Georgetown Law Journal

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Georgetown Law Journal THE GEORGETOWN LAW JOURNAL VOLUME 30 APRIL 1942 NUMBER 6 NATURAL LAW AND AMERICAN LEGAL REALISM: THEIR RESPECTIVE CONTRIBUTIONS TO A THEORY OF LAW IN A DEMOCRATIC SOCIETYt Francis E. Lucey, S. J.* PROPER treatment of the subject matter of this article involves many questions worthy of separate and extensive treatment in their own right. What is Democracy? What are the various forms of Real ism? Who are Realists? What is Behaviorism and what are its various shades of meaning? What is Psychoanalysis? What is Positivism, Pragmatism, Instrumentalism, Conceptualism, Nominalism? What is meant by Natural Law? Scholastic Natural Law? Brevity required by the time element, permits but a slight nod of recognition to some of these problems, with the hope that the reader has at least a bowing acquain tance with their relationship to the main problem. The main problem here is Realism versus Scholastic Natural Law, so often confused with that Pseudo-Natural Law of 19th Century American Jurisprudence, that philosophy which decapitated the sound philosophy of the founding fathers. The problems involved in the subject matter of the article would com plicate matters sufficiently for any writer. But to add to one's woes there is another difficulty which stems from a much too common and re grettable characteristic of modern writers among whom my Realist friends may be classed. Ideas are tossed out singly and in blocks. One looks in vain for clean cut propositions with definite subjects and predi cates. But it is difficult to find anything into which to put one's teeth. There is an abundance of leaves, but it is hard to find the fruit therein concealed, except the crab-apples. After reading masses of words and tThis article is a further development of a paper read at the Meeting of the Association of American Law Schools held in Chicago on December 30, 1941, at the Round Table on Jurisprudence. *A.B., M.A., Woodstock College; Ph.D., LL.B., Georgetown University; Member of the Bar of the District of Columbia; Professor of Jurisprudence (1928- ) and Regent, Georgetown University, School of Law (1931- ) ; Professor of Metaphysics and Logic, Loyola College, Maryland (1924-1927) ; Professor of Metaphysics, Ethics, and History of Social Thought, Georgetown University (1929-1931); President, Jesuit Philosophical Asso ciation of the Eastern States (1934-1935) ; Author of Jurisprudence and the Future Social Order (1941) 16 Social Science 211. 493 494 The Georgetown Law Journal [Vol. 30: p. 493 phrases one is left with only what one Realist well called an after-glow, although I, myself, with a less charitable disposition have a tendency to denominate the same an after-haze. In reading modern legal writers, I am usually befuddled and bemuddled. I am more conscious of things implied or suggested than things stated, albeit suggested in grandilo quent manner. Many years of honest endeavor to get something more than a fleeting glimpse through the thick foliage at those pretentious Pride's Crossing Mansions of Wisdom nestling on the shore, that is re stricted to superior intelligence, at one time, almost drove me to despair. It was only when Pound, the anti Realist, found difficulty in under standing Realists' writings, and Carl Llewellyn, the Realist, generously reciprocated, that I recovered my balance and agreed with both.1 The confessions of Llewellyn and Pound proved very valuable to me. I re-examined the materials and discovered a new and fruitful approach. I found that at times I acquired a better insight into the proposed theory by reading between the lines rather than by focusing analysis on the express declarations of the author. At other times, I discovered that what the theorists emphasized and fought about was relatively un important and that what they stated or implied but did not emphasize frequently constituted the real heart of their theory. I am fully conscious that being forced to reconstruct the Realist's theory, to a great extent, from the contents of after-glows, between the line readings and from vitally important unemphasized or de-empha sized statements is beset with the danger of misstating the theory and resulting unfairness. Despite that handicap, I shall try to state the case of Realism as correctly and realistically as possible. However, I can not guarantee complete justice to each Realist, because of the variety of psychologies they profess, and the variable extent to which they apply the same to their theory of Jurisprudence. With the thesaurus of unusual words placed beyond my reach and with as little recourse as possible to impressive excerpts from foreign languages, living, doomed or dead, I shall try to state simply the theories involved and their re spective effects on Democracy. First of all then, what is Realism? The Background of Realism Analytical Jurisprudence Realism can be best appreciated by the historical approach, because Realism is only a further development and refinement of Holmes' Socio logical Jurisprudence, and Holmes' Jurisprudence was, in reality, just in laSo that misinterpretation is undoubtedly present, for we have as much trouble getting the Dean's meaning as he at times has in getting the meaning of Realists." Llewel lyn, Some Realism about Realism (1931) 44 Harv. L. Rev. 1222, 1229 n. 19. 