AN ART of RHETORICAL LISTENING: ARISTOTLE’S TREATMENT of AUDIENCE in the RHETORIC Christopher D

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

AN ART of RHETORICAL LISTENING: ARISTOTLE’S TREATMENT of AUDIENCE in the RHETORIC Christopher D AN ART OF RHETORICAL LISTENING: ARISTOTLE’S TREATMENT OF AUDIENCE IN THE RHETORIC Christopher D. Schmidt, Ph.D. University of Dallas, 2021 Scott F. Crider, Director ABSTRACT For Aristotle, the art of rhetoric—an ability to see what is persuasive in any given case—is a matter both of speaking and of listening, of persuading and of judging persuasive speeches. Rhetorical artists may exercise their theoretical powers for the sake of productive activity, discovering persuasive arguments to deploy in the courtroom and the assembly, or they may use those same powers to judge the validity or political utility of other speakers’ arguments, “seeing” the difference between the persuasive and the “apparently persuasive.” This conception of rhetorical artistry is consistent with Aristotle’s teaching about arts generally. In the Physics and the Metaphysics, Aristotle distinguishes between technē, which is a rational and theoretical capacity, and poiēsis, which is a productive activity. In the Politics, he advises free people to study the arts, not so that they may please audiences or clients with their artifacts (which is a vulgar pursuit), but so that they may become better judges of others’ works (a liberal one). Consistent with this conception of receptive and evaluative artistry, the Rhetoric analyzes topics, proofs, enthymeme, and metaphor from both the speaker and the audience’s perspectives, showing how one may be rhetorically artistic both as a speaker and as a judge. The dialectical arrangement of the Rhetoric trains Aristotle’s students and readers in this art of rhetorical listening, teaching them to see not only the available “means” of persuasion, but also persuasion’s material, formal, and final causes. ii THE BRANIFF GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF DALLAS AN ART OF RHETORICAL LISTENING: ARISTOTLE’S TREATMENT OF AUDIENCE IN THE RHETORIC by CHRISTOPHER D. SCHMIDT B.A., UNIVERSITY OF NORTH TEXAS, 2004 M.A., UNIVERSITY OF DALLAS, 2012 A dissertation submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the University of Dallas in partial fulfillment of requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Literature in the Institute of Philosophic Studies. April 28, 2021 Reading Committee: Scott F. Crider, Chair Gregory Roper Joshua Parens Eugene Garver Christopher D. Schmidt, An Art of Rhetorical Listening: Aristotle’s Treatment of Audience in the Rhetoric, © 2021 iv for Laura, femina bona dicendi perita “Where twain together go”— Iliad 10.224; Nicomachean Ethics 1155a CONTENTS Tables and Figures vi Acknowledgements vii Introduction ix I The Unity of Aristotle’s Rhetoric 1 II Judgment, Dialectic, and the Art of Rhetoric (Rhetoric 1.1) 25 III Art and Judgment in the Physics and Metaphysics 51 IV Judgment and the Ends of Persuasion (Rhetoric 1.2-3) 87 V Material Causes: Special Topics, Character, and Passions (1.4 – 2.17) 129 VI Formal Causes: Logic, Arrangement, and Style (2.20-3.19) 177 Appendix I: Uses of “Rhetōr” 218 Appendix II: Uses of “Technē” 219 Appendix III: Arts, Virtues, and Powers 221 Notes 225 Bibliography 244 vi TABLES AND FIGURES Figure 1. The five-part structure of Rhetoric 1.1 9 Figure 2. Five-step dialectical argument repeated three times in Rhetoric 1.1 11 Figure 3. Detailed chart of the cyclical, dialectical structure of 1.1.3-12 12 Figure 4. Endoxa taught by the sophistic Arts of Speech, with corresponding Socratic replies from the Gorgias and Phaedrus 17 Figure 5. An imperfect syllogistic rendering of Rhetoric 1.1.2 21 Figure 6. Syllogistic rendering of 1.1.11 37 Figure 7. Aristotle’s four causes (Physics 193a-195b) 68 Figure 8. Efficient causes of any