that The works of Locke, Shaftsbury, Hutcheson, Hume, Smith, Ferguson, and almost every other British philosopher of note were full of problems that needed solutions and observations that needed to be explained, if German philosophy of the traditional sort was to succeed. (Kuehn 2001, 183-4) Although many German philosophers of the period could read English, the wide reception of these British authors was made possible in large part by the, in some cases rapid, translation of their texts into German. This is certainly true of the Scottish philosopher who will be the focus of this paper: Francis Hutcheson (1694-1747). A translation of Hutcheson’s posthumous System of Moral Philosophy, first published in 1755, was published just one year later in 1756. Translations of Hutcheson’s An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions (1728) and An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue (1725) followed somewhat soon thereafter, appearing in 1760 and 1762 respectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Mctaggart's Proof of the Unreality of Time
    McTaggart's proof of the unreality of time Jeff Speaks phil 20229 January 24, 2008 1 The A series and the B series . 1 2 Problems with the A-series . 2 2.1 Does the present move? . 3 2.2 McTaggart's argument that the A series is contradictory . 3 3 McTaggart's view that time is unreal . 5 4 Time without the A-series . 6 John (McTaggart Ellis) McTaggart was one of the most prominent British exponents of idealism in the late 19th and early 20th centuries. His most prominent work is The Nature of Existence (in two volumes) from which we read an excerpt. McTaggart's idealism consisted largely in the denial that what we usually take to be cen- tral features of reality are, in fact, real. Accordingly, much of his work was devoted to exposing contradictions, or difficulties, inherent in our ordinary picture of the world. Per- haps his most famous, ambitious, and influential such argument is his argument that our ordinary view that things exist in time is false. This was first systematically presented in his 1908 paper, `The Unreality of Time.' We will be looking at his later (1927) exposition of the argument. 1 The A series and the B series McTaggart's first central claim is that, as he puts it \Positions in time . are distinguished in two ways. Each position is Earlier than some and Later than some of the other positions. To constitute such a series there is required a transitive asymmetrical relation, and a collection of terms such that, of any two of them, either the first is in this relation to the second, or the second is in this relation to the first.
    [Show full text]
  • From Zarathustra to the Wisdom of Salomon Wolfgang Leidhold, Cologne [EVS: Panel 2 — Religious Experience : Eric Voegelin and Beyond]
    DRAFT - Seattle 2011 The Noetic Turn: From Zarathustra to the Wisdom of Salomon Wolfgang Leidhold, Cologne [EVS: Panel 2 — Religious Experience : Eric Voegelin and Beyond] Summary: Taking Eric Voegelin‘s theory of experience as a point of departure, this essay examines more closely the logic of experience (and of religious experience in particular). Voegelin‘s main thesis is that, since all ideas and concepts are based on experience, there is no „history of ideas― as an isolated process that is intelligible in itself but ideas must be studied and can only be understood if based on the founding experiences as their intelligible field. In an attempt to go beyond Voegelin‘s achievements, the paper sets ou by analyzing the structure of experience more closely. The results are applied to historic case-studies, starting with the Gathas of Zarathustra; neolithic myth and paleolithic symbolism are studied next; from here the analysis proceeds to Hindu and Daoist traditions, finally to some Old and New Testament sources. In the end, the findings are summarized as a new theory: the structure of experience varies not only regarding compactness and differentiation; but the experiental field itself is changing in terms of horizon, dimensions, and structure. As a consequence, experience and its symbolization are equivalent only if the structure is similar. The difference between „cultures― does not only regard the varying symbolizations of basically equivalent experiences, they are based on different modes of experience. Therefore we have to go one step beyond Eric Voegelin‘s achievements and study the history of experience. 1. Star Gazer One night as a young boy about twelve years of age I sat at home in the kitchen and looked out of the window at the nocturnal sky.
    [Show full text]
  • Dummett on Mctaggart's Proof of the Unreality of Time
    Dummett on McTaggart’s Proof of the Unreality of Time Brian Garrett Australian National University Abstract Michael Dummett’s paper “A Defence of McTaggart’s Proof of the Unreality of Time” put forward an ingenious interpretation of McTaggart’s famous proof. My aim in this discussion is not to assess the cogency of McTaggart’s reasoning, but to criticise Dummett’s interpretation of McTaggart. Keywords: McTaggart, Dummett, Time, Space, A-series. 1. Introduction The reasoning of McTaggart’s 1908 article “The Unreality of Time” runs as follows. We distinguish positions in time in two ways: a permanent B-series (in which events and facts are distinguished using the relations of earlier than and later than) and a dynamic A-series (in which events and facts are future, then present, then past). Both series are essential to time, yet the A-series is more fundamental since only it allows for change (McTaggart 1908: 458). This concludes the first part of McTaggart’s reasoning: his argument for the fundamentality of the A-series. Having established this conclusion, McTaggart then claims that the A-series “involves a contradiction” (McTaggart 1908: 466). His argument for the contradiction is seemingly straightforward: past, present and future are “incompatible determinations” yet “every event has them all” (McTaggart 1908: 469). This argument is typically known as McTaggart’s Paradox. McTaggart is aware of a natural rejoinder to his argument. No event, it will be urged, is simultaneously past, present and future, only successively, and from this no contradiction follows. But, claims McTaggart, this rejoinder entails either a vicious circle or a vicious infinite regress, and so the contradiction is not removed.