1942] Natural Law and Legal Realism 495 a modification of Analytical Jurisprudence. Pragmatism refined Utili tarianism. Sociological Jurisprudence reformed Analytical Jurispru dence. There are of course traces of other schools in the complicated picture of Realism. Realism seems inexplicable without some sort of volkgeist producing folkways and social institutions or a volkgeist in the form of an unconscious mind urge. Environmental stimulus control has to flow from something. We get a better insight into Realism by considering first of all the relationship between Analytical and Sociological Jurisprudence. What are the vital fundamentals assumed by Analytical Jurisprudence? If one is acquainted with Hobbes and Bentham, he has the answer. In the Hobbesian Philosophy, the State is the result of dominant force or a social compact for fear of the same. In Analytical Jurisprudence the authority of government consists in force exercised by the dominant group upon the dominated by issuing imperatives, which from the sub jective viewpoint of the dominant seem useful for civil society. The dominant group arbitrarily predetermines the useful, because the domi nant are subject to no objective norm. There are no oughts or limita tions over the dominant group, because the dominant are the ultimate force in the Society. The dominant group makes the norms and can make anything a norm which it considers socially useful. The dominated are bound to keep within these norms, not by a moral ought, but by compulsory physical force. Just as might creates the right of authority in the dominating group so the might of the dominant group protecting and insuring the approved and decreed behavior of the dominated, con stitutes the rights of the individual and the correlative duty of others.2 The dominant have a sort of self-imposed duty to make their imperative norms aim at an end. What is that end? Social utility. This social utility must be discovered by reason and logic. The utility is as it were predetermined by logic. The reason and logic of the dominant group evaluates ahead of time, predetermines the useful, and then applies it in the form of norms for behavior. Cases and controversies, as they arise, are then decided in a slot machine manner by their conformity or non conformity with the utility norm. This constitutes the basis of the School. Of course, granted these premises, it follows that law is consciously made by the dominant group, that law is normative and composed of imperatives, arbitrarily made, however, as should be noted; that the dominant group has no interest in the past; that typical law is statutory; that reason and logic are masters over the utility or experience, and 2"That which gives validity to a legal right is, in every case, the force which is lent to it by the state. Anything else may be the occasion, but is not the cause, of its obligatory- character." Holland, Jurisprudence (13th ed. 1924) 83. 496 The Georgetown Law Journal [Vol. 30: p. 493 pass judgment on the same; that all law is absolutely flexible, since utility and arbitrary will are flexible; and that determination of cases is a sort of a slot machine practice. There are still other corollaries of the Analytical School worthy of mention. It makes law stand on its own feet, absolutely divorces law and morals as to the formal element of a moral ought, makes the individual live and behave by privilege not right, deprives man of all innate dignity, and thus reduces him to the status of an animal. If one keeps before his mind the vital roll played by force, reason and utility in the Analytical School he can readily see the modifications in Analytical Jurisprudence brought about by Sociological Jurisprudence. Sociological Jurisprudence: Holmes and Pound What did Sociological Jurisprudence object to and change in Analyti cal Jurisprudence? The answer is really a bifurcated one, because we had a Poundian Sociological Jurisprudence and a Holmesian Sociological Jurisprudence, the latter being the father of Realism. While Pound and Holmes differed as to the degree of departure from Analytical Jurisprudence, they had one thing at least in common, namely the prag matic test of utility. Pragmatism did not deny that utility was the test for truth and goodness. It merely denied that you could know utility before experimenting to see what worked. What worked, not reason and logic determined utility. You couldn't decide cases by a predetermined utility, as the Analytical School had held.
Recommended publications
  • Studies in History and Jurisprudence, Vol. 2 [1901]
    The Online Library of Liberty A Project Of Liberty Fund, Inc. Viscount James Bryce, Studies in History and Jurisprudence, vol. 2 [1901] The Online Library Of Liberty This E-Book (PDF format) is published by Liberty Fund, Inc., a private, non-profit, educational foundation established in 1960 to encourage study of the ideal of a society of free and responsible individuals. 2010 was the 50th anniversary year of the founding of Liberty Fund. It is part of the Online Library of Liberty web site http://oll.libertyfund.org, which was established in 2004 in order to further the educational goals of Liberty Fund, Inc. To find out more about the author or title, to use the site's powerful search engine, to see other titles in other formats (HTML, facsimile PDF), or to make use of the hundreds of essays, educational aids, and study guides, please visit the OLL web site. This title is also part of the Portable Library of Liberty DVD which contains over 1,000 books and quotes about liberty and power, and is available free of charge upon request. The cuneiform inscription that appears in the logo and serves as a design element in all Liberty Fund books and web sites is the earliest-known written appearance of the word “freedom” (amagi), or “liberty.” It is taken from a clay document written about 2300 B.C. in the Sumerian city-state of Lagash, in present day Iraq. To find out more about Liberty Fund, Inc., or the Online Library of Liberty Project, please contact the Director at [email protected].
