<<

Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a

Jianning Su, Wu Feng, and Richard J. Greechie

Abstract. We introduce “π-versions” of five familiar conditions for distributivity by applying the various conditions to 3-element only. We prove that they are inequivalent concepts, and characterize them via exclusion systems. A lattice L satisfies D0π if a∧(b∨c) 6 (a∧b)∨c for all 3-element antichains {a, b, c}. We consider a congruence ∼ whose blocks are the maximal autonomous chains and define e the order-skeleton of a lattice L to be L := L/∼. We prove that the following are e equivalent for a lattice L: (i) L satisfies D0π , (ii) L satisfies any of the five π-versions e of distributivity, (iii) the order-skeleton L is distributive.

1. Introduction

Distributive lattices are perhaps the most familiar class of lattices. They may be defined via any of the following ternary relations on L: D(a,b,c) means a ∧ (b ∨ c) = (a ∧ b) ∨ (a ∧ c), D∗(a,b,c) means a ∨ (b ∧ c) = (a ∨ b) ∧ (a ∨ c), Dm(a,b,c) means (a ∧ b) ∨ (b ∧ c) ∨ (c ∧ a) = (a ∨ b) ∧ (b ∨ c) ∧ (c ∨ a), and D0(a,b,c) means a ∧ (b ∨ c) 6 (a ∧ b) ∨ c. In fact, a lattice L is distributive in case any one, and hence all, of the follow- ing equivalent conditions hold:

(i) D(a,b,c) for all a,b,c ∈ L, (ii) D∗(a,b,c) for all a,b,c ∈ L, (iii) Dm(a,b,c) for all a,b,c ∈ L, (iv) D0(a,b,c) for all a,b,c ∈ L.

Recall that elements a, b of a lattice L are incomparable, written as a k b, if they are not comparable. An in L is a of L in which any two distinct elements are incomparable. We denote by πL the set of antichains in n L and by πL the set of n-element antichains in L, where n ≥ 1. In [8], one of us found that a π-version of distributivity proved to be of some importance in the study of when certain mappings are residuated. This motivated us to consider the π-version of each of the properties (i)-(iv), by 3 replacing, in each case, “for all a,b,c ∈ L” with “ for all {a,b,c} ∈ πL.”

Presented by . . . Received . . . ; accepted in final form . . . 2010 Subject Classification: Primary: 06D75. Key words and phrases: lattice, , π-distributive lattice, order-skeleton, residuated, exclusion systems. 2 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie univers.

A lattice L is π-meet-distributive (resp. π-join-distributive) if D(a,b,c) ∗ 3 (resp. D (a,b,c)) holds for all {a,b,c} ∈ πL. A lattice L is π-distributive if it is both π-meet-distributive and π-join-distributive. A lattice L satisfies the 3 π-median law if Dm(a,b,c) holds for all {a,b,c} ∈ πL. A lattice L satisfies 3 D0π if D0(a,b,c) holds for all {a,b,c} ∈ πL. We have resisted considering π-semi-distributivity because it is equivalent to semi-distributivity as defined in [4]. We observe that for a , the five π-versions of distributivity are all equivalent to distributivity. But, in general, they are not equivalent to each other as we show in Section 3. Let C1 and C2 be two classes of such that C1 ⊂ C2; an exclusion system for C1 ⊂C2 is a class S⊂C2 −C1 such that, for L ∈C2, L/∈C1 iff there exists S ∈ S isomorphic to a subalgebra of L. We denote by L, D, and M the classes of lattices, distributive lattices, and modular lattices, respectively. Let D0π, Dmπ, D∧π, D∨π, and Dπ be the classes of lattices satisfying D0π, the π-median law, π-meet-distributivity, π-join-distributivity, and π-distributivity, respectively. Recall that N5 is the 5-element non-modular lattice and M3 is the 5-element modular non-distributive lattice. It is well known that {M3,N5} is an exclusion system for D ⊂ L. In Section 3, we characterize the five π-versions 2 of distributivity via exclusion systems; we show that [M3, 3 ), {L15}, {L14}, and {L13} are exclusion systems for D0π ⊂ L, Dmπ ⊂ D0π, D∧π ⊂ Dmπ, and 2 D∨π ⊂ Dmπ, respectively, where [M3, 3 ) is defined in Section 3. We study the notion of the order-skeleton Le of a lattice L, which was first introduced in [8] and discussed in [9]. In Theorem 2.8, we prove that L satisfies D0π iff its order-skeleton Le is distributive. Our main result, Corollary 3.6, is that L satisfies D0π iff Le satisfies any of the five π-versions of distributivity presented. In particular, if a lattice L is isomorphic to its order-skeleton, then all the five π-versions of distributivity are equivalent to distributivity. We conclude the paper by studying several other weakened distributivity conditions, giving the relation between them and our π-versions of distribu- tivity. The authors wish to thank Dr. Jinko Kanno, Dr. Marcel Ern´e, and Dr. Peter Jipsen for comments which improved this paper.

2. Order-skeletons

Let L be a lattice and a,b ∈ L. As usual, we write [a,b] := {x ∈ L | a 6 x 6 b} and [a,b) := {x ∈ L | a 6 x

a ∼ b means a ∦ b and π(a)= π(c) for all c ∈ [a,b] ∪ [b,a]. Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeletonofalattice 3

M3 L1 L2 L13

L3 L4 L5 L14

L Lg6 Lg7 Lg8 15

(a) A 9-element exclusion system for D0π ⊂L (b)

Figure 1. A 12-element exclusion system for Dπ ⊂ L

Following [16], a non-empty subset S of L is called (order-)autonomous in case, for all p∈ / S, (1) if there is an s ∈ S with s 6 p, then x 6 p for all x ∈ S; and (2) if there is an s ∈ S with p 6 s, then p 6 x for all x ∈ S.