thing’s coming to be, not by nature 74 Figure 9. Taxonomy of proofs (pisteis), 1.2.3-4 90 Figure 10. Theoretical, audience-centered taxonomy of rhetoric (1.3.1-4) 102 Figure 11. Chapter outline of Politics book 8 122 Figure 12. Topics of fallacious enthymemes 203 vii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS My mother taught me to read and write; my father, to inquire, deduce, and discuss. Grandma Harthan taught me that kindness and good will are as persuasive as a well-reasoned argument. Grandpa Harthan taught me that clarity, the chief virtue of rhetorical style, comes as much from common sense as from art or training. Grandma Schmidt taught me to study inductively: Observe, outline, obtain! Grandpa Schmidt taught me to parse and exegete. Somewhere there is a picture of him and me sitting at the old Pine Street house with lexicons and commentaries strewn about the dining room table, wondering about Paul’s syntax in the first chapter of Ephesians. Growing up in Gulf Coast Bible Church meant learning to read and listen carefully and to recite one’s lessons with confidence and precision. Grandpa Schmidt’s hour-long sermons, during which I was always expected to take copious notes, inculcated the habits of careful listening that I hope to have discerned in Aristotle; and I can remember a number of times when Grandma, Mom, or Dad would insist that I articulate some fine distinction that Grandpa had drawn, always correcting my wording when I remembered poorly. These technical skills are not the chief end for which my parents, grandparents, and neighbors labored. I often wonder if, despite their efforts, I learned a bit too much dicendi peritus and not nearly enough vir bonus. But this is a matter for prayer, not for academic study. At the University of North Texas, Richard Ruderman, Martin Yaffe, and Joe Barnhart taught me to read political philosophy. Eugene Wright, a professor of Shakespeare, insisted that I study Aristotle’s Ethics, and J. Baird Callicott helped me to situate Aristotle in the history of ethical thought. Professor Bruner in the Communication Studies Department and Ulrike Jaeckel in the English Department brought me to the Rhetoric. By chance or by providence, I happened viii upon Scott Crider’s The Office of Assertion, which brought me to the University of Dallas. There, Scott Crider, John Alvis, Gerard Wegemer, David O. Davies, and the rest of the IPS faculty carefully honed my exegetical skills over five years of first-rate lectures and seminars. Scott’s new book, The Art of Persuasion: Aristotle’s “Rhetoric” for Everyone, should become the standard guide for young rhetors. My wife Laura was the first to suggest that I apply for graduate school. She encouraged and supported my studies, patiently doing more than her share to run our household and to bring up our children “beautifully by means of habits,” while also working as a marketer and copy writer. One neither expects nor merits such kindness, nor does one hope ever to repay it adequately—though God knows I will try. ix INTRODUCTION The species of rhetoric are three in number; for such is the number to which the hearers of speeches belong. A speech consists of three things: a speaker and a subject on which he speaks and someone addressed, and the objective of the speech relates to the last (I mean the hearer). –Rhetoric 1.3.11 To theorize about rhetoric is not only to explain how speakers use the means of persuasion; it is also to wonder about how audiences listen and why they judge as they do. As a power or capacity (dunamis), rhetoric is bi- (and often multi-) directional. To treat it as a unidirectional exertion, in which an active speaker transmits a message to a passive audience, is to ignore or minimize most of the political circumstances, ethical considerations, and psychological conditions that inhere in the reciprocal act of speaking and listening. Such