    [Show full text]
  • Law and Order
    THE HAMLYN LECTURES Thirty-seventh series Law and Order Ralf Dahrendorf K.B.E., F.B.A. STEVENS Law and Order by Ralf Dahrendorf K.B.E., F.B.A. Professor of Social Science in the University of Constance; formerly Director of the London School of Economics In this book, based on his 1985 Hamlyn Lectures, Professor Ralf Dahrendorf considers the fundamental questions posed for the social order of free countries by the decline in respect for the law. Taking as his point of departure the terrors of our streets and the riots in our football grounds, Professor Dahrendorf discusses the implication for social order and liberty of such issues as unemployment, the cracks in the party system and the growing disorientation of the young. There are four major themes in the book— • The Road to Anomia—crime statistics are but the most dramatic symptoms of a loosening of social ties and norms. • Seeking Rousseau, Finding Hobbes—a widespread dream of goodness has resulted in the dismantling of some of the institutions designed to protect us from badness. • The Struggle for the Social Contract—underlying social changes have led from the class struggle to conflicts about the boundaries of society. • Society and Liberty—most reactions to the new condition involve threats to liberty—we need to reassert the links between law, order and liberty. Professor Dahrendorf has had a most distinguished career, both in his native Germany and in the United Kingdom. In Law and Order he offers a lively and stimulating analysis of a topic of vital importance in the life of every citizen.
    [Show full text]
  • Democracy and the Death of Knowledge Suzanna Sherry
    Vanderbilt University Law School Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship 2007 Democracy and the Death of Knowledge Suzanna Sherry Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Suzanna Sherry, Democracy and the Death of Knowledge, 75 University of Cincinnati Law Review. 1053 (2007) Available at: http://scholarship.law.vanderbilt.edu/faculty-publications/307 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Vanderbilt Law School Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Vanderbilt Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DEMOCRACY AND THE DEATH OF KNOWLEDGE Suzanna Sherry* Judges are under unprecedented attack in the United States. As former Justice Sandra Day O'Connor wrote in the Wall Street Journal last month, "while scorn for certain judges is not an altogether new phenomenon, the breadth and intensity of rage currently being leveled at the judiciary may be unmatched in American history."' Popular unhappiness with particular decisions-which began even before the Constitution and has occurred continuously since then-has turned into something deeper: a rejection of judicial review itself and a belief that judges should bow to the wishes of the popular majority. A few years ago, I diagnosed this phenomenon as the result of a misconception that all law is politics. I suggested that it was now conventional wisdom to believe that "constitutional adjudication is simply politics by another name.",2 And because politics is the province of the people and their representatives, judges should stay out of it.
    [Show full text]
  • THE FUTURE of IDEAS This Work Is Licensed Under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial License (US/V3.0)
    less_0375505784_4p_fm_r1.qxd 9/21/01 13:49 Page i THE FUTURE OF IDEAS This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial License (US/v3.0). Noncommercial uses are thus permitted without any further permission from the copyright owner. Permissions beyond the scope of this license are administered by Random House. Information on how to request permission may be found at: http://www.randomhouse.com/about/ permissions.html The book maybe downloaded in electronic form (freely) at: http://the-future-of-ideas.com For more permission about Creative Commons licenses, go to: http://creativecommons.org less_0375505784_4p_fm_r1.qxd 9/21/01 13:49 Page iii the future of ideas THE FATE OF THE COMMONS IN A CONNECTED WORLD /// Lawrence Lessig f RANDOM HOUSE New York less_0375505784_4p_fm_r1.qxd 9/21/01 13:49 Page iv Copyright © 2001 Lawrence Lessig All rights reserved under International and Pan-American Copyright Conventions. Published in the United States by Random House, Inc., New York, and simultaneously in Canada by Random House of Canada Limited, Toronto. Random House and colophon are registered trademarks of Random House, Inc. library of congress cataloging-in-publication data Lessig, Lawrence. The future of ideas : the fate of the commons in a connected world / Lawrence Lessig. p. cm. Includes index. ISBN 0-375-50578-4 1. Intellectual property. 2. Copyright and electronic data processing. 3. Internet—Law and legislation. 4. Information society. I. Title. K1401 .L47 2001 346.04'8'0285—dc21 2001031968 Random House website address: www.atrandom.com Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper 24689753 First Edition Book design by Jo Anne Metsch less_0375505784_4p_fm_r1.qxd 9/21/01 13:49 Page v To Bettina, my teacher of the most important lesson.