Lemma 2.1. Let L be a lattice with a,b ∈ L. The following are equivalent. (i) a ∼ b. (ii)[a,b] or [b,a] is a chain and π(a)= π(b). (iii)[a,b] or [b,a] is an autonomous chain.

Proof. (i) ⇒ (ii) We may assume that a ∼ b and a 6 b. We need only to show that [a,b] is a chain. For any c, d ∈ [a,b], we have π(c)= π(a)= π(d), so that c ∦ d. It follows that [a,b] is a chain. (ii) ⇒ (iii) Since π(a)= π(b), we have a ∦ b. Assume a 6 b, so that [a,b] is a chain. Let c ∈ [a,b] and p∈ / [a,b]. If p 6 c, then p 6 b. Since π(a) = π(b), we have p ∦ a. Since p∈ / [a,b], we have p 6 a. Thus, p 6 x for all x ∈ [a,b]. Dually, if c 6 p, then x 6 p for all x ∈ [a,b]. Therefore, [a,b] is autonomous. (iii) ⇒ (i) We may assume that [a,b] is an autonomous chain. Let c ∈ [a,b] and x∈ / [a,c]. Note that, x 6 a iff x 6 c, and a 6 x iff c 6 x. Thus, x k a iff x k c. It follows that π(a)= π(c), so that a ∼ b. 

Recall that an θ on a lattice L is a iff for any a,b,c ∈ L, aθb implies that (a ∨ c) θ (b ∨ c) and (a ∧ c) θ (b ∧ c) (cf. [5]).

Lemma 2.2. The relation ∼ defined on a lattice L is a congruence relation. 4 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

Proof. First, we claim that ∼ is an equivalence relation. The reflexivity and symmetry follow directly from the definition. The transitivity follows from the fact that the of autonomous chains are autonomous chains and the of two autonomous chains having a non-empty is an autonomous chain. Now, we show that ∼ is a congruence relation. Let a,b,c ∈ L and suppose that a ∼ b. Since a ∦ b, we may assume that a 6 b. We shall argue that a ∨ c ∼ b ∨ c by the following two cases. Case 1. Suppose that a ∦ c. Since π(a) = π(b), we have b ∦ c. Thus, {a,b,c} is a chain. If c 6 a 6 b, then a ∨ c = a ∼ b = b ∨ c. If a 6 c 6 b, then a ∨ c = c ∼ b = b ∨ c. If a 6 b 6 c, then a ∨ c = c ∼ c = b ∨ c. Therefore, in all cases, a ∨ c ∼ b ∨ c. Case 2. Suppose that a k c. Since a 6 b, we have a ∨ c 6 b ∨ c. By Lemma 2.1, [a,b] is an autonomous chain. Since a 6 a ∨ c, we have b 6 a ∨ c, so that b ∨ c 6 a ∨ c. Thus, a ∨ c = b ∨ c, and therefore, a ∨ c ∼ b ∨ c. By a argument, we have a ∧ c ∼ b ∧ c. Therefore, ∼ is a congruence relation. 

Define [a] := {b | a ∼ b } and Le := L/∼ = {[a] | a ∈ L }. We call the quotient lattice hL; ∨e, ∧ei the order-skeleton of L. (The order-skeleton of a e L L poset is introduced in [8].) Lemma 2.3. Let L be a lattice with a,b ∈ L. Then

(i)[a] 6Le [b] iff there exist a1 ∈ [a] and b1 ∈ [b] such that a1 ≤ b1; (ii)[a]

(iii) If a is meet-reducible in L, then W[a] exists and W[a]= a. W W (iv) If x is meet-reducible in Le, then x exists and x ∈ x. Proof. By , we need only prove (i) and (ii). (i) Let a ∈ L be join-reducible. We need only show that a is the lower bound of [a]. There exist b,c ∈ L such that b k c and a = b ∨ c. Since b k c and a ∦ c,

we have [a] 6= [b]. By Lemma 2.3 (i), we have [b] 6Le [a], so that [b]

(ii) L := (L)= {{x} | x ∈ L}, i.e., ∼e is equality on L. e ge e L e ∼ (iii) L = Le iff Le = {{a} | a ∈ L}. Proof. (i) Let x ∈ Le. For any b,c ∈ x, we have b ∼ c, so that b ∦ c; hence x is a chain. Let p∈ / x and b,c ∈ x. If b 6 p, then by Lemma 2.1, we have [b,c] or [c,b] is autonomous, so that c 6 p. Similarly, p 6 b implies p 6 c. Hence, x is autonomous. We now show that x is maximal. Let S ⊆ L be an autonomous chain containing x. For a ∈ x and s ∈ S, we have that [a,s] or [s,a] is autonomous, so that by Lemma 2.1, a ∼ s. Thus, S ⊆ [a]= x, i.e., x is a maximal autonomous chain. (ii) Let x, y ∈ L and x ∼e y. Since x e y, we may assume that x 6e y, e L ∦L L and hence, there exist a ∈ x and b ∈ y such that a 6 b. For any c ∈ L with

a 6 c 6 b, we have x 6Le [c] 6Le y. Thus, πLe(x) = πLe([c]), and hence, by Lemma 2.3 (vi), π(a)= π(c). It follows that a ∼ b, so that x = y. Therefore, x = {x}. e (iii) If Le = {{a} | a ∈ L}, then the a 7→ [a] is easily seen to be ∼ an . For the converse, assume that L = Le via the isomorphism 6 f : L → Le. Let a,b ∈ L with a ∼ b. We may assume that a b. Since f is an isomorphism, we have f(a) 6Le f(b). Let x be an arbitrary element in [f(a),f(b)] and let c := f −1(x). We have c ∈ [a,b], and thus, π(c) = π(a)