treatments are not only theoretically inaccurate but also practically deficient. As Aristotle observes, persuasion is always directed at someone.2 To practice the craft of speaking rationally and artistically, a speaker must, to whatever degree is possible, know her audience—just as she knows her subject and the canons of rhetoric. But understanding an audience means treating its constituent members as human beings who are by nature rational, ethical, emotive, and political—and who are therefore capable of active participation, not only of passive reception, in persuasive discourse. Ultimately, this realization demands that a study of rhetoric treat the rhetorical exchange not only from the perspective of the speaker or writer, whose persuasive goals the speech must instrumentally achieve, but also from the perspective of the reader or listener, whose purposes in hearing the speech, whether acknowledged or not, are broadly political and ethical. A speaker may want to convict a defendant or to see a motion passed; an audience, composed of citizens who may or may not rise to speak, will render a judgment with broad implications and long-lasting x consequences for the administration of justice or the pursuit of common advantage. As a matter of theory, then, rhetoric must explain not only the workings of the speaker’s language, logic, and vocal performance, but also the workings of reason, emotions, and moral convictions in listeners’ souls—all of which serve political and ethical ends that constitute the public good. While cities come into being for the sake of living, they exist for the sake of living well; and, while the art of rhetoric does not in itself discover or determine what constitutes the just or the good, it nevertheless studies and provides arguments about those ends. According to Aristotle, it is part of the same capacity to see what is persuasive about such matters and what is only apparently so. Insofar as the discipline of rhetoric explains how a speaker can best achieve his or her instrumental goals, it should also explain how audiences can best judge the relationship between those instrumental goals and the ends of politics and human life.
Recommended publications
  • Introduction: Oratory and Law at Athens
    Introduction: Oratory and Law at Athens One of the many intriguing (and unique) aspects of Athenian law is that our information about it comes very largely from speeches composed for delivery in court. These date to the period 420-320,1 and reflect in part the high value the Greeks in all periods placed on effective speaking. Even Achilles, whose fame rested primarily on his martial superiority, was brought up to be “a speaker of words and a doer of deeds” (Iliad 9.443). Great Athenian leaders like Themistocles and Pericles were accomplished public speakers; and epic poetry, tragedy, comedy, and history all made frequent use of set speeches. The formal pleadings of the envoys to Achilles in Iliad Book Nine, the messenger speeches in tragedy reporting events like the battle of Salamis in Aeschylus’ Persians, and Pericles’ funeral oration in Thucydides’ History are but a few indications of the Greeks’ never-ending fascination with the spoken word, and with formal public speaking in particular, which reached its height in the public oratory of the fifth and fourth centuries. I. Oratory2 Originally, oratory was not a specialized subject of study but was learned by practice and example. The formal study of rhetoric as an “art” (technē) began, we are told, in the middle of the fifth century in Sicily with Corax and his pupil Tisias.3 These two are scarcely more than names to us, but another Sicilian, Gorgias of Leontini (c. 490-390), developed a dazzling new style of speech and argument. Gorgias initiated the practice, which continued into the early fourth century, of composing speeches for mythical or imaginary occasions.