    [Show full text]
  • Ross and Olivecrona on Rights
    Scholarship Repository University of Minnesota Law School Articles Faculty Scholarship 2009 Ross and Olivecrona on Rights Brian H. Bix University of Minnesota Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/faculty_articles Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Brian H. Bix, Ross and Olivecrona on Rights, 34 AUSTL. J. LEG. PHIL. 103 (2009), available at https://scholarship.law.umn.edu/faculty_articles/211. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the University of Minnesota Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in the Faculty Scholarship collection by an authorized administrator of the Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Ross and Olivecrona on Rights BRIAN H. BIX1 Introduction The Scandinavian legal realists, critically-inclined theorists from Denmark, Norway, and Sweden, who wrote in the early and middle decades of the 20t century,2 are not as widely read as they once were in Britain, and they seemed never to have received much attention in the United States. This is unfortunate, as the work of those theorists, at their best, is as sharp in its criticisms and as sophisticated philosophically as anything written by the better known (at least better known in Britain and the United States) American legal realists, who were writing at roughly the same time. The focus of the present article, Alf Ross and Karl Olivecrona, were arguably the most accessible of the Scandinavian legal realists, with their clear prose, straight- forward style of argumentation, and the availability of a number of works in English.
    [Show full text]
  • NP 2013.Docx
    LISTE INTERNATIONALE DES NOMS PROTÉGÉS (également disponible sur notre Site Internet : www.IFHAonline.org) INTERNATIONAL LIST OF PROTECTED NAMES (also available on our Web site : www.IFHAonline.org) Fédération Internationale des Autorités Hippiques de Courses au Galop International Federation of Horseracing Authorities 15/04/13 46 place Abel Gance, 92100 Boulogne, France Tel : + 33 1 49 10 20 15 ; Fax : + 33 1 47 61 93 32 E-mail : [email protected] Internet : www.IFHAonline.org La liste des Noms Protégés comprend les noms : The list of Protected Names includes the names of : F Avant 1996, des chevaux qui ont une renommée F Prior 1996, the horses who are internationally internationale, soit comme principaux renowned, either as main stallions and reproducteurs ou comme champions en courses broodmares or as champions in racing (flat or (en plat et en obstacles), jump) F de 1996 à 2004, des gagnants des neuf grandes F from 1996 to 2004, the winners of the nine épreuves internationales suivantes : following international races : Gran Premio Carlos Pellegrini, Grande Premio Brazil (Amérique du Sud/South America) Japan Cup, Melbourne Cup (Asie/Asia) Prix de l’Arc de Triomphe, King George VI and Queen Elizabeth Stakes, Queen Elizabeth II Stakes (Europe/Europa) Breeders’ Cup Classic, Breeders’ Cup Turf (Amérique du Nord/North America) F à partir de 2005, des gagnants des onze grandes F since 2005, the winners of the eleven famous épreuves internationales suivantes : following international races : Gran Premio Carlos Pellegrini, Grande Premio Brazil (Amérique du Sud/South America) Cox Plate (2005), Melbourne Cup (à partir de 2006 / from 2006 onwards), Dubai World Cup, Hong Kong Cup, Japan Cup (Asie/Asia) Prix de l’Arc de Triomphe, King George VI and Queen Elizabeth Stakes, Irish Champion (Europe/Europa) Breeders’ Cup Classic, Breeders’ Cup Turf (Amérique du Nord/North America) F des principaux reproducteurs, inscrits à la F the main stallions and broodmares, registered demande du Comité International des Stud on request of the International Stud Book Books.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Do Nations Obey International Law?