since a ∼ b. Since f is an isomorphism, we have πLe(x)= πLe(f(a)). Therefore, by definition, f(a) ∼Le f(b). By (ii), we have f(a) = f(b), so that a = b.  Therefore, ∼ is equality on L, and Le = {{a} | a ∈ L}. Let L and K be two lattices. Recall that a (lattice-)embedding f : L ֒→ K is a one-to-one from L to K. L is (lattice-)embeddable in K if there exists an embedding from L into K. The following lemma utilizes the of Choice. Lemma 2.6. Let L be a lattice. Consider the following conditions.

(i) Every doubly-reducible element in Le is a singleton subset of L. 6 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

.ii) There exists an embedding β : Le ֒→ L such that β(x) ∈ x for every x ∈ Le) (iii) Le is embeddable in L. (iv) The cardinality of the set of doubly-reducible elements in L equals the cardinality of the set of doubly-reducible elements in Le. Then (i) ⇔ (ii) ⇒ (iii) ⇒ (iv). In particular, if L contains finitely many doubly-reducible elements, then the four conditions are equivalent to each other.

Proof. (i) ⇒ (ii) Assume that every doubly-reducible element in Le is a sin- gleton subset of L. Note that, by Lemma 2.4, if x is join-reducible (resp. V W V W meet-reducible) in Le, then x (resp. x) exists and x ∈ x (resp. x ∈ x). V W By assumption, if x is doubly-reducible in Le, then x = x. Thus, there exists a selection function β : Le → L such that (1) β(x) ∈ x, (2) if x is join-reducible, then β(x)= V x, and (3) if x is meet-reducible, then β(x)= W x.

It is easy to see that β : Le → L is one-to-one. We now show that β is a homomorphism. Let [a], [b] ∈ L. If [a] e [b], then β([a]∨e [b]) = β([a])∨β([b]). e ∦L L If [a] kLe [b], then both [a] ∨Le [b] and a ∨ b are join-reducible, so that by Lemma 2.3 (iii) and Lemma 2.4, β([a] ∨Le [b]) = β([a ∨ b]) = V[a ∨ b]= β([a]) ∨ β([b]). Dually, we have β([a] ∧Le [b]) = β([a]) ∧ β([b]). Therefore, β is an embedding. .ii) ⇒ (i) Let β : Le ֒→ L be an embedding such that β(x) ∈ x for every x ∈ Le) Let x ∈ Le be a doubly-reducible element. Since x is join-reducible in Le, there exist y,z ∈ L such that y ke z and x = y ∨e z. By Lemma 2.3 (v), β(y) k β(z), e L L so that β(x)= β(y) ∨ β(z) is join-reducible in L. By Lemma 2.4, β(x)= V x. Dually, β(x)= W x, so that V x = W x, i.e., x is a singleton subset of L. (ii) ⇒ (iii) This is trivial. iii) ⇒ (iv) Let f : L ֒→ L be an embedding. Let c and ce be the cardinality) e L L of the doubly-reducible elements in L and Le respectively. Note that f maps the doubly-reducible elements in Le to the doubly-reducible elements in L, so that cLe 6 cL. Also note that every doubly-reducible element a ∈ L corresponds to a doubly-reducible element [a] ∈ L, so that c 6 ce. Therefore, c = ce. e L L L L Now assume that L contains finitely many doubly-reducible elements. (iv) ⇒ (i) Suppose that x is doubly-reducible in Le but not a singleton subset of L. Since every doubly-reducible element a ∈ L corresponds to a doubly- reducible element [a] ∈ L, we have c 6 ce. Also note that there is no e L L doubly-reducible element in L that corresponds to x. It follows that cL < cLe which contradicts (iv).  Note that (i), (iii), and (iv) are not in general equivalent to each other. For example, let L be the horizontal sum of L15 with countably many copies 32 of the . Then Le is the horizontal sum of countably many copies of the 32 . Therefore Le is embeddable in L, but L contains a horizontal summand isomorphic to L15 so that Le contains a doubly-reducible element which is not a singleton subset of L, i.e., (iii) ; (i). Now let M be the vertical sum of Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeletonofalattice 7

two 22 so that there is a bi-reducible element in M. Let Q be the horizontal sum of L15 with countably many copies of M. In this example, both Q and Qe have countably many bi-reducible elements, but Qe is not embeddable in Q, i.e., (iv) ; (iii). Define a pentagon in a lattice L to be a quintuple ha,b,c,u,vi such that a,b,c,u,v ∈ L and v

(i) L satisfies D0π. (ii) Le satisfies D0π. (iii) Le is distributive. Proof. First, we prove that (i) and (ii) are equivalent. (i) ⇔ (ii) If L satisfies D , then {[a], [b], [c]} ∈ π3 implies {a,b,c} ∈ π3 and 0π Le L