    [Show full text]
  • Goneis in Athenian Law (And Perception)
    GONEIS IN ATHENIAN LAW (AND PERCEPTION) David Whitehead Queen’s University Belfast [email protected] Abstract: This paper aims to establish what the laws of classical Athens meant when they used the term goneis. A longstanding and widespread orthodoxy holds that, despite the simple and largely unproblematic “dictionary” definition of the noun goneus/goneis as parent/parents, Athenian law extended it beyond an individual’s father and mother, so as to include – if they were still alive – protection and respect for his or her grandparents, and even great-grandparents. While this is not a notion of self-evident absurdity, I challenge it on two associated counts, one broad and one narrow. On a general, contextual level, genre-by genre survey and analysis of the evidence for what goneus means (and implies) in everyday life and usage shows, in respect of the word itself, an irresistible thrust in favour of the literal ‘parent’ sense. Why then think otherwise? Because of confusion, in modern minds, engendered by Plato and by Isaeus. In Plato’s case, his legislation for Magnesia contemplates (I argue) legal protection for grandparents but does not, by that mere fact, extend the denotation of goneis to them. And crucially for a proper understanding of the law(s) of Athens itself, two much-cited passages in the lawcourt speeches of Isaeus, 1.39 and 8.32, turn out to be the sole foundation for the modern misunderstanding about the legal scope of goneis. They should be recognised for what they are: passages where law is secondary and rhetorical persuasion paramount.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking the Connection of Metaphor and Commonplace
    RETHINKING THE CONNECTION OF METAPHOR AND TOPOS MAREIKE BUSS & JÖRG JOST RWTH AACHEN 1. Introduction Having survived the «death of rhetoric» (R. BARTHES 1985: 115), metaphor has become the centre of intensive research by philosophers of language and linguists in the twentieth cen- tury. Nowadays it is widely accepted that metaphor is not reducible to «a sort of happy extra trick with words» (I. A. RICHARDS [1936] 1964: 90), but is rather said to be a funda- mental principle of linguistic creativity with an invaluable cognitive function and heuristic potential. Topos or rather commonplace has, in contrast, a predominantly negative connota- tion in everyday and scientific language. Topos, which originally designated the place where to find the arguments for a speech, has become the cliché, the worn out phrase, or the stereotype. Nevertheless, there are numerous critical studies focusing on topoi in their heu- ristic and argumentative function. Aristotle’s Art of Rhetoric is one of the first and most important ‘textbooks’ for speech production. Following Aristotle, the purpose of rhetorical speech consists in persuading by argumentation. In this respect he defines rhetoric as «the faculty of discovering the possible means of persuasion in reference to any subject whatever.» (Rhetoric I, 1355b/14,2). Now, persuasion presupposes – as any perlocutionary act – that the utterances have been under- stood by the audience, in short: it presupposes (text) comprehension.1 When analysing the first three phases of rhetoric – heuresis, taxis and lexis – two features in particular stand out on account of the role they play in argumentation: topos and metaphor, which are treated in the heuresis and the lexis.2 Metaphor works in a heuristic and aesthetic manner, while topos operates in a heu- ristic and logical manner.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue and Rights in American Property Law Eric R
    Cornell Law Review Volume 94 Article 14 Issue 4 May 2009 Virtue and Rights in American Property Law Eric R. Claeys Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Eric R. Claeys, Virtue and Rights in American Property Law, 94 Cornell L. Rev. 889 (2009) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol94/iss4/14 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. RESPONSE VIRTUE AND RIGHTS IN AMERICAN PROPERTY LAW Eric R. Claey4 INTRODUCTION: ON VIRTUE AND FRYING PANS In Plato's Republic, Socrates persuades his conversationalists to help him construct a city organized around commerce. Glaucon, who has an idealist streak, dismisses this city as a "city of pigs."1 In re- sponse, Socrates sketches for Glaucon an ideal city ruled by the most virtuous citizens-the philosophers. 2 To make the city as just and har- monious as possible, the philosophers abolish the institution of pri- vate property. They require the auxiliary citizens to use external 3 assets only in cooperation, to contribute to common civic projects. This conversational thread presents a tension that is simply un- solvable in practical politics in any permanent way. Politics focuses to an important extent on low and uncontroversial ends, most of which are associated with comfortable self-preservation.