    Review Essay Why Do Nations Obey International Law? The New Sovereignty: Compliance with InternationalRegulatory Agreements. By Abram Chayes" and Antonia Handler Chayes.*" Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1995. Pp. xii, 404. $49.95. Fairness in International Law and Institutions. By Thomas M. Franck.- Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995. Pp. 500. $55.00. Harold Hongju Koh Why do nations obey international law? This remains among the most perplexing questions in international relations. Nearly three decades ago, Louis Henkin asserted that "almost all nations observe almost all principles of international law and almost all of their obligations almost all of the time."' Although empirical work since then seems largely to have confirmed this hedged but optimistic description,2 scholars Felix Frankfurter Professor of Law, Emeritus, Harvard Law School ** President, Consensus Building Institute. Murray and Ida Becker Professor of Law; Director. Center for International Studtcs. New York University School of Law. t Gerard C. and Bernice Latrobe Smith Professor of International Law; Director. Orville H, Schell, Jr., Center for International Human Rights, Yale University. Thts Essay sketches arguments to be fleshed out in a forthcoming book, tentatively entitled WHY NATIONS OBEY: A THEORY OF COMPLIANCE WITH INTERNATIONAL LAW. Parts of this Review Essay derive from the 1997 \Vaynflete Lectures. Magdalen College, Oxford University, and a brief book review of the Chayeses volume in 91 Am. J. INT'L L. (forthcoming 1997). 1 am grateful to Glenn Edwards, Jessica Schafer. and Douglas Wolfe for splendid research assistance, and to Bruce Ackerman, Peter Balsam, Geoffrey Brennan. Paul David, Noah Feldman. Roger Hood, Andrew Hurrell, Mark Janis, Paul Kahn, Benedict Kingsbury, Tony Kronran.
    [Show full text]
  • New Legal Realism at Ten Years and Beyond Bryant Garth
    UC Irvine Law Review Volume 6 Article 3 Issue 2 The New Legal Realism at Ten Years 6-2016 Introduction: New Legal Realism at Ten Years and Beyond Bryant Garth Elizabeth Mertz Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.uci.edu/ucilr Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Bryant Garth & Elizabeth Mertz, Introduction: New Legal Realism at Ten Years and Beyond, 6 U.C. Irvine L. Rev. 121 (2016). Available at: https://scholarship.law.uci.edu/ucilr/vol6/iss2/3 This Foreword is brought to you for free and open access by UCI Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in UC Irvine Law Review by an authorized editor of UCI Law Scholarly Commons. Garth & Mertz UPDATED 4.14.17 (Do Not Delete) 4/19/2017 9:40 AM Introduction: New Legal Realism at Ten Years and Beyond Bryant Garth* and Elizabeth Mertz** I. Celebrating Ten Years of New Legal Realism ........................................................ 121 II. A Developing Tradition ............................................................................................ 124 III. Current Realist Directions: The Symposium Articles ....................................... 131 Conclusion: Moving Forward ....................................................................................... 134 I. CELEBRATING TEN YEARS OF NEW LEGAL REALISM This symposium commemorates the tenth year that a body of research has formally flown under the banner of New Legal Realism (NLR).1 We are very pleased * Chancellor’s Professor of Law, University of California, Irvine School of Law; American Bar Foundation, Director Emeritus. ** Research Faculty, American Bar Foundation; John and Rylla Bosshard Professor, University of Wisconsin Law School. Many thanks are owed to Frances Tung for her help in overseeing part of the original Tenth Anniversary NLR conference, as well as in putting together some aspects of this Symposium.