[a]∧Le ([b]∨Le [c]) = [a∧(b∨c)] 6Le [(a∧b)∨c] = ([a]∧Le [b])∨Le [c], so that L satisfies e 3 D0π. Now we assume that L does not satisfy D0π. Then ∃{a,b,c} ∈ πL such that a ∧ (b ∨ c)  (a ∧ b) ∨ c. Let d = a ∧ (b ∨ c) and e = (a ∧ b) ∨ c, so that d e. Since {a,b,c} ∈ π3 , we have {[a], [b], [c]} ∈ π3 . Since d 6 a,  L Le c 6 e, and c  a, we have e  d. Thus, d k e. It follows, [d] kLe [e]. Since [a] ∧Le ([b] ∨Le [c]) = [d] Le [e] = ([a] ∧Le [b]) ∨Le [c], we have D0([a], [b], [c]) does not hold. Thus, Le does not satisfy D0π. Now we prove that (ii) and (iii) are equivalent. 3 (ii) ⇔ (iii) Assume that L is distributive. For any {x,y,z} ∈ π , x∧e(y∨ez)= e Le L L (x∧e y)∨e (x∧e z) 6e (x∧e y)∨e z. Thus, L satisfies D . Now we may assume L L L L L L e 0π that Le is not distributive. Then Le contains a sublattice isomorphic to M3 or N5. It is easy to verify that M3 does not satisfy D0π. We may assume that Le contains a pentagon hx,y,z,u,vi. By Lemma 2.7, we may assume that ∃ w ∈ L 3 e such that x = y ∨e w and {w,y,z} ∈ π . Since w ∧e z 6e x ∧e z = v 6e y, we L Le L L L L have w ∧e (z ∨e y)= w e y = (w ∧e z) ∨e y, i.e., L does not satisfy D .  L L L L L e 0π 8 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

We conclude this section by observing that a simple induction proves that a lattice L is π-meet-distributive iff x ∧ (W(A −{x})) = W (x ∧ a) for a∈A−{x} every finite π-set A ⊆ L and x ∈ A. And the dual statement holds for π-join- distributivity. Note that this is not true when A is not finite. For example, let N0 := N ∪{0} and consider the lattice hN0; lcm, gcdi. Note that 0 is the top element and 1 is the bottom element. This is a distributive lattice, and thus, a π-meet-distributive lattice. Let O be the set of all odd integers, A = O ∪{2}, and x = 2. We have 2 ∧ (W O)=2 ∧ 0 = 2 but W (2 ∧ a)= W 1 = 1. a∈O a∈O

3. Exclusion systems

In this section, we characterize the five π-versions of distributivity intro- duced in Section 1 by the exclusion systems. We observe that they are not equivalent to each other. Note that in Figure 1, L13 is π-meet-distributive but not π-join-distributive, while L14 is π-join-distributive but not π-meet- distributive. L15 satisfies D0π but does not satisfy the π-median law. Also, both L13 and L14 satisfy D0π and the π-median law, but do not satisfy π- distributivity. For a lattice L with a,b,c ∈ L, we use Γ{a,b,c} to denote the sublattice of L generated by a,b,c. We write 1K (resp. 0K ) for the top (resp. bottom) element of a sublattice K of L.

3 Lemma 3.1. Let L be a lattice with {a,b,c} ∈ πL. The following statements hold. 3 (i) If a ∧ (b ∨ c) ∈{/ a ∧ b,a ∧ c}, then {a ∧ (b ∨ c),b,c} ∈ πL. 3 (ii) If a ∨ (b ∧ c) ∈{/ a ∨ b,a ∨ c}, then {a ∨ (b ∧ c),b,c} ∈ πL. 3 (iii) If a ∨ b< 1Γ{a,b,c} and a ∨ c< 1Γ{a,b,c}, then {(a ∨ b) ∧ (a ∨ c),b,c} ∈ πL. 3 (iv) If 0Γ{a,b,c}

Recall that D0(a,b,c) means a ∧ (b ∨ c) 6 (a ∧ b) ∨ c. Dually, we can define ∗ ∗ D0(a,b,c) to mean (a ∨ b) ∧ c 6 a ∨ (b ∧ c). Note that D0(a,b,c)= D0(c,b,a).

3 Lemma 3.2. Let L be a lattice with {a,b,c} ∈ πL. The following statements are equivalent. Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeletonofalattice 9

(i) D0(a,b,c) holds. (ii) c ∨ (a ∧ (b ∨ c)) = (a ∧ b) ∨ c. (iii) a ∧ (b ∨ c)= a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b)). 3 (iv) {a ∧ (b ∨ c), b, (a ∧ b) ∨ c} ∈/ πL. Proof. It is easy to see that (i), (ii), and (iii) are equivalent. It is trivial that (i) implies (iv). We need only to show that (iv) implies (i). Let a1 := a ∧ (b ∨ c) and c1 := (a ∧ b) ∨ c. Note that a1 6 a and c 6 c1. 3 Suppose that {a1,b,c1} ∈/ πL. We have a1 ∦ b, b ∦ c1, or a1 ∦ c1. Note that, since b  a and a1 6 a, we have b  a1. Therefore, if a1 ∦ b, then since b  a1, we have a1

(i) L does not satisfy D0π. 3 (ii) ∃{a,b,c} ∈ πL such that a 6 b ∨ c and a ∧ b 6 c. 3 (iii) ∃{a,b,c} ∈ πL such that a ∧ b =0Γ{a,b,c} and b ∨ c =1Γ{a,b,c}.

Proof. Let a1 := a ∧ (b ∨ c) and c1 := (a ∧ b) ∨ c. Note that a1 6 a and c 6 c1. 3 (i) ⇒ (ii) Since L does not satisfy D0π, ∃{a,b,c} ∈ πL such that a1  c1. By 3 Lemma 3.2 (iv), {a1,b,c1} ∈ πL. Thus, a1 ∧ b = a ∧ b 6 (a ∧ b) ∨ c = c1. Similarly, a1 6 b ∨ c1. (ii) ⇒ (iii) It is trivial. (iii) ⇒ (i) a ∧ (b ∨ c)= a  c = (a ∧ b) ∨ c, i.e., D0(a,b,c) does not hold. 