    [Show full text]
  • Robert Wallace's Publications
    Publications: Books, single author 1. Reconstructing Damon. Music, Wisdom Teaching, and Politics in Perikles’ Athens. forthcoming 2013, Oxford University Press (UK) 2. The Areopagos Council, to 307 B.C., The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore MD, 1989, xvii + 294 pages. Winner of the Gustave O. Arlt Award in the Humanities, awarded by the Council of Graduate Schools, 1988. Reviews : Gnomon 69 (1997) 76-78 W. Schuller; Aevum 66 (1992) 178-180 L. Pignoloni; Rechtshist. Journ. 10 (1991) 8-11 D. Cohen; Amer. Hist. Rev. 96 (1991) 487 R. Garner; Class. World 84 (1991) 416-417 R. Moorton; Journ. Hell. Stud. 110 (1990) 252-253 R. Knox; Class. Rev. 40 (1990) 356-358 D. Lewis; Gr.& R. 37 (1990) 242 P. Rhodes; Amer. Journ. Philol. 111 (1990) 410-414 E. Carawan; New Engl. Class. Newsl. & Journ., May 1990, 35-36 D. Held; History 1989, pp. 129-130 P. Krentz; Choice 26-5503 (June 1989) P. Mitsis. Book, co-authored 3. Origins of Democracy in Ancient Greece, by Kurt A. Raaflaub, Josiah Ober, and Robert W. Wallace, University of California Press, Berkeley and Los Angeles 2007, pp. xi + 242; paperback ed. 2008. Reviews: Bryn Mawr Cl. Rev. (Rhodes), Class. Rev. 58 (2008) 513-14 (Christ), HistLit 5 (2007) 66-68 (Bernett), Sehepunkt 7 (2007) 10 (Welwei), HistLit 5 (2007) 66-68 (Bernett), Gnomon 80 (2008) 704-708 (Walter), HistZeitschr. 285 (2007) 684-686 (Schubert), Eirene 45 (2009) 181-182 (Oliva); Perspectives on Politics 7 (2009) 950-951 (Saxonhouse), Hermathena 186 (2009) 91-95 (Champion) 3a. Le origini della democrazia nell'antica Grecia, Ariele Press, Milan, 2011.
    [Show full text]
  • Rethinking Mimesis
    Rethinking Mimesis Rethinking Mimesis: Concepts and Practices of Literary Representation Edited by Saija Isomaa, Sari Kivistö, Pirjo Lyytikäinen, Sanna Nyqvist, Merja Polvinen and Riikka Rossi Rethinking Mimesis: Concepts and Practices of Literary Representation, Edited by Saija Isomaa, Sari Kivistö, Pirjo Lyytikäinen, Sanna Nyqvist, Merja Polvinen and Riikka Rossi Layout: Jari Käkelä This book first published 2012 Cambridge Scholars Publishing 12 Back Chapman Street, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2XX, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2012 by Saija Isomaa, Sari Kivistö, Pirjo Lyytikäinen, Sanna Nyqvist, Merja Polvinen and Riikka Rossi and contributors All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-4438-3901-9, ISBN (13): 978-1-4438-3901-3 Table of ConTenTs Introduction: Rethinking Mimesis The Editors...........................................................................................vii I Concepts of Mimesis Aristotelian Mimesis between Theory and Practice Stephen Halliwell....................................................................................3 Rethinking Aristotle’s poiêtikê technê Humberto Brito.....................................................................................25 Paul Ricœur and
    [Show full text]
  • Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: the Medium As
    Isocrates & Europe - 1 Isocrates and the Rhetorical Creation of Europe: The Medium as Message I. Introduction: Overview The idea that Isocrates helped create the concept of transnationalism that fostered Europe both as an idea and as an eventual political union is common fare in rhetorical studies. De Romilly (1992) writes that “Isocrates was perhaps the first in antiquity to focus his political theories on the idea of Europe” (p. 2). Isocrates anticipated “the idea of Europe” (Hariman, 2004, p. 231) and used the words Europen and Europes 13 times in his essays. But, to date, critical exploration of Isocrates’ role in developing the idea of Europe has primarily dealt with the content of his works – with his eloquent and relentless focus on panhellenism and the related conflict between Europe and Asia. This paper, however, will focus on medium rather than message. It will focus on Isocrates’ pioneering use of a new medium – written documents/syggrammata – and the role that the new rhetorical medium played in forming Europe. The most famous passage in the Isocratean canon, the so-called Hymn to Logos (Jaeger, 1944/1971), which first appeared in Nicocles (5-9) and was repeated in Antidosis (253-257), holds that speech/logos is a civic and political unifier, by means of which “we have come together and founded cities and made laws and invented arts” (Nicocles 6). Yet before Isocrates, who was “the first individual who could be termed a ‘writer’ in the modern sense of the term” (Lentz, 1989), logos and its community-building powers Isocrates & Europe - 2 traveled primarily orally: Cities, alliances, arts, and laws were built through face-to-face communication.
    [Show full text]
  • "Bringing-Before-The-Eyes": Visuality and Audience in Greek Rhetoric By
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by ASU Digital Repository "Bringing-before-the-eyes": Visuality and Audience in Greek Rhetoric by Brent D. Chappelow A Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy Approved April 2016 by the Graduate Supervisory Committee: Shirley K Rose, Co-Chair Kathleen S. Lamp, Co-Chair Maureen Daly Goggin ARIZONA STATE UNIVERSITY May 2016 ABSTRACT "Bringing-before-the-eyes": Visuality and Audience in Greek Rhetoric examines how Greek rhetorical theories are understood through the lens of visuality and the ways in which orators accounted for audience knowledges and expectations in the creation of rhetorical texts and performances. Through a close reading of Greek rhetorical texts from the classical period, I develop three heuristics for analyzing the ways in which rhetoricians invite and encourage visualized images through rhetorical practice. By exploring (1) language cues that orators use to signal visualization, (2) the ways in which shared cultural memories and ideas allow orators to call upon standardized images, and (3) the influence of stylistic choices and audience emotions related to the vividness of rhetorical images, I argue that it is possible to analyze the ways in which classical Greek orators understood and employed visual elements in their rhetorical performances. I then conduct an analysis of the visual aspects of Demosthenes' On the Embassy using these heuristics to demonstrate the ways in which these three aspects of visuality are intertwined and contribute to a greater understanding of the relationship between the verbal and the visual in rhetorical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das a Dissertation Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirement
    Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison Das A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Washington 2015 Reading Committee: Ruby Blondell, Chair Deborah Kamen Alexander Hollmann Program Authorized to Offer Degree: Classics Department Allison Das ii ©Copyright 2015 Allison E. Das Allison Das iii University of Washington Abstract Medical Language in the Speeches of Demosthenes Allison E. Das Chair of Supervisory Committee Dr. Ruby Blondell Classics Department Introduction This project is intended as an examination of medical language and imagery in the speeches of Demosthenes, with special attention given to his speeches against his political opponent Aeschines, Against the False Embassy (19) and On the Crown (18). In Chapter 1, I contextualize his use of such language and imagery by exploring the influence of Hippocratic medicine on fourth- and fifth-century non-medical literature. I argue that the shared anxieties of medicine and politics, namely that both arts demand quick action and foresight on the part of the good practitioner, and the rich new vocabulary of suffering and disease, made Hippocratic medicine an enticing model for the political writer, that is, the historian, philosopher, and orator. Demosthenes' medical language and imagery should thus be seen as part of a tradition of analogizing the two arts, which began during the circulation of the first Hippocratic treatises and continued well into and past his own day. Allison Das iv In Chapter 2, I look at medical language and imagery in Demosthenes' prosecution of Aeschines for political misconduct during the Second Embassy to Philip II of Macedon, On the False Embassy.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Benefits and Costs of Legal Expertise: Adjudication in Ancient Athens
    On the Benefits and Costs of Legal Expertise: Adjudication in Ancient Athens Robert K. Fleck John E. Walker Department of Economics Clemson University Clemson, SC 29634 e-mail: [email protected] F. Andrew Hanssen John E. Walker Department of Economics Clemson University Clemson, SC 29634 phone: (864) 656-5474 e-mail: [email protected] December 27, 2011 Abstract: Legal expertise permits detailed laws to be written and enforced, but individuals with expertise may employ their special knowledge to skew decisions in privately beneficial directions. We illustrate this tradeoff in a simple model, which we use to guide our analysis of the legal system in ancient Athens. Rather than accepting the costs of expertise in return for the benefits, as do most modern societies, the Athenians designed a legal system that banned professional legal experts. And this was not because Athenian society was simple: The Athenians employed sophisticated contingent contracts and litigated frequently (to the point that the law courts featured prominently in several famous comedies). Furthermore, the Athenians recognized that forgoing expertise was costly, and where the cost was particularly high, designed institutions that made use of expertise already existing in society, employed knowledgeable individuals who were unable to engage in significant rent seeking, or increased the private returns to collecting publicly beneficial information. Although the Athenian legal system differs in many ways from modern legal systems, it nonetheless functioned very effectively. Investigation of the Athenian system serves to illustrate how important it is for institutional designers to consider legal institutions as a bundle, whose pieces must complement one another.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens
    Trinity University Digital Commons @ Trinity Philosophy Faculty Research Philosophy Department 2014 Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens Damian Caluori Trinity University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.trinity.edu/phil_faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Repository Citation Caluori, D. (2014). Rhetoric and Platonism in fifth-century Athens. In R. C. Fowler (Ed.), Plato in the third sophistic (pp. 57-72). De Gruyter. This Contribution to Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Trinity. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Research by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Trinity. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Damian Caluori (Trinity University) Rhetoric and Platonism in Fifth-Century Athens There are reasons to believe that relations between Platonism and rhetoric in Athens during the fifth century CE were rather close.Z Both were major pillars of pagan cul- ture, or paideia, and thus essential elements in the defense of paganism against in- creasingly powerful and repressive Christian opponents. It is easy to imagine that, under these circumstances, paganism was closing ranks and that philosophers and orators united in their efforts to save traditional ways and values. Although there is no doubt some truth to this view, a closer look reveals that the relations be- tween philosophy and rhetoric were rather more complicated. In what follows, I will discuss these relations with a view to the Platonist school of Athens. By “the Platon- ist school of Athens” I mean the Platonist school founded by Plutarch of Athens in the late fourth century CE, and reaching a famous end under the leadership of Dam- ascius in 529.X I will first survey the evidence for the attitudes towards rhetoric pre- vailing amongst the most important Athenian Platonists of the time.
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistic Patterns of Viewpoint Transfer in News Narratives
    Cognitive Linguistics 2019; 30(3): 499–529 Kobie van Krieken* and José Sanders Smoothly moving through Mental Spaces: Linguistic patterns of viewpoint transfer in news narratives https://doi.org/10.1515/cog-2018-0063 Received 1 June 2018; revised 18 December 2018; accepted 20 December 2018 Abstract: This article presents a Mental Space model for analyzing linguistic patterns in news narratives. The model was applied in a corpus study categoriz- ing various linguistic markers of viewpoint transfers between the mental spaces that readers must conceptualize while processing news narratives: a Reality Space representing the journalist and reader’s projected here-and-now view- point; a News Narrative Space representing the newsworthy events from a there-and-then viewpoint; and an Intermediate Space representing the informa- tion of the news actors provided from a temporal viewpoint in-between the newsworthy events and the present. Viewpoint transfers and their markers were examined in a corpus of 100 Dutch crime news narratives published over a period of fifty years. The results reveal clear patterns, which indicate that both linguistic structures and narrative-based as well as genre-based inferences play a role in the processing of news narratives. The results furthermore clarify how these narratives have been gradually crystallizing into a genre over the past decades. These findings elucidate the complex yet fluent process of conceptually moving between mental spaces, thus advancing our understanding of the rela- tion between the linguistic and the cognitive representation of narrative discourse. Keywords: viewpoint, mental spaces, news narrative, tense, temporal adverbs 1 Introduction A considerable proportion of human communication takes place in narrative formats (Bruner 1991).
    [Show full text]