    [Show full text]
  • Adam Smith on Justice, Rights, and Law David Lieberman
    Adam Smith on Justice, Rights, and Law David Lieberman Jurisprudence and Social Policy Program University of California, Berkeley [forthcoming in Knud Haakonssen (ed.), Cambridge Companion to Adam Smith (Cambridge University Press)] Preliminary Draft - please do not cite or quote December, 1999 Adam Smith on Justice, Rights and Law 1. The Unexecuted Account of Law and Government “I shall in another discourse,” Adam Smith reported in the final paragraph of The Theory of Moral Sentiments, “endeavour to give an account of the general principles of law and government, and of the different revolutions they have undergone in the different ages and periods of society …” (TMS.VII.iv.37). Smith’s announcement of this future volume on the general principles of law and government - originally presented in the 1759 first edition of his moral treatise - was then reissued over the next three decades in all the subsequent editions of The Theory of Moral Sentiments published in Smith’s own lifetime. Even the heavily-revised sixth edition of 1790, published in the year of Smith’s death, retained the passage; though by this time Smith acknowledged that his “very advanced age” left him “very little expectation” of completing “this great work” which some thirty years earlier he “entertained no doubt of being able to execute” in its entirety (TMS, “Advertisement”, p.3) i. As in the case of Smith’s two most famous publications, the projected work on “the general principles of law and government” took shape as part of Smith’s duties as a professor at Glasgow University. He had, in fact, first lectured on law and jurisprudence even before he received election in 1751 to the first of his two Glasgow chairs.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship@Western Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 12-15-2015 12:00 AM Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics Michael H. Walschots The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Corey Dyck The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Walschots, Michael H., "Moral Sense Theory and the Development of Kant's Ethics" (2015). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 3383. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/3383 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MORAL SENSE THEORY AND THE DEVELOPMENT OF KANT’S ETHICS (Thesis format: Monograph) by Michael H. Walschots Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada © Michael H. Walschots 2015 Abstract This dissertation investigates a number of ways in which an eighteenth century British philosophical movement known as “moral sense theory” influenced the development of German philosopher Immanuel Kant’s (1724-1804) moral theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Locke, Kant, and Synthetic a Priori Cognition
    Brian A. Chance Locke, Kant, and Synthetic APriori Cognition Abstract: This paper attempts to shed light on threerelated issues that bear di- rectlyonour understandingofLockeand Kant.The first is whether Kant believes Lockemerelyanticipates his distinction between analytic and synthetic judg- ments or also believes Lockeanticipateshis notion of synthetic apriori cogni- tion. The second is what we as readers of Kant and Lockeshould think about Kant’sview whatever it turnsout to be, and the third is the nature of Kant’sjus- tification for the comparison he drawsbetween his philosophyand Locke’s. I argue(1) that Kant believes Lockeanticipates both the analytic-synthetic distinc- tion and Kant’snotion of synthetic apriori cognition, (2)thatthe best justifica- tion for Kant’sclaim drawsonLocke’sdistinction between trifling and instruc- tive knowledge,(3) that the arguments against this claim developed by Carson, Allison, and Newman fail to undermine it,and (4) that Kant’sown jus- tification for his claim is quite different from what manycommentators have thoughtitwas (or should have been). Introduction Kant’srelationship to his empiricist predecessors is complex, and this complex- ity is perhaps no more evident than in the caseofLocke, whose philosophyin- fluenced not onlythe likes of Berkeley,Hume, and Reid but alsoageneration of Kant’sGermanpredecessors.¹ The “famous Locke” is the first philosopher Kant mentionsinthe Critique of Pure Reason (CPR), but he is also critical of Locke’s “physiology of the human understanding” and contrasts his transcendental de- Citations from the Critique of Pure Reason use the standardA/B formattorefer to the pagesof the first (A) and second (B) editions. Citations from Kant’sother worksuse the volume number and pagination of KantsgesammelteSchriften,edited by the Royal Prussian(laterGerman, then Berlin-Brandenburg) Academy of the Sciences.
    [Show full text]