    [Show full text]
  • American Jurisprudence Between the Wars: Legal Realism and the Crisis of Democratic Theory Edward A
    digitalcommons.nyls.edu Faculty Scholarship Articles & Chapters 1969 American Jurisprudence Between the Wars: Legal Realism and the Crisis of Democratic Theory Edward A. Purcell Jr. New York Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.nyls.edu/fac_articles_chapters Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Law and Psychology Commons Recommended Citation 75 American Historical Review 424 (1969) This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at DigitalCommons@NYLS. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles & Chapters by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@NYLS. American Jurisprudence between the Wars: Legal Realism and the Crisis of Democratic Theory Author(s): Edward A. Purcell, Jr. Source: The American Historical Review, Vol. 75, No. 2 (Dec., 1969), pp. 424-446 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the American Historical Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1849692 Accessed: 13-12-2017 11:33 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Oxford University Press, American Historical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Historical Review This content downloaded from 132.174.250.77 on Wed, 13 Dec 2017 11:33:39 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms American Jurisprudence between the VWars: Legal Realism and the Crisis of Democratic Theory EDWARD A.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Realism Explains Nothing Anthony D'amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected]
    Northwestern University School of Law Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons Faculty Working Papers 2010 Legal Realism Explains Nothing Anthony D'Amato Northwestern University School of Law, [email protected] Repository Citation D'Amato, Anthony, "Legal Realism Explains Nothing" (2010). Faculty Working Papers. Paper 84. http://scholarlycommons.law.northwestern.edu/facultyworkingpapers/84 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Working Papers by an authorized administrator of Northwestern University School of Law Scholarly Commons. Legal Realism Explains Nothing, by Anthony D'Amato* 1 Washington University Jurisprudence Review, 1-20 (2009) Abstract: I argue that American legal realism as derived from Oliver Wendell Holmes's prediction theory of law was misinterpreted, and that a deeper examination of law-as-prediction might help to reduce the pathology of judicial lawmaking that has been the unfortunate consequence of legal realism. Tags: Legal Realism, Prediction Theory of Law, Judicial Decisions, Oliver Wendell Holmes [pg1] I.JUDICIAL FREEDOM VARIES INVERSELY WITH PERSONAL FREEDOM I argue that American legal realism as derived from Oliver Wendell Holmes's prediction theory of law was misinterpreted, and that a deeper examination of law-as-prediction might help to reduce the pathology of judicial lawmaking that has been the unfortunate consequence of legal realism. Legal realism is the theory that judges may decide cases by taking into account factors other than preexisting law.FN1 Judge Richard A. Posner recently extended the theory to its limits by announcing that there is no such thing as preexisting law: [L]aw is the activity of licensed persons, the judges, rather than a body of concepts (rules, principles, whatever)...
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Realism, Lex Fori, and the Choice-Of-Law Revolution
    Legal Realism, Lex Fori, and the Choice-of-Law Revolution Michael S. Green The choice-of-law revolution rejected the previously dominant view that a state has the sole power to determine how events occurring within its territory should be adjudicated by other states. The revolution is widely recognized to have been a product of legal realism. Nevertheless, an adequate understanding of this relationship has been hampered by a common misunderstanding. The prevailing view is that the revolutionaries' legal realism led them to accept a consequentialist' jurisprudence, in particular, a jurisprudence under which advancement of the policies of the forum state guides adjudication. Commentators then cite the revolutionaries' acceptance of this jurisprudence as the reason that the revolutionaries advocated the application of the lex fori or law of the forum (a choice-of-law principle we can call lexforismn2 ) whenever the forum is interested in the application of its law. This account of the relationship between legal realism and the revolutionaries' lexforism is often presented by those, such as Lea Brilmayer and Perry Dane.3 who offer as an alternative certain rights-based or deontologica' theories of adjudication. Such rights-based theories of adjudication, they claim, are incompatible with the revolutionaries' lexforism. Brilmayer's and Dane's account of the revolution is logically and historically in error. It is logically in error because, far from being essentially consequentialist. legal realism is compatible with any normative theory of adjudication, including those in which the policies of the forum are subordinated to the rights of the litigants. Clarifying this logical error helps to explain an important historical error in the account: One of the foremost revolutionaries, Walter Wheeler Cook, did not accept that lexforism follows 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Learned Hand's Trademark Jurisprudence: Legal Positivism and the Myth of the Prophet Kenneth L
    McGeorge Law Review Volume 27 | Issue 2 Article 4 1-1-1996 Learned Hand's Trademark Jurisprudence: Legal Positivism and the Myth of the Prophet Kenneth L. Port Marquette University Law School Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarlycommons.pacific.edu/mlr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Kenneth L. Port, Learned Hand's Trademark Jurisprudence: Legal Positivism and the Myth of the Prophet, 27 Pac. L. J. 221 (1996). Available at: https://scholarlycommons.pacific.edu/mlr/vol27/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals and Law Reviews at Scholarly Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in McGeorge Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarly Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Learned Hand's Trademark Jurisprudence: Legal Positivism and the Myth of the Prophet Kenneth L. Port "I hate justice, which means that I know that if a man begins to talk about that, for one reason or another he is shirking thinking in legal terms."' I. INTRODUCTION Learned Hand is considered by nearly all to be one of the most respected jurists in American legal history. The literature is replete with references to Hand, depicting him in superlative terms as one of the most accomplished and respected judges to sit on any United States court.2 Most recently, two of the people most qualified to make the determination have concluded that Hand was a "great judge." Gerald Gunther in his biography on Hand (and in subsequent spin-off * Copyright 1995 Kenneth L. Port.
    [Show full text]