As mentioned in the introduction, distributivity implies D0π, but D0π does 3 not imply distributivity. Moreover, for {a,b,c} ∈ πL, if either D(a,b,c) or ∗ D (c,b,a) holds, then D0(a,b,c) holds. But the converse is not true. Figure 2 ∗ is an example of a lattice satisfying D0π, but not D(a,b,c) or D (c,b,a) (this can be verified by applying the above lemma). The following lemma is well known.

Lemma 3.4. {M3} is an exclusion system for D⊂M. In [6], the following lemma is proved. Lemma 3.5. Let L be a lattice containing a pentagon ha,b,c,u,vi and an 3 element d such that a = b ∨ d and {b,c,d} ∈ πL. Then L contains a sublattice isomorphic to L1, L3, L4, Lf6, Lf7, or Lf8. We follow the notation from [14, 11, 12]. Note that M3, L1, L2, L3, L4, L5, L13, L14 and L15 are subdirectly irreducible lattices and each fLi is the order-skeleton of the corresponding lattice Li for i = 6, 7, 8 as found in these references. Note that L1 and L2 are dual; L4 and L5 are dual. By Lemma 2.7, Lemma 3.5 and its dual, and the fact that the eight lattices L1,L2,L3,L4,L5, Lf6, Lf7, and Lf8 are not modular, we have the following corollary. 10 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

a b c

Figure 2. A lattice L satisfying D0π but satisfying neither D(a,b,c) nor D∗(c,b,a).

Corollary 3.6. Let L be a lattice. The order-skeleton Le is modular iff Le contains no sublattice isomorphic to L ,L ,L ,L ,L , L , L , or L . 1 2 3 4 5 f6 f7 f8 Note that the lattices M3,L1,L2,L3,L4,L5, Lf6, Lf7, and Lf8 satisfy the con- dition (i) in Lemma 2.6. Therefore, we have the following corollary. Corollary 3.7. For F ∈ {M3,L1,L2,L3,L4,L5, Lf6, Lf7, Lf8}, if Le contains a sublattice isomorphic to F , then L contains a sublattice isomorphic to F .

Let hLF ; 6i be the poset of all finite lattices with the ordering defined by →֒ order-embedding, i.e., L1 6 L2 iff there exists a one-to-one mapping f : L1 L2 such that x 6 y iff f(x) 6 f(y) for all x, y ∈ L1. We define the half open in LF by [L1,L2) := {L ∈ LF : L1 6 L

Recall that a lattice L satisfies the π-median law iff Dm(a,b,c) holds for 3 all {a,b,c} ∈ πL. For convenience of notation, for a,b,c ∈ L, define au := (a ∨ b) ∧ (a ∨ c), bu := (a ∨ b) ∧ (b ∨ c), and cu := (a ∨ c) ∧ (b ∨ c). Dually, define Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 11 al := (a ∧ b) ∨ (a ∧ c), bl := (a ∧ b) ∨ (b ∧ c), and cl := (a ∧ c) ∨ (b ∧ c). Also, define mu := (a ∨ b) ∧ (b ∨ c) ∧ (c ∨ a) and ml := (a ∧ b) ∨ (b ∧ c) ∨ (c ∧ a). 2 It is easy to verify that the nine lattices in [M3, 3 ) do not satisfy the π-median law, so that Dmπ ⊂ D0π. Lemma 3.9. ∼ 32 Let L be a lattice and Le = . If L does not satisfy the π-median law, then L15 is embeddable in L. Proof. Note that L =∼ 32 is generated by its 3-element antichain. Since L does e 3 not satisfy the π-median law, there exists {a,b,c} ∈ πL such that Dm(a,b,c) 3 does not hold. Since {[a], [b], [c]} ∈ π , we have L =Γe{[a], [b], [c]}. Without Le e L loss of generality, we may assume that [a] and [c] are complements in Le. Since Dm(a,b,c) does not hold, we have ml = (a ∧ b) ∨ (b ∧ c) ∨ (c ∧ a) < (a ∨ b) ∧ (b ∨ c) ∧ (c ∨ a) = mu. Since ml = bl 6 b 6 bu = mu and ml ∼ mu, we have [ml] = [b] = [mu]. Consider the inverse of ∼: L → Le in L, one can verify that {0, 1,a,bu,bl,c,a ∧ b,b ∧ c,a ∨ b,b ∨ c} =∼ L15. 

Lemma 3.10. {L15} is an exclusion system for Dmπ ⊂ D0π.

Proof. It is easy to verify that L15 does not satisfy the π-median law. Now assume that L satisfies D0π, but does not satisfy the π-median law. There 3 exists {a,b,c} ∈ πL such that Dm(a,b,c) does not hold, so that ml

Lemma 3.12. {L14} is an exclusion system for D∧π ⊂ Dmπ.

Proof. It is easy to verify that L14 is not π-meet-distributive. Now assume that L satisfies the π-median law, but does not satisfy the π-meet-distributivity. 3 There exists {a1,b,c} ∈ πL such that D(a1,b,c) does not hold. Let a := a1 ∧ (b ∨ c). Since a1 ∧ b 6 (a1 ∧ b) ∨ (a1 ∧ c) < a1 ∧ (b ∨ c) = a, we have 3 a 6= a1 ∧ b. By symmetry, a 6= a1 ∧ c. By Lemma 3.1 (i), {a,b,c} ∈ πL. We have (a ∧ b) ∨ (a ∧ c) = (a1 ∧ b) ∨ (a1 ∧ c) < a1 ∧ (b ∨ c) = a ∧ (b ∨ c), i.e., D(a,b,c) does not hold. Let F =Γ{a,b,c}. We have b ∨ c = a ∨ b ∨ c =1F . 12 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

Since L satisfies the π-median law, we have ml = mu. Since b ∨ c = 1F , mu = (a∨b)∧(b∨c)∧(c∨a) = (a∨b)∧(a∨c)= au. Since al = (a∧b)∨(a∧c) < a ∧ (b ∨ c) = a ∧ 1F = a 6 au and al ∨ (b ∧ c) = (a ∧ b) ∨ (b ∧ c) ∨ (c ∧ a) = ml = mu = au, we have 0F < b ∧ c. Since a 6 au and a  b, we have au  b. Since au  b and bl 6 b, we have au 6= bl. Since au 6= bl and bl ∨ (a ∧ c) = (a ∧ b) ∨ (b ∧ c) ∨ (c ∧ a)= ml = mu = au, we have 0F

By Theorem 3.11, Lemma 3.12, and their dual statements, we have the following theorem.

2 Theorem 3.13. (i)[M3, 3 )∪{L14,L15} is an exclusion system for D∧π ⊂ L. 2 (ii)[M3, 3 ) ∪{L13,L15} is an exclusion system for D∨π ⊂ L. 2 (iii)[M3, 3 ) ∪{L13,L14,L15} is an exclusion system for Dπ ⊂ L.

Remark 3.14. By definition, π-distributivity implies both π-meet- and π- join-distributivity. By comparing the exclusion systems of the π-versions of distributivity, one can also see that either one of π-meet-distributivity and π-join-distributivity implies the π-median law, and the π-median law implies D0π. In particular, π-distributivity implies D0π.

By using the exclusion systems with Theorem 2.8, we have the following corollary.

Corollary 3.15. Let L be a lattice. The following statements are equivalent.

(i) L satisfies D0π. 2 (ii) L contains no sublattice isomorphic to a lattice in [M3, 3 ).

(iii) Le is distributive. (iv) Le is π-distributive. (v) Le is π-meet-distributive. (vi) Le is π-join-distributive. (vii) Le satisfies the π-median law. (viii) Le satisfies D0π. This corollary tells us that, if a lattice L is isomorphic to its own order- skeleton, then all these π-properties are equivalent to distributivity. We con- clude this section by observing that no two of the properties (iii) - (viii) are equivalent for general lattices. Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 13

4. Motivation and related results

In another paper ([9]), we study the residuated approximation to order- preserving maps on complete lattices. A mapping between two posets is resid- uated if the inverse image of every principle in Q is a principle ideal in L (see [2]). If the posets are complete lattices, then the mapping is residuated iff it preserves all joins. Any function f : L → Q between two complete lattices dominates a largest residuated mapping, called ρf , the residuated approxima- tion of f. In [1], Andr´eka, Greechie, and Strecker introduced the shadow σf of f in order to efficiently approximate ρf by iterating σf where σf is defined −1 by σf (x) := V{q ∈ Q | x 6 W f (↓ q)}. They proved the following theorem. Theorem 4.1. For a Q, Q is completely distributive iff for every complete lattice L and every order-preserving mapping f : L → Q, the shadow σf is residuated. Also, Greechie and Janowitz [10, 9, 8] proved a result implying the following corollary. Corollary 4.2. Let L and Q be two complete lattices and f : L → Q be an order-preserving mapping. If L is completely distributive, then σf is residuated. Notice that both the theorem and the corollary are concerned with dis- tributivity conditions. But even if both L and Q are non-distributive, it is still possible that the shadow is residuated. In [9], we study the structure of L in order to make the shadow σf residuated and found the following theorem. Theorem 4.3. Let L be a lattice with no infinite chains. The following state- ments are equivalent.

(i) σf is residuated whenever Q is a complete lattice and f : L → Q is an order-preserving mapping. (ii) L satisfies D0π. (iii) Le is distributive. This theorem motivated us to study the π-versions of distributivity and the order-skeleton of a lattice. Now we discuss the relation between the π-versions of distributivity in this paper to some weakened conditions found elsewhere [7, 13]. Note that both 2 and N5 are π-distributive lattices, but 2 × N5 does not satisfy D0π. Thus, by Comment 3.14, both 2 and N5 satisfy the five π-versions of distributive conditions, but 2 × N5 does not satisfy any of these five con- ditions. Therefore, the five classes of lattices satisfying the various π-versions of distributivity described in this paper are not lattice varieties since they are not closed under products. A lattice L is semi-distributive whenever, for every a,b,c ∈ L, (SD1) a ∧ b = a ∧ c implies a ∧ b = a ∧ (b ∨ c); and (SD2) a ∨ b = a ∨ c implies a ∨ b = a ∨ (b ∧ c). 14 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

It is easy to show that the π-version of semi-distributivity (again by apply- 3 ing the conditions only to {a,b,c} ∈ πL) is equivalent to semi-distributivity. Davey, Poguntke, and Rival proved that {M3,L1,L2,L3,L4,L5} is an exclu- sion system for SD ⊂L where SD is the class of all semi-distributive lattice [4]. A lattice L is near-distributive whenever, for every a,b,c ∈ L, (ND1) a ∧ (b ∨ c)= a ∧ (b ∨ (a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b)))) and (ND2) a ∨ (b ∧ c)= a ∨ (b ∧ (a ∨ (c ∧ (a ∨ b)))). As with semi-distributivity, it is not difficult to show that the π-version of near-distributivity is equivalent to near-distributivity. It is also easy to show that near-distributivity implies semi-distributivity. We now show that D0π implies near-distributivity.

Lemma 4.4. Let L be a lattice. If L satisfies D0π, then L is near-distributive.

Proof. Since near-distributivity and its π-version are equivalent, we need only 3 to show that the π-version holds. Let {a,b,c} ∈ πL. By Lemma 3.2 (iii), we know that a ∧ (b ∨ c) = a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b)). Let r := a ∧ (b ∨ (a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b)))) be the right hand side of (ND1). Since a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b)) 6 a and a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b)) 6 b ∨ (a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b))), we have a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b) 6 r. Also, we have r 6 a ∧ (b ∨ (a ∧ (c ∨ b))) 6 a ∧ (b ∨ (c ∨ b)) = a ∧ (b ∨ c). Therefore, a ∧ (b ∨ c) = r = a ∧ (b ∨ (a ∧ (c ∨ (a ∧ b)))), i.e., (ND1) holds. By duality, (ND2) holds. Therefore, L is near-distributive. 

A lattice L is almost-distributive if it is near-distributive and for every x,y,z,u,v ∈ L, (AD1) v ∧ (u ∨ c) 6 u ∨ (c ∧ (v ∨ a)); and (AD2) v ∨ (u ∧ c′) ≥ u ∧ (c′ ∨ (v ∧ a′)), where a = (x ∧ y) ∨ (x ∧ z), c = x ∧ (y ∨ (x ∧ z)), a′ = (x ∨ y) ∧ (x ∨ z), and c′ = x ∨ (y ∧ (x ∨ z)). Note that a′ is the dual of a, c′ is the dual of c, and (AD2) is the dual of (AD1).

Lemma 4.5. Let L be a lattice. If L satisfies D0π, then L is almost distribu- tive.

Proof. Let L be a lattice satisfying D0π. By Lemma 4.4, L is near-distributive. Thus, by duality, we need only to show that (AD1) holds. Since L satisfies D0π, by Theorem 2.8, Le is distributive. Recall that ∼ is a congruence relation on L. In L,[a] = [(x ∧ y) ∨ (x ∧ z)] = ([x] ∧e [y]) ∨e ([x] ∧e e L L L [z]) = [x] ∧Le ([y] ∨Le [z]) = [x ∧ (y ∨ z)] = [c]. Thus, a ∼ c and clearly, a 6 c. If a k v, then c k v and by Lemma 2.4, v ∨ a = V[v ∨ a]= V[v ∨ c]= v ∨ c, so that v ∧ (u ∨ c) 6 u ∨ c = u ∨ (c ∧ (v ∨ c)) = u ∨ (c ∧ (v ∨ a)). If v 6 a, then v ∧(u∨c) 6 v 6 a 6 u∨a = u∨(c∧(v ∨a)). If c 6 v, then v ∧(u∨c) 6 u∨c = u ∨ (c ∧ (v ∨ a)). If a 6 v 6 c, then v ∧ (u ∨ c)= v 6 u ∨ v = u ∨ (c ∧ (v ∨ a)). Thus, (AD1) holds.  Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 15

Note that the converse of this lemma is not true. For example, Lf6 is almost distributive but does not satisfy D0π. In [15], Rose proved that for any subdirectly irreducible lattice L, L is almost distributive iff L =∼ D[d] for some distributive lattice D and d ∈ D (see also [11, 13]). Here D[d] is the “doubling” construction introduced by Day [3]. ∼ ∼ Note that Dg[d] = De. If De = D, then the order-skeleton Dg[d] is isomorphic to D, and every block of the order-skeleton is a singleton subset except one block which is a doubleton subset. Recall the definition of a pentagon ha,b,c,u,vi preceding Lemma 2.7. The following lemma follows from the definition of the “doubling” construction.

Lemma 4.6. Let L =∼ D[d] for some distributive lattice D with d ∈ D. If L contains a pentagon ha,b,c,u,vi and θ is the smallest congruence relation that identifies a and b, then L/θ =∼ D and θ is the congruence relation that identifies only a and b.

Lemma 4.7. Let L be a π-distributive lattice with x,y,z ∈ L and L =∼ D[d] for some distributive lattice D with d ∈ D. If L contains a pentagon ha,b,c,u,vi and x ∨ v = y ∨ v, then (x ∧ z) ∨ v = (y ∧ z) ∨ v.

Proof. Assume that (x ∧ z) ∨ v 6= (y ∧ z) ∨ v. Let θ be the smallest congruence relation that identifies a and b. By Lemma 4.6, L/θ is distributive, so that [(x∧z)∨v]θ = ([x]θ ∧θ [z]θ)∨θ [v]θ = ([x]θ ∨θ [v]θ)∧θ ([z]θ ∨θ [v]θ) = [(x∨v)∧(z∨ v)]θ = [(y ∨ v) ∧ (z ∨ v)]θ = [(y ∧ z) ∨ v]θ. Since (x ∧ z) ∨ v θ (y ∧ z) ∨ v, we have {(x ∧ z) ∨ v, (y ∧ z) ∨ v} = {a,b} and we may assume that (x ∧ z) ∨ v = a and (y∧z)∨v = b. Since a  b, we have x  y. Note that x∨a = x∨v = y∨v = y∨b. Since a 6 x ∨ a = y ∨ b and a  b, we have y  b. Since x 6 x ∨ a = y ∨ v and x  y, we have b  y. Thus, y k b. Since b 6 y ∨ b = y ∨ v 6 y ∨ c and b  c, we have y  c. Since y

Lemma 4.8. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible π-distributive lattice. If L contains a pentagon ha,b,c,u,vi, then u =1 and v =0.

Proof. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible π-distributive lattice with a pentagon ha,b,c,u,vi. Assume that u 6=1 or v 6= 0. By duality, we may assume v 6= 0. Define a relation α on L by xαy iff x ∨ v = y ∨ v. It is easy to see that α is an equivalent relation such that for any x,y,z ∈ L with xαy, we have x ∨ zαy ∨ z and, by Lemma 4.7, x ∧ zαy ∧ z, so that α is a congruence relation. Let θ be the smallest congruence relation that identifies a and b. By Lemma 4.6, θ identifies only a and b. Note that, since a ∨ v = a 6= b = b ∨ v, we have a 6αb, so that θ 6= α. Let β be a congruence relation with β ⊆ α and β ⊆ θ, and suppose that c, d ∈ L with c β d. Since c θ d, we have c = d or 16 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

{c, d} = {a,b}. Since c α d, we have c = d. Therefore, β is equality, which implies that L is not subdirectly irreducible, contradicting the assumption. 

Theorem 4.9. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible lattice with L 6= N5. Then L is distributive iff L is π-distributive.

Proof. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible π-distributive lattice with L 6= N5. By Comment 3.14, L satisfies D0π, and by Lemma 4.5, L is almost distributive, so that L =∼ D[d] for some distributive lattice D and d ∈ D. Assume that L is not distributive, so that L contains a sublattice isomorphic to M3 or N5. Since M3 does not satisfy D0π, L contains a pentagon ha,b,c,u,vi. By Lemma 4.8, u = 1 and v = 0. Since L 6= N5, there exists e ∈ L such that e∈{ / a, b, c, 0, 1}. We have a ≮ e, for if a

Proof. By Lemma 4.5, D0π implies almost distributivity. We now prove the sufficiency. Let L be a subdirectly irreducible almost distributive lattice. There exists a distributive lattice D and an element d ∈ D such that L =∼ D[d]. ∼ ∼ Notice that the order-skeleton Le = Dg[d] = De is distributive, by Corollary 3.15, L satisfies D0π. 

In [7], Ern´eintroduced n-zipper-distributivity and the conditions of Hn where n ≥ 3. It turns out that the π-version of n-zipper-distributivity is also equivalent to n-zipper-distributivity. In Figure 3, we present a diagram indi- cating the implications between the various weakened distributive conditions discussed above. We observe that nothing collapses except the five π-versions of distributivity discussed in Corollary 3.15 even if a lattice L is isomorphic to its own order-skeleton. Details can be found in [17].

References

[1] Andr´eka H., Greechie R. J., Strecker G. E.: On residuated approxiations. Categorical Methods in Computer Science With Aspects from , 393, 333-339 (1989) [2] Blyth T. S., Janowitz M. F.: Residuation theory. Pergamon Press, (1972) [3] Day A.: A simple solution to the word problem for lattices. Canadian Mathemtical Bulleton, 13, 253-254 (1970) [4] Davey B. A., Poguntke W., Rival I.: A characterization of semi-distributivity. Algebra Universalis, 5, 72-75 (1975) [5] Davey B. A., Priestley H. A.: Introduction to lattices and order. Cambridge University Press, New York (1980) Vol. 00, XX Distributivity conditions and the order-skeleton of a lattice 17

meet-semi-distributivity

4-zipper-distributivity

semi-distributivity meet-near-distributivity

near-distributivity modularity 3-zipper-distributivity almost-distributivity

D0π H3

π-median law

π-meet-distributivity π-join-distributivity H4

π-distributivity

distributivity

Figure 3. The implications between various weakened dis- tributive conditions.

[6] Davey B. A., Rival I.: Finite sublattices of three-generated lattices. Journal of Australian Mathematical Society (Series A), 21, 171-178 (1976) [7] Ern´eM.: Weak distributive laws and their role in lattices of congruences and equational theories. Algebra Univeralis, 25, 290-321 (1980) [8] Feng W.: On calculating residuated approximations and the structure of finite lattices of small width. PhD dissertation, Louisiana Tech University (2010) [9] Feng W., Su J., Greechie R. J.: On calculating residuated approximations (submitted to Algebra Universalis) [10] Greechie R. J., Janowitz M. F.: Personal Communication. [11] J´onsson B., Rival I.: Lattice varieties covering the smallest non-modular variety. Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 82, 463-478 (1979) [12] Jipsen P., Rose H.: Varieties of lattices. Springer Verlag, (1992) [13] Lee J. G.: Almost distributive lattice varieties. Algebra Univeralis, 21, 280-304 (1985) [14] McKenzie R.: Equational bases and nonmodular lattice varieties. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, 174, 1-43 (1972) [15] Rose H.: Nonmodular lattice varieties. Memoirs of American Mathematical Society, 292 (1984) [16] Schr¨oder B. S. W.: Ordered sets: an introduction, Birkh¨auser (2002) [17] Su J.: Results in lattices, ortholattices, and graphs. PhD dissertation, Louisiana Tech University (2011)

Jianning Su Program of Mathematics and Statistics, Louisiana Tech University, Ruston 71272, USA e-mail: [email protected]

Wu Feng 18 J.Su,W.Feng,andR.J.Greechie Algebra univers.

The Center for Secure Cyberspace, Louisiana Tech University, Ruston 71272, USA e-mail: [email protected]

Richard J. Greechie Program of Mathematics and Statistics, Louisiana Tech University, Ruston 71272, USA e-mail: [email protected] URL: http://www2.latech.edu/∼